Commentary
The Myth of the Libertarian Constitution

The original Constitution, as designed by the framers in Philadelphia, has often been seen as guaranteeing individual freedom from government repression. Many of Donald Trump’s critics see him as undermining our nation’s foundational constitutional principles, and people and groups from Joe Biden to Black Lives Matter are often seen as trying to restore them. But is this accurate? In fact, the main purpose of the original Constitution was to expand federal power. The Bill of Rights was in essence a tack-on granting some very important rights while also failing to fully reign in the authoritarian tendencies of the 1787 Constitution.

In order to understand the original purpose of the Constitution, one must consider its historical context. The Constitution’s predecessor, the Articles of Confederation, did not prevent state governments from violating individual freedom but left the central government very weak, prohibiting it from, for example, collecting taxes without approval from the states. The Constitution was designed to change this. Getting the government “off the backs of people,” as William O. Douglas once put it, was not a major goal. In fact, the original Constitution expanded federal involvement in enforcing American slavery. Article 4, Section 2, Clause 3 required the return of slaves who escaped from states where slavery was legal to states where it was banned. The “Fugitive Slave Clause,” crowed James Madison, “was expressly inserted to enable owners of slaves to reclaim them. This is a better security than any that now exists.”

Faced with a document expanding federal power, many Americans called for a bill of rights to be included. After all, even England had a bill of rights. So, in exchange for enough states ratifying the Constitution, a bill of rights was promised. While many important protections for civil liberties were included, many others were conspicuous by their absence. Slavery was still given active federal support. It would be misleading to say the federal government just tolerated slavery. Rather, the federal government promoted slavery, used its police power to hunt down runaway slaves, and worked to prevent Northerners from offering them aid or refuge. There was no explicit right of self-ownership, allowing presidents starting with George Washington to sanction military conscription. State governments were free to restrict voting based on race, sex, and class. This made a mockery of the idea of government by consent of the governed. Rather than establishing that property can only be seized by the State in cases of extreme national emergency, the Fifth Amendment’s “Takings Clause” established that private property could “be taken for public use” as long as “just compensation” was provided. In practice, the vagueness of both “public use” and “just compensation” allowed the government to assume the role of the Sheriff of Nottingham while presenting itself as Robin Hood. Many Americans still hold out hope that the policy of eminent domain protected under the Fifth Amendment allows the State to aid the common good by taking land to build hospitals, schools, and homeless shelters. In reality, it allows government officials to seize property from working and middle-class people and redistribute it to themselves and their wealthy constituents. Worse, it allows them to do this without proving that there is any overwhelming necessity to redistribute the property upward or providing the injured parties with enough compensation to possibly offset the hardship. Our soon-to-be lame duck president is only one of the more inglorious examples of rich people exploiting the vague, statist nature of the Takings Clause to try to have the government seize property from the less wealthy on their behalf.

The right to bodily autonomy, i.e. keeping government “out of the bedroom,” was also not addressed, leaving state laws against homosexuality intact until much later. More broadly speaking, there was no explicit prohibition on government restricting any category of civil rights based on race, sex, gender, and other immutable traits. Language such as “Congress shall make no law” indicated that the Bill of Rights only restrained the federal government and not state governments. This interpretation was common prior to the passage of the Fourteenth Amendment about eighty years later, and some on the Right still cling to it today.

It is no surprise that eliminating legal slavery, official denials of equal rights for women and racial minorities by government, and restrictions on the right to vote overall required seven new amendments. Nor is it any surprise that many of the Supreme Court’s most important decisions regarding equal rights, such as Brown v. Board of Education, Loving v. Virginia, Lawrence v. Texas, and Obergefell v. Hodges were based on the Fourteenth Amendment, not the Bill of Rights. And some of the most important cases dealing with the Bill of Rights, such as West Virginia Board of Education v. Barnette, Texas v. Johnson, Tinker v. Des Moines, and City of Indianapolis v. Edmond, would have been more difficult without the Fourteenth Amendment banning state governments from violating the Bill of Rights.

I may be accused of holding the original Constitution to a modern standard. But we can find examples of legal codes from the late 1700s and early 1800s which were more libertarian on some of these issues. Vermont passed antislavery legislation in 1777 and allowed black men to vote without government interference. Haiti banned slavery after its own revolution in 1804. France also legalized homosexuality in 1791, and Haiti made no attempt to ban it after gaining independence. In addition, many Native American societies were more libertarian on issues of women’s rights, slavery, homosexuality, and gender nonconformity than America under the original Constitution. It is no surprise that abolitionists such as William Nell, Wendell Phillips and William Lloyd Garrison regarded the framers’ Constitution as a barrier to personal freedom. And it is no surprise that Roy Moore, who wishes for a government combining 1860 Richmond with 2020 Riyadh, wishes to revert to the original Constitution.

Books and Reviews
Board Game Review: Bloc by Bloc

For better or worse, board games tend to be a popular form of entertainment in radical spaces, and yet there are precious few games that explicitly deal with anarchist ideas. For those exhausted by games glorifying nationalistic conquest, monopoly capitalism, and settler colonialism, Bloc by Bloc: The Insurrection Game may offer a breath of refreshing (if tear-gas-scented) air. According to the introduction in the manual, Bloc by Bloc is “a semi-cooperative game simulating protest movements, riots and popular uprisings in urban areas of the world during the first decades of the 21st century.” The name refers to the black bloc, a tactic used to anonymize and thereby protect participants in these uprisings, and in the game refers to the literal wooden blocks that represent such participants.

Released by Out of Order Games in 2018, the latest edition of Bloc by Bloc features randomized map generation, area control strategy, and hidden agendas, where each player is a faction of revolutionaries fighting against the police in an attempt to liberate their city. Each of the various factions (workers, neighbors, prisoners, and students) has a special ability giving them an advantage in their struggle against the state. For example, the students can more easily and freely move about the city, whereas the neighbors are better at building barricades to slow down the movement of the police.

Bloc by Bloc is a game for 2 to 4 players and it typically takes 2 to 3 hours to play. Players new to strategy board games might find the learning curve a little steep, but the instruction manual is clearly worded and includes reference cards that remind players of their available actions. Experienced board gamers will probably find many of the mechanics familiar. Board game comparison site boardvsgame.com gives it a complexity rating of 2.7 out of 5; compare this to the 2.3 / 5 of the classic competitive mainstay Settlers of Catan or the 2.4 / 5 of the popular cooperative game Pandemic.

While it can be played in fully cooperative mode, the game’s unique semi-cooperative mode is the recommended way to play, and in this Final Straw Radio interview, the game’s designer TL explains why. In contrast to fully cooperative games, where all players are on the same team and playing against the game’s “cardboard AI,” the players in Bloc by Bloc might all be on the same team — but they also might not. In fully co-op games, there is a tendency for everyone to follow the lead of the most experienced player, at its worst becoming a de-facto game of solitaire with less experienced players acting as mere extensions of the most experienced. This dynamic (while perhaps a rational strategy, the players want to win after all), isn’t necessarily encouraging of the critical thinking and anti-hierarchical mindset that anarchists seek to cultivate. But by introducing uncertainty about other players’ agendas, Bloc by Bloc instead forces each player to autonomously evaluate any particular move on its own strategic merit. 

Each player is randomly assigned a hidden agenda card at the beginning of the game: either a social agenda (which wins along with all other social players), or one of two different anti-social agendas, (nihilist or vanguardist, which can only win alone). This hidden agenda mechanic not only makes the game more fun by centering each individual player’s agency, it also arguably makes it more realistic. In real life, we can’t always necessarily judge others’ intentions with perfect accuracy, and the possible infiltration and coopting of social movements by those seeking to derail the movement or attain personal power are unfortunately all-too-real phenomena.

The gameplay is based on four tactics widely adopted by modern insurrections: occupying, looting, barricading, and clashing with the police.

Occupying physical space and turning it towards radical ends is perhaps the tactic most central to liberation. It exemplifies “building a new world in the shell of the old” and the prefiguration of our aspirations. Whether this manifests as workers seizing the means of production by taking over their workplace, or neighbors organizing a rent strike to take back their homes from landlords, these occupations can directly address people’s unmet needs and serve as hubs from which other radical actions can be organized and carried out. Bloc by Bloc gives a nod to this importance by making at least some occupying a necessary victory condition of every agenda, as well as occupations being able to form new blocs and produce useful items (“loot” in the game’s terminology).

Looting, or popular expropriation, is an important aspect of liberation insofar as it consists of systematically exploited and marginalized people taking back those resources that have been stolen from them and enclosed by the capitalist state. Whether these stolen resources are the product of land and water previously held in common, or the surplus value extracted by depriving laborers of their full product, looting can be a means of restoring property to its rightful owners. This bottom-up form of redistribution directly addresses people’s unmet needs to the extent that it gives them access to goods, like groceries or tools, that they may not be able to otherwise afford. But it can also be a way of striking a blow against those institutions that are complicit in their oppression and, by shattering the invulnerability of the status quo, it can inspire resistance in others. In Bloc by Bloc, players can loot shopping centers to acquire items that help make other actions easier or more effective, and may even be required to burn these sites of exploitation to the ground as part of their victory conditions.

One assumption that the game implicitly makes, but that more market-friendly anarchists may not share, is that “commercial districts” are unavoidably exploitative and therefore cannot be occupied or liberated, leaving them only as places that must be looted and/or burned. There is of course much to oppose in our existing capitalist hellscape of strip malls, commercial zoning laws, and suburban sprawl. But aside from perhaps reasons of game mechanics, it’s not clear why prison buildings, for example, are not so structurally and architecturally oppressive that they can’t be occupied and turned to liberatory ends, whereas grocery stores apparently are.

Barricading consists of blocking or slowing movement and redirecting flows through space. In order to defend ourselves and our communities we must sometimes structure our spaces in ways that work to physically exclude cops and other clearly malicious actors. These barriers must be selectively permeable in the sense of actively preventing the passage of those seeking to cause harm while still enabling the passage of friendly actors. In Bloc by Bloc, barricades are placed between districts and stop police from entering, whereas blocs can move through them freely.

Finally, directly and physically confronting state agents is an unavoidable element of insurrections. De-arrests, shield walls, and kicking back the tear gas canisters that the cops shoot at protestors are examples of such confrontation. In Bloc by Bloc, players clash with the police to defend occupations and strategic areas, and successful clashes send police back to the staging area, keeping police morale low and slowing the countdown to the arrival of the military that will quash the uprising if players fail.

This way of losing the game by running out of time has been more common in my experience compared to being completely wiped out by the police. The police often take unstrategic actions, but if players don’t focus on keeping the police morale low, the cops can still overrun the city and prevent the players from accomplishing their objectives. The police are controlled by random dice rolls and cards drawn from the police ops deck, which is arguably a fair simulation of the knowledge problems inherent to their hierarchical organization in the face of illegible and dynamic insurrectionary forces. The game’s difficulty can be adjusted by adding or removing reinforcement cards from the police ops deck, but it’s balanced and random enough that losing on “easy” and winning on “hard” are both real possibilities. A combination of good strategy and good luck is required in order to win.

What such a victory might look like after the insurrection succeeds is left to the imagination. One might imagine the uprising spreads to other cities, regions, or the world, overturning privilege and abolishing power structures throughout society at large. Or maybe authorities just retreat and give the movement some concessions. If the insurrection fails however, according to the manual, “all factions lose and years of repression follow.” The stakes are high.

The physical components of the game are sturdy and the cute grungy cartoon art style is aesthetically attractive. The board is made up of thick cards that are shuffled and arranged randomly to generate a brand new city every time. These cards are laid out on a cloth grid, itself actually a stylized black bandana, (just in case players need to use it to bloc up irl).

All in all, Bloc by Bloc is a creative exploration of insurrectionary anarchist ideas as well as a challenging and fun game in its own right. It might prompt interesting questions, like “why are the police our enemy?” and “how is looting and burning justified?” but it doesn’t in and of itself provide compelling answers. It could maybe serve as supplementary material for a playful propagandist willing to thoughtfully and carefully address the questions it prompts, but don’t expect to convert someone to anarchism just by handing them a copy. As of this writing, the game is currently sold out on the Out of Order Games website, but fortunately, they’ve made everything you need to play freely available as print and play files.

Italian, Stateless Embassies
Contro la Giustizia Penale, I: Niente Pena Mai

Di Jason Lee Byas. Pubblicato il 16 novembre 2020 con il titolo Against the Criminal Justice System, Pt. I: No One Should Ever Be Punished. Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.

Pubblicato originariamente sul blog Students for Liberty il 25 agosto 2015.

Mentre dolore, sofferenza, costi della giustizia penale statunitense vanno alle stelle, crescono le richieste di riforma. Perfino il governatore del Texas, Rick Perry, che un tempo dichiarava di non avere remoreper questioni come la pena di morte, comincia ad appoggiare la riduzione delle carceri.

Quello che servirebbe, però, oggi più che mai, è qualcosa di più profondo di una semplice riforma della giustizia penale: serve l’abolizione. Occorre abolire il sistema penale, compreso quel sistema schiavistico chiamato “carcere”, e fondare un sistema basato sulla difesa e il risarcimento.

Ognuno di questi argomenti – abolizione del sistema penale, sostituzione con un puro sistema della responsabilità civile basato sul risarcimento e la difesa, abolizione delle carceri – richiede un esame attento. Questo articolo è il primo di una serie. Cominceremo spiegando perché un libertario dovrebbe opporsi alla pena[1].

Il libertarismo[2] parte distinguendo tra uso accettabile e uso non accettabile della violenza sulla base della semplice intuizione. In situazioni normali, pensiamo che la violenza sia giustificata solo come autodifesa, e che anche questa debba essere limitata da considerazioni di proporzionalità. Se io voglio ucciderti, e puoi fermarmi solo uccidendomi, sei giustificato. Se ti do noia puoi mandarmi via, ma non uccidermi, neanche darmi un pugno. Se ho rubato il tuo televisore, puoi riprendertelo con la forza, perché tenendo il tuo televisore commetto un atto di aggressione continuata.

Ora, quest’atto di non aggressione è in conflitto totale con l’atto del punire. Mentre la difesa e il risarcimento – esigere una compensazione da parte dell’aggressore per risarcire il risarcibile alla vittima – sono giustificati dalla necessità di porre fine alla violazione dei diritti, così non è nel caso del sistema punitivo. La punizione va oltre la difesa e il risarcimento[3], infligge all’aggressore una pena che non ha nulla a che vedere con la necessità di fermare un atto di aggressione. La pena diventa così essa stessa un’aggressione. Nell’ottica libertaria, giustificare la pena non può che significare giustificare la violenza.

Deterrenza e riabilitazione

Spesso la punizione, o pena, è giustificata come dissuasione. Che può essere generale, ovvero la punizione dei criminali al fine di dissuadere altri dal fare lo stesso; oppure specifica, ovvero si punisce un particolare criminale al fine di dissuaderlo dal commettere un altro crimine.

Forse un libertario pro-pena potrebbe appellarsi alla necessità della dissuasione. Dopotutto, se la difesa giustifica legittimamente la violenza, e la dissuasione protegge da future aggressioni, allora un libertario può legittimare la violenza sulla base della necessità di dissuadere.

Ampliando il concetto di difesa alla dissuasione si arriva a conclusioni assurde. Se la dissuasione giustifica la violenza, allora giustifica anche la punizione di innocenti.

Nel caso della dissuasione generale, basta che una persona sia considerata colpevole, non che abbia veramente commesso un crimine. Perché se una persona è innocente di fatto, ma è ritenuta colpevole, con la sua punizione si avrebbe comunque un effetto di dissuasione generale. Se non accettiamo questa punizione, dobbiamo dire che la dissuasione sociale non giustifica di per sé la violenza.

Se si tratta di dissuadere, basta che la punizione dissuada qualcuno dal commettere un crimine in futuro, che abbia realmente commesso un crimine non importa. Immaginiamo un mondo in cui la dissuasione vada un po’ oltre: se si pensa che una persona sia “sulla cattiva strada”, pur non avendo commesso alcun crimine, viene tenuta in galera per qualche mese (giusto per dargli una lezione). Se la dissuasione specifica legittimasse la violenza, allora questa pratica sarebbe perfettamente legittima.

La stessa critica potrebbe essere fatta contro la punizione a fini riabilitativi. Se è legittimo mettere un criminale in carcere per riabilitarlo, perché non fare lo stesso prendendo a caso dalla strada[4] quelle persone che potrebbero in futuro commettere un crimine?

La giustizia retributiva

Altro problema è che la dissuasione e la riabilitazione non offrono le basi della proporzionalità. Cioè non spiegano perché la pena debba “essere adeguata al crimine”, qualunque cosa s’intenda con ciò. Per questo, molti sostenitori della pratica punitiva optano per la compensazione. Credono che chi ha commesso un crimine meriti di subire un crimine uguale, così da riportare in equilibrio la bilancia della giustizia. Un grosso pregio è che i criteri della proporzionalità qui sono molto chiari e precisi: occhio per occhio. Allora è bene spiegare l’ingiustizia dell’eccesso di pena.

Analizzando il concetto di proporzionalità insito nella giustizia retributiva, vediamo che le conclusioni non sono migliori di quelle a cui ci hanno condotto la dissuasione e la riabilitazione. La giustizia retributiva, ad esempio, dice che non solo è lecito, ma anzi è doveroso uccidere violentemente un assassino violento, e così lo stupratore dovrebbe essere stuprato a sua volta, e gli aggressori aggrediti. Secondo il principio della giustizia retributiva, davanti a certe esecuzioni barbare che procurano una morte atroce non dovremmo provare orrore, ma soddisfazione per l’effettivo ristabilimento della giustizia.

Tornando all’ottica libertaria, è chiaro che la proporzionalità offerta dalla giustizia retributiva non è esattamente quella proporzionalità che andiamo cercando. In un caso tipico di conflitto interpersonale, consideriamo legittima la violenza soltanto finché è necessaria a proteggere noi stessi o altri da un’aggressione. Se cerco di darti un pugno, tu puoi fermare la mia mano, bloccare le mie braccia, o fare qualunque altra cosa al fine di difenderti dal mio pugno. Quello che non puoi fare, secondo noi, è darmi un pugno alle spalle dopo che ti ho dato un pugno e sto andando via. Ci sono casi in cui una reazione del genere appare comprensibile, ma non è moralmente permessa, meno che mai è permesso quel genere di cose che scaturiscono direttamente da una richiesta di giustizia. In fatto di violenza interpersonale siamo chiaramente contro la giustizia retributiva.

Non farla franca

Allora eliminare la pena significa non far nulla davanti ad un’aggressione? No, significa solo non rispondere con la pena. Il criminale dovrebbe essere costretto a rifondere la vittima, così da recuperare il recuperabile. Questo degrada di fatto il diritto penale a diritto civile. Nel prossimo articolo analizzeremo il significato di questa rivoluzione.


Note

[1] Con “punizione” o “pena” intendo l’uso istituzionale della violenza vendicativa contro un criminale, in risposta ad un suo crimine ma non in difesa da una sua particolare aggressione, né mirata a rifondere il danno alla vittima. Ovviamente, sulla pena si propongono e si sostengono tante teorie, e qui lo spazio è limitato. Io mi limito ad esaminare quelle ragioni per cui la pena, in particolare nell’ottica libertaria, è considerata illegittima. A chi volesse approfondire le tante altre ragioni addotte dai filosofi del diritto raccomando la lettura di The Problem of Punishment di David Boonin. Un attacco contro la pena, meno elaborato ma ugualmente persuasivo, si trova in The Structure of Liberty: Justice & the Rule of Law di Randy Barnett, e Anarchy & Legal Order: Law and Politics for a Stateless Society di Gary Chartier.

[2] Non tutto quello che scrivo qui ovviamente si applica alle convinzioni di tutti i libertari. A scanso di malintesi, non sto dicendo che un libertario che non basa la propria fede sul principio della non aggressione non è libertario. Sto solo prendendo i libertari fedeli al principio di non aggressione come esempio paradigmatico.

[3] Da notare che “difesa e risarcimento” sono in realtà piuttosto ridondanti. Il risarcimento è giustificato dal fatto che l’aggressore, avendo privato la vittima di qualcosa di suo (il denaro), si trova ad essere in debito con questa.

[4] Questo è ciò che accade, in una certa misura, con il trattamento sanitario obbligatorio. Ma la riabilitazione, intesa come giustificazione della pena, portata alle sue logiche conclusioni porterebbe ad un’applicazione pratica molto, molto più ampia di quanto non accada ora.

Portuguese, Stateless Embassies
Contra o Sistema Penal, Parte II: O Direito Criminal É Um Crime

Jason Lee Byas. Título original: Against the Criminal Justice System, Pt. II: The Criminality of Criminal Law. Traduzido para o português por Gabriel Serpa.

Na primeira parte desta série, apresentei razões para os libertários rejeitarem as práticas punitivistas. Como alternativa, sugeri que o papel adequado do Direito é a busca pela resolução de conflitos, e que a violência advinda dele só pode ser direcionada à defesa do ofendido ou para restitui-lo. Com efeito, elimina-se assim o direito penal, deixando em seu lugar o direito civil.

Na sequência, tentarei dar mais estofo a essa conclusão, demonstrando brevemente por quais motivos os libertários devem se opor à lei penal, para além da ilegitimidade das punições.

Visões Jurídicas: Centradas Na Vítima x Centradas Na Soberania

​​Os libertários gastam muito tempo (acertadamente) discutindo a injustiça em torno de crimes sem vítimas. Mesmo assim, se aceitarmos a ideia da lei penal, não fica claro por quê — já que pelo seu enquadramento, crimes não diriam respeito às verdadeiras vítimas para começo de conversa.

Em vez disso, quando uma pessoa comete um homicídio, a lei penal nos diz que o verdadeiro crime foi cometido contra a sociedade. É por isso que existem promotores de justiça, os quais podem levar adiante denúncias — mesmo que contra a vontade da vítima em questão—, e a essas denúncias dá-se nomes como “O Povo do Estado da Califórnia em face de José das Couves”, e não simplesmente “José das Couves em face de João Ninguém”.

Historicamente, essa ideia advém dos tempos em que todos os crimes eram interpretados como ataques diretos ao rei, e as punições eram penas imputadas a criminosos por desafiarem a autoridade do monarca. Como nos explica o filósofo Gary Chartier:

A categoria legal dos crimes contemporâneos se encontra no âmbito daquilo que comumente é enquadrado como ataque ao “público” … ou ao “estado”. Em um sistema supostamente democrático, o estado será identificado — retórica e erroneamente — como o todo da população. Mas é claro que categorizar o estado como a vítima de crimes se popularizou nos tempos da monarquia — com a identificação do estado como soberania popular.

O crime era compreendido como um ato que atentava contra o rei por inúmeros motivos: por violar a legislação real e contestar sua autoridade; pelo medo que o monarca tinha dos efeitos colaterais advindos de violações legais; pelos crimes demandarem o uso das cortes judiciais do rei; e pelo fato dos atos criminosos potencialmente diminuírem a arrecadação de tributos. Além disso, algumas transgressões só existiam dada a existência do próprio monarca: insultos ao rei, ataques à igreja do reino, certamente as tentativas de deposição — [a criação de] uma categoria à parte foi necessária para estas, em parte por serem inconcebíveis sem a presença de um rei (e não estariam presentes em um sistema voltado para a resolução de conflitos entre partes juridicamente iguais), e em parte porque havia todos os incentivos para que o monarca ratificasse a sua importância.

Em outras palavras, desde seu início, a lei penal esteve atrelada a uma noção abertamente autoritária de soberania. Para os libertários, que entendem que a soberania não subjaz a um monarca ou a um povo, mas ao indivíduo de carne e osso, isto faz do direito penal algo inadmissível.

Mens Rea É Crime De Pensamento

Uma das consequências deste formato do direito penal centrado em soberania é que ele se preocupa não apenas com o actus reus (o ato culposo), mas também com a mens rea (a mente [ou intenção] culposa). O criminoso deve ser responsabilizado e moralmente culpado. Assim, as punições também variam de acordo com o quão moralmente culpados eles são — pune-se mais o assassino que planejou meticulosamente seus atos do que aquele que o faz em um rompante de ira.

Isso pode parecer inquestionável até que percebamos o que realmente significa: sob o direito penal, todo crime envolve o crime de pensamento.

Para que uma conduta passe de mera contravenção a um crime — e para que a resposta a ela passe da restituição à punição — é preciso que haja o instituto de mens rea. E para justificar um maior uso de violência [na punição], os defensores do direito penal precisam sustentar que ideias transgressoras são, por si só, uma justificativa à parte para se valerem desta mesma violência. Do contrário, ir da restituição para a punição não está dentro do princípio da proporcionalidade.

É difícil imaginar um conceito mais repugnante para libertários do que crime de pensamento, o que nos dá razões suficientes para que deixemos de lado qualquer apego que tenhamos e dispensemos o direito penal.

O Direito Penal É Dado A Violações De Direitos

Para além destas duas características inerentemente iliberais — o foco (equivocado) em soberania e a mens rea —, há mais um motivo para que libertários tenham um pé atrás com o direito penal. Notadamente, ele abre mais espaço para o autoritarismo no campo do Direito.

Como mencionado antes, a lei penal, em sua essência, não está preocupada com a vítima, mas com danos abstratos causados, de forma muito genérica, à sociedade. Torna-se muito fácil advogar pela penalização de erros morais, pela prevenção paternalista de doenças sociais, ou o que quer possa ser visto e atacado como um perigo iminente para a sociedade como um todo.

Historicamente, isso se demonstra com o direito penal sendo imposto pelos estados às sociedades, em vez de se desenvolver espontaneamente de instituições livres e voluntariamente constituídas. Já aqueles sistemas legais que foram mais libertários em seus formatos — menos voltados ao estado e mais descentralizados — sempre tenderam mais ao direito civil e ao sistema de restituição do que ao direito penal e ao punitivismo. É o caso da Islândia medieval, da Irlanda e Inglaterra pré-conquistas e do sistema jurídico policêntrico da Somália (chamado Xeer).

Sob tais sistemas, o Direito não é imposto por meio de legislação, mas emerge naturalmente de decisões reais, envolvendo pessoas e conflitos de verdade. Por isso, prescindem de um código penal à parte, concentrando-se em indenizar o que pode ser indenizado às vítimas, e não em agredir o agressor.

Conferindo Uma Função Específica Ao Direito

Uma grande vantagem de mudar para um sistema baseado na restituição e no direito civil é que ele edifica uma função bem determinada para o Direito. Sob estes moldes, ele não se dedica a solucionar problemas sociais (nem mesmo o crime!), tampouco faz prescrições morais em nome de uma coletividade. Ele, especificamente, apazigua disputas entre particulares e indeniza vítimas em conflitos.

Em parte, isso resulta em implicações libertárias mais profundas e abrangentes do que a princípio pode parecer, politicamente falando. Um texto futuro desta série dedicar-se-á à exposição de tais implicações. Entretanto, no próximo, responderemos a algumas críticas que frequentemente são feitas às teorias jurídicas puramente voltadas à restituição.

Green Market Agorist, Podcast, Stigmergy - C4SS Blog
Green Market Agorist Episode 9: C4SS Holiday Special (feat. Alex McHugh)

In case you haven’t already heard, I have been hosting the Green Market Agorist podcast and YouTube/Bitchute channel in addition to my writings here at C4SS. My solo video output is sporadic at best but I keep a steady schedule with podcasts being released on the 15th of every month.

This month I was joined by our new C4SS coordinating director, Alex McHugh, to talk about his new role and plans for the Center moving forward, as well as fun stuff like egoism, mysticism, and religion. Previous episodes explore topics such as systematic racism, community defense, electoral politics, and more through a series of interviews with anarchists and other radicals who have inspired myself and other community organizers that I work with.

It is my joy to share these interviews and hope you enjoy listening to them. You can listen to the Green Market Agorist podcast on Anchor or Spotify and be sure to check out my YouTube and Bitchute channels while you’re at it. If you wish to support this project further and allow me more time and material resources to focus on it, you can do so by subscribing to the Green Market Agorist Patreon or SubscribeStar or by making a one time donation via PayPal or CoinPayments.

Stigmergy - C4SS Blog
How Roderick Long Helped You; How You Can Help Roderick Long

Philosopher, writer, C4SS Senior Fellow, and longtime anarchist theorist Roderick T. Long is facing steep medical costs and needs our help paying his bills.

I’ve known Roderick Long for the better part of a decade and few people have had a bigger impact on my life. Roderick is my biggest intellectual inspiration. Not just because he’s usually right but because he’s overflowing with intellectual charity, curiosity, rigor, nuance, clarity, and wit. He’s never dismissive, hostile, or cryptic. I aspire to cultivate his discursive virtue. His writing also has something of a revelatory feel to it. Not in the shallow way that conspiracy theorists usually aim for, but in the rich way that people who think sincerely and deeply about many interrelated issues aim for.

His book Wittgenstein, Austrian Economics, and the Logic of Action: Praxeological Investigations contains some of the most important contributions to metaphysics, philosophy of (social) science, and economic theory in recent memory.

His book Rituals of Freedom: Austro-Libertarian Themes in Early Confucianism is a fascinating exploration into Ancient Chinese ideas and builds thought-provoking bridges between Eastern and Western philosophy.

His monograph Reason and Value: Aristotle versus Rand offers profound insights into epistemology, ethics, and the relationship between the two.

His 10-part lecture series Foundations of Libertarian Ethics provides deeply compelling, yet nuanced, solutions to vital issues surrounding human flourishing, morality, and social order.

He’s written dozens of essays thoughtfully exploring complex topics in philosophy, politics, and economics:

Libertarian Anarchism: Responses to Ten Objections
Liberty: The Other Equality
Corporations versus the Market
Libertarian Feminism: Can This Marriage Be Saved?
Why Does Justice Have Good Consequences?
Economics and its Ethical Assumptions
A Plea For Public Property
Market Anarchism as Constitutionalism

He’s also launched his own series of video essays and interviews this year called the Agoric Cafe.

Roderick has spent much of his life thinking very hard about the most fundamental issues of the human condition: the nature of reality and knowledge; action and cooperation; social institutions and freedom.

His work will be making an impact on the world for a long time to come.

And (perhaps more importantly) so will his always-sincere, yet-never-too-serious, attitude toward that work.

After years teaching philosophy in Auburn, taking care of his mother, and promoting the ideas of left-market anarchism whenever he had the chance, Roderick Long is now facing serious financial struggles due to medical expenses (for both his mother and himself) and the high-interest loans he took out to pay them.

Roderick has been a teacher, mentor, and friend to so, so many.

Now, we pay him back.

Donate Here

Stigmergy - C4SS Blog
Agoric Cafe: Interview With Sheldon Richman (Part 2)

In episode no. 14 of Agoric Cafe and in Part 2 of this 2-part interview, Roderick Long chats with Sheldon Richman about the Israeli occupation of Palestine; u.s. intervention in the Middle East; the meaning of Jewish identity; the relation between libertarian individualism and social cooperation; the communistic theories of Frédéric Bastiat; the theologico-political merits of Spinoza; Nathaniel Branden and George H. Smith on atheism; Thomas Paine and Lysander Spooner on deism; the philosophical failings of the New Atheists; rehabilitating the cost-of-production theory of value; the uses of coherentist epistemology for both theists and atheists; reading Wittgenstein for relaxation; the advantages and disadvantages of Randian approaches to knowledge and concepts; the sordid truth behind the special effects in Roderick’s videos (and in particular, what the deal is with Roderick’s hair); Sheldon’s case against open Borders; and the shocking misuse of libertarian think tank resources to photocopy body parts (but who did it, Sheldon or Roderick? and which body parts? watch and learn!). Watch here or below.

Mutual Exchange Radio, Podcast
Mutual Exchange Radio: Aurora Apolito and William Gillis, Part II

This episode is Part II of a two-part interview with Aurora Apolito and William Gillis, two of the lead contributors to our summer symposium on Decentralization and Economic Coordination. Listen to Part I here, or on Spotify, iTunes, and Stitcher.

Aurora Apolito is a mathematician and theoretical physicist. She studied physics in Italy and mathematics in Chicago, and later worked for various scientific institutions in the US, Canada, and Germany. She also works on mathematical linguistics, and on mathematical models for neuroscience and has authored six books on various aspects of this work. I should also note that Aurora Apolito is a pen name meant to differentiate this research from her work in other fields.

Our other guest is someone most listeners will be familiar with, William Gillis. Will currently acts as technology coordinator at C4SS and was formerly our coordinating director. Will is a second-generation anarchist who’s worked as an activist in countless projects and capacities since getting involved in the lead-up to N30 (also known as the “Battle in Seattle”). Gillis studies high energy physics and has held a deep fascination with the egalitarian potential of markets since 2003. Their writing can be found at C4SS.org and humaniterations.net.

Here are both Will & Aurora’s essays in the summer Symposium:

Studies
Hayek’s Fatal Conceit

Traducción al español: La fatal arrogancia de Hayek

View or download a PDF copy of Kevin Carson’s C4SS Study: Hayek’s Fatal Conceit

Oskar Lange famously said, against the background of the debates over Ludwig von Mises’ economic calculation argument, that a statue of Mises should be erected in the planning ministry of a future socialist society, in honor of the service he performed to socialism in forcing socialist theoreticians to grapple with the challenge his argument presented. But if any capitalist ideologue — Austrian or not — deserves to be honored for his services to socialism, it’s Friedrich Hayek. (That’s not to say he shouldn’t also be burned in effigy, in every college history department in the world, for his crimes against historiography.)

Capitalism and the Historians.  In his introductory essay to Capitalism and the Historians, Hayek observes: “…[T]he historical beliefs which guide us in the present are not always in accord with the facts; sometimes they are even the effects rather than the cause of political beliefs. Historical myths have perhaps played nearly as great a role in shaping opinion as historical facts.”1 And shortly after:

…[M]ost of the assertions to which [socialist history] has given the status of “facts which everybody knows” have long been proved not to have been facts at all; yet they still continue, outside the circle of professional economic historians, to he almost universally accepted as the basis for the estimate of the existing economic order.2

But Hayek goes on, here and elsewhere, to demonstrate that he himself is guilty of asserting ahistorical “facts which everybody knows.”

The capitalist legitimizing ideology relies heavily on ahistorical myths:  e.g., the “original accumulation of capital” through thrift and abstention; the “initial appropriation of the land” and origin of modern forms of private property through peaceful homesteading to “remove it from the common”; the cash nexus’s rise to hegemony through a natural human “propensity to truck, barter, and exchange”; and the predominance of specie currency arising as a solution to the problem of “dual coincidence of wants.” 

And Hayek is one of the more egregious — and self-confident — promoters of these just-so stories.

In the ensuing discussion in his introductory essay, Hayek focuses almost entirely on challenging the predominant perception among radicals that the working class standard of living declined in the early industrial revolution. To this he opposes the consensus of economic historians that living standards in fact rose under factory employment, and places strong emphasis on the role of such employment in supporting those who — due to lack of land or income — would otherwise have starved.

In so doing he studiously ignores the question of just how these workers came to be devoid of land and consequently in need of employment. He ignores, likewise the issue of employers’ collusion with the state to reduce the bargaining power of labor and ensure that capital’s share of output relative to labor was artificially large. In other words, he ignores the two most important subject areas of English radical historiography. 

He devotes himself almost entirely to refuting The Condition of the Working Class in England, while ignoring the much more fundamental earlier issues of the enclosures and the imposition of authoritarian social controls on the working class. In this he is like Lincoln’s anecdotal Jesuit who, charged with killing ten men and a dog, triumphantly produced the dog in court.

Although Hayek delves more deeply into actual historical questions in The Fatal Conceit, his approach from the outset is almost totally ahistorical, comprised almost entirely of just-so stories from capitalist ideology that are directly contradicted by actual history.3 He starts by defining capitalism as an “extended order of human cooperation,” and asserting that the order “resulted not from human design or intention but spontaneously….”4

But capitalism, at least as much as any hypothetical socialist order, required centrally directed social engineering for its establishment. It’s ironic that Hayek quotes Henry Sumner Maine, on the indispensability of “several property” to civilization, as the epigraph to Chapter Two.5 In the body of that chapter, Hayek handwaves about the development of several property in land, in the vaguest of terms, as an outgrowth of “cultural and moral evolution” or “slow selection by trial and error.”6 Several property in land, he speculates, developed in some unspecified way by expanding the concept of private possession of moveable goods like tools. He cites the Greeks and Romans, in particular, as having learned through collective social experience about the inseparability of property from freedom.

The first individually crafted durable tools probably became attached to their makers because they were the only ones who had the skill to use them… Separate ownership of perishable goods, on the other hand, may have appeared only later as the solidarity of the group weakened and individuals became responsible for more limited groups such as the family. Probably the need to keep a workable holding intact gradually led from group ownership to individual property in land….

…There will also have developed, especially with regard to land, such arrangements as ‘vertical’ division of property rights between superior and inferior owners, or ultimate owners and lessees, such as are used in modern estate developments, of which more use could perhaps be made today than some more primitive conceptions of property allow.7

We find ourselves, in other words, in the realm of edifying but ahistorical nursery fables, like the “initial appropriation of land” by “withdrawing it from the common” through “admixture of labor.” Capitalist legitimizing ideology relies heavily on promoting the assumption that its dominant institutions arose peacefully and spontaneously, and Hayek’s outgassings here are very much in keeping with that imperative.8

Now, in one sense the Romans learned a great deal about the connection between property and freedom, considering how much of the plebs lost its freedom to debt slavery thanks to the privatization of the ager publicus. But at no point does Hayek reference such actual historical phenomena. Maine, better than almost anybody, could have told him about the real — i.e., collective — nature of property in land in ancient society, and the extent to which violence and robbery were required to establish “private property” as we understand it.

Hayek’s Disneyfication of the origins of capitalism in Europe is even more impressive. The expansion of capitalism in the late middle ages “owes its origins and raison d’etre to political anarchy.” Capitalism expanded 

not under the more powerful governments, but in the towns of the Italian Renaissance, of South Germany and of the Low Countries, and finally in lightly-governed England, i.e., under the rule of the bourgeoisie rather than of warriors, that modern industrialism grew. Protection of several property, not the direction of its use by government, laid the foundations for the growth of the dense network of exchange of services that shaped the extended order.9

Well, except for a few inconvenient details like the fact that the establishment of capitalism involved the suppression of the free towns by the gunpowder armies of the absolute states. Or that the creation of the wage system on which the English Industrial Revolution depended presupposed the expropriation and enclosure of arable land on a nationwide scale. Or that the Industrial Revolution, according to Lewis Mumford, was brought about by a constellation of class forces including the agrarian capitalists who enclosed all that land, the armaments industry, and the mining and coinage industries — all allied with the absolutist political regime. 

Despite all the platitudes Hayek quotes from Locke, Hume, Ferguson et al (e.g. “Where there is no property there is no justice”), he seems remarkably reticent to look into the actual origins of the property of Locke’s Whig patrons — and who they stole it from. 

Especially laughable is framing the adoption of modern “private property” as unconnected with any benefits foreseen by the adopters. Hume wrote, Hayek says,  

that these rules ‘are not derived from any utility or advantage which either the particular person or the public may reap from his enjoyment of any particular good’…. Men did not foresee the benefits of rules before adopting them, though some people gradually have become aware of what they owe to the whole system.10

Hence his strawman dismissal of those who “suspect some secret and dishonest manipulation — some conspiracy, as of a dominant ‘class’ — behind ‘designs’ whose designers are nowhere to be found.”11  

I’m morally certain that the landed gentry and nobles who enclosed the open fields for sheep pasture envisioned themselves as the beneficiaries of that process. And the ruling class literature of the mid- and late-18th century is full of very explicit complaints that, with rights of access to common pasture, wood and fen, and the right of landless peasants to build a cottage on the waste, the laboring classes would not work as hard or as cheaply for wages as capitalist farmers desired; the creation of the modern property regime from the late middle ages on was consciously envisioned, at every step of the way, as a project to increase the extraction of surplus labor. And it was every bit as radical a reordering of society, according to a conscious design, as Hayek attributes to the socialists.

Indeed J.L. and Barbara Hammond argued that Britain, in the revolution from above imposed through Enclosures and the totalitarian social controls instituted for the working class, was “taken to pieces … and reconstructed in the manner in which a dictator reconstructs a free government.”12 And ironically, Soviet theoreticians like Yevgeny Preobrazhensky explicitly compared the “socialist accumulation” of forced collectivization, in which a surplus was to be extracted from the countryside in order to subsidize industrialization, to the primitive accumulation in early industrial Britain.

If the above examples of Hayek’s historical illiteracy are not enough, there’s also this (God help us):  

Capitalism created the possibility of employment. It created the conditions wherein people who have not been endowed by their parents with the tools and land needed to maintain themselves and their offspring could be so equipped by others, to their mutual benefit….

Thus the whole idea that the rich wrested away from the poor what, without such acts of violence would, or at least might, belong to them, is absurd.

The size of the stock of capital of a people, together with its accumulated traditions and practices for extracting and communicating information, determine whether that people can maintain large numbers. People will be employed, and materials and tools produced to serve future needs of unknown persons, only if those who can invest capital to bridge the interval between present outlay and future return will gain an increment from doing this which is at least as great as what they could have obtained from other uses of that capital.

Thus without the rich — without those who accumulated capital — those poor who could exist at all would be very much poorer indeed, scratching a livelihood from marginal lands on which every drought would kill most of the children they would be trying to raise.13

I can’t resist mentioning, in passing, that in addition to Hayek’s sanitized vision of the history of capitalism, he also — like most right-libertarians who take others to task for their alleged ignorance of economics — fails to grasp its present-day functioning:

It evidently has not occurred to them that the capitalists who are suspected of directing it all are actually also tools of an impersonal process, just as unaware of the ultimate effects and purpose of their actions, but merely concerned with a higher level, and therefore a wider range, of events in the whole structure.14

The last I heard, the assortment of artificial scarcities and artificial property rights, state-enforced entry barriers, socialized inputs, and direct subsidies, through which big business extracts the economic rents that constitute the bulk of its profits, were no more the result of an “impersonal process” than were the various acts of Enclosure two hundred years before. And it’s a safe bet that the corporations that lobby for all these measures are quite aware of the purpose of their actions.

He exhibits the same incomprehension when he attributes anti-capitalism to opposition to commerce, reflecting in turn a popular unwillingness

to accept that quantitative increases of available supplies of physical means of subsistence and enjoyment should depend less on the visible transformation of physical substances into other physical substances than on the shifting about of objects which thereby change their relevant magnitudes and values.15

The problem, again, is that this ignores the extent to which capitalist profit depends, rather, on stopping or hindering the “shifting about of objects,” by means of legal monopolies, entry barriers, and artificial scarcities — resentment of which is, therefore, entirely justified.

Likewise this: “Concern for profit is just what makes possible the more effective use of resources.”16 No; under actually-existing capitalism, profit is more likely to result from hindering (or threatening to hinder) the most effective use of resources. This is done by means referred to variously as “capitalized disserviceability” (i.e., the collection of tribute for the “service” of not obstructing production)17 or “monopolizing natural opportunities.”18 

What that means, in practical terms, is this: In marginalist theory, the “marginal productivity” of a factor input is what it contributes to the final value of a good or service — essentially, whatever its owner is able to charge for it. So a landlord can fence in a piece of undeveloped land, or a patent owner can put a legal fence around an idea, and then charge tribute for what they “contribute to production” by allowing others to put it to use. Marxist economist Maurice Dobb used the illustration of government granting, to a specific class of people, the privilege of erecting toll-gates across all the highways in a country and collecting tribute for the favor of not obstructing traffic — the revenue going, not to fund maintenance of the highways, but simply to enrich the gate-owner. In marginalist theory, a gate-owner’s toll would be their reward for the “service” of not obstructing the road, and whatever the tolls added to the price of goods and services would be the “marginal productivity” of raising the bar.19

But in Hayek’s imaginary universe, the most noteworthy monopolies engaged in restricting production or hindering efficiency are “monopolies of organised groups of workers, ‘unions’, which create an artificial scarcity of their kind of work by preventing those willing to do such work for a lower wage from doing so.”20

It’s instructive, in evaluating Hayek’s claims for the spontaneous origin of capitalism, to contemplate what recognizable aspects of the British industrial capitalism of 1750-1850 would be left if we subtracted the late medieval enclosure of open fields, the Parliamentary Enclosure of common pasture and waste, the whipping of vagrants and forcing of “masterless men” into peonage, the Established Church’s suppression of feast days and merriment, the Navigation Wars, the Battle of Plassey and Hastings’ Permanent Settlement, the Poor Laws and Laws of Settlement, the Riot Act, prohibitions on friendly societies and societies of correspondence, the Combination Laws, and mass repression like that at Peterloo. For the ordinary person at the village level, the period of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries which Hayek celebrates as a freeing up of individual energies and intellect was, rather, a massive retreat into repression and authoritarianism compared to the height of the late Middle Ages.21

Equally instructive is to ask a similar question as to what would be left of the American capitalism of Hayek’s day, had it not been for the railroad land grants, the industrial tariff, patent pooling and cartels, the role of government in promoting highways and trucking and creating the civil aviation system virtually from whole cloth, and the use of federal troops and the National Guard for breaking strikes.

It’s doubly ironic that Hayek characterizes socialism as proposing “the abolition of individual ownership of means of production,” placing them under direction by a “central authority.”22

As Marx argued in Grundrisse, capitalism and the wage system came into being by essentially destroying any meaningful individual property rights in the means of production for the overwhelming majority of the population. The property rights of the peasant and the artisan in the pre-capitalist economy amounted to “the relation of the working (producing or self-reproducing) subject to the conditions of his production or reproduction as his own,” as member of a clan or village.23 Far from guaranteeing this property right, capitalism presupposed the nullification and abolition of the only meaningful property claims of the vast majority of the population. For capitalism to come into existence, propertyless laborers with only their labor-power to sell had to confront the owners of the means of production. Laborers had to be “freed” of their relations to the means of production — “free of all property; dependent on the sale of [their] labour capacity… as [their] only source of income.”24 This required robbery. Capitalism was established through the negation of the property rights of the overwhelming majority. 

The ultimate result was to concentrate property in the means of production in the hands of a small number of artificial legal persons known as corporations. The investment resources of society are allocated among these corporations by an even smaller number of banks, with production centrally planned by the corporations’ managerial oligarchies. For the great bulk of the population today, “private property” consists at most of a dwelling space and small surrounding yard — and even among so-called “home-owners,” in most cases the putative owner is a tenant of the bank into old age.

In other words, under capitalism, “individual private property” for most actual individuals is nothing more than a right to work with the means of production owned by someone else, and to spend every living moment in space owned by someone else.

Although Hayek contrasts the “collectivism” of socialism with the “individualism” of capitalism, Marx was correct in arguing that collectivism was in fact created by capitalism itself. Industrial production became a collective phenomenon in which enterprises employing thousands of people were collectively owned by capital, as represented by fictitious collective persons, rather than by any identifiable individuals or partnerships between individuals. The only thing that remained individual was the rentiers who clipped the coupons, and the only thing “private” was the nominally private status of the corporations in capitalist legal theory.

And as Marx also argued, for most of the population socialism would in fact be a return to meaningful individual property rights in the means of production for the first time in their lives. The outcome of the working class expropriating the capitalists is “for labour to relate to its objective conditions as its property again….”25

This is the restoration, on a higher technical level, of the pre-capitalist right of access to the conditions of production and subsistence, by virtue of membership in society.  

Of course, Hayek might point out in response that an individual worker has no meaningful right of ownership in a state factory whose output is determined by a planning ministry in the national capital. And he would be correct to do so — although it would remain equally true that a factory owned by a large capitalist corporation is not private or individual property in any meaningful sense. The point is that the very distinction between “public” and “private” property becomes meaningless when we talk about national governments and oligopoly corporations that are not accountable in any real sense to those affected by them. It is for this reason that I go on to argue for a model of socialism based on social ownership of land, and of the means of production, through distributed, self-managed, human-scale institutions.

Hayek’s presentation of the alleged contrast between the old, negative liberal conception of freedom, and the new, positive one of the socialists, sheds some light here — albeit perhaps inadvertently.

To the great apostles of political freedom the word had meant freedom from coercion, freedom from the arbitrary power of other men, release from the ties which left the individual no choice but obedience to the orders of a superior to whom he was attached. The new freedom promised, however, was to be freedom from necessity, release from the compulsion of the circumstances which inevitably limit the range of choice of all of us, although for some very much more than for others. Before man could be truly free, the “despotism of physical want” had to be broken, the “restraints of the economic system” relaxed.

Freedom in this sense is, of course, merely another name for power or wealth…. What the promise really amounted to was that the great existing disparities in the range of choice of different people were to disappear. The demand for the new freedom was thus only another name for the old demand for an equal distribution of wealth.26

And in a footnote, he remarked on the “characteristic [i.e. of socialism] confusion of freedom with power…”27

But the distinction he makes is to a large extent arbitrary, and reflects unstated assumptions about where power and coercion lie — or do not lie — within the present system. A legal guarantee of access rights to some share of the means of production and subsistence, as in a share in governance and returns of a worker-controlled enterprise, or to rent-free housing in a community land trust, is a return to the usufruct or possessory property and guaranteed rights of access to the means of production (e.g. a guaranteed share of subsistence as a member of a hunter-gatherer band, or to a certain number of furlong strips and pasturage rights as a member of a village) that prevailed within pre-capitalist societies before it was forcibly stamped out by states in league with capital. Hunter-gatherer bands and stateless agrarian villages had solidarity-based economies characterized by usufructory property rights and mutual aid —  along with what Murray Bookchin, borrowing from Paul Radin, called the “irreducible minimum”:  

the shared notion that all members of a community are entitled to the means of life, irrespective of the amount of work they perform. To deny anyone food, shelter, and the basic means of life because of infirmities or even frivolous behavior would have been seen as a heinous denial of the very right to live. Nor were the resources and things needed to sustain the community ever completely privately owned: overriding individualistic control was the broader principle of usufruct-the notion that the means of life that were not being used by one group could be used, as need be, by another.28

And such social models based on usufruct and the irreducible minimum persisted in many places even under class and state rule — for example in Bengal until it was stamped out by Warren Hastings, in East Africa until destroyed by British colonial authorities, and in the Russian Mir until suppressed first by Stolypin and then by Stalin.

Indeed the very distinction between “negative” and “positive” freedom, as it is made by right-libertarians — i.e. that “positive” freedom requires compulsion or invasion of the rights of others — relies on the assumption of a society of atomistic individuals with no communal or social property rights. And that form of society is in fact the product of state violence, which forcibly nullified communal property rights, and suppressed all social institutions that guaranteed an irreducible minimum of support by virtue of one’s membership.

If we reject Hayek’s ahistorical assumption that the distributions of wealth and economic power under the present system are spontaneous outcomes of free interaction and treat them as the forcible usurpations they are, it follows that common access rights and the irreducible minimum constitute negative freedom against the arbitrary authority and coercion of landlord or employer. In this sense freedom is power; the freedom of the British subject in his or her “castle” against arbitrary invasion of the state is directly analogous to freedom from arbitrary eviction or dismissal.

And Hayek’s negative vs. positive framing of the equal distribution of wealth makes sense, similarly, only if we start from his unstated assumption that existing inequalities result from the freedom of the market, rather than from rents on artificial property rights based on past robbery, and that greater equality requires forcible intervention into the natural order of things. On the other hand if we view inequality largely as the fruit of robbery and of ongoing rent extraction, and the existing authority of landlords and employers as a violent imposition, it follows that the restoration of the majority’s rightful property in the means of production, and the abolition of special privilege, will result in an equalization of wealth through greater freedom.

The Road to Serfdom. This was the book that made Hayek’s name, and figured highly among the things that helped kick off the right-libertarian propaganda offensive. Nevertheless, many of his critiques of central planning are useful from a libertarian socialist perspective.

One of the problems with a central planning regime, Hayek argues, is that it tends to remove ever greater areas of policy from legislative oversight and reduces the legislative role to one of rubber-stamping. More specifically, it requires permanent delegation (i.e. virtual alienation) of authority to administrative bodies 

because the matter in hand cannot be regulated by general rules but only by the exercise of discretion in the decision of particular cases. In these instances delegation means that some authority is given power to make with the force of law what to all intents and purposes are arbitrary decisions….29

Perhaps even more alarming, he argues that a planned economy would lead to authoritarianism, because the imperative of protecting the planning state against constant political disruption and reversals with every change of government would lead to restrictions on parliamentary democracy. He cites a rhetorical question raised by Harold Laski as to “whether in a period of transition to Socialism, a Labour Government can risk the overthrow of its measures as a result of the next general election…”30

But the truth is that any economic order requires treating some fundamental rules as foundational, and beyond the reach of ordinary politics.

In fact Hayek’s own “liberal” order of private property and contract requires granting special constitutional status to capitalism’s particular rules of property and contract — which are actually particular arbitrary selections from among many alternative possible sets of such rules — and removing them from the realm of politics. 

The United States Constitution was created in large part to counter the perceived danger of populist coalitions in the state legislatures cancelling debt and redividing land — hence the explicit prohibition on states passing legislation to impair the obligations of contract. And in discussing provisions to guarantee to the states a republican form of government, and authorizing the US military to suspend habeas corpus and put down insurrections, Federalist polemicists referenced the cancellation of debt and redivision of land as the sorts of “wicked projects” that might result in those clauses being invoked.

What’s more, capitalist ruling classes have a long history, in various countries, of resorting to extra-legal violence and political repression when capitalism’s property and contract rules do come under political threat. This has been true in comparatively liberal regimes of the imperial core areas — e.g. the blackshirts in Italy as a response to the post-WWI factory occupations, the American Legion and Ku Klux Klan as a response to postwar radicalism in the United States, McCarthyism and COINTELPRO in the post-WWII period, etc. But it is true even more so of the formerly colonized areas of the Global South, in which the United States and other Western powers have repeatedly intervened via coups, military invasions, and covert support for death squads when the interests of capital were threatened in one area or another.31

The Fatal Conceit. The title of the book refers to “the fatal conceit that man is able to shape the world around him according to his wishes.”32 Its general perspective is indicated by one of its epigraphs — a quote from Carl Menger: “How can it be that institutions that serve the common welfare and are extremely significant for its development come into being without a common will directed towards establishing them?”33 As already suggested by our discussion in the first section, Menger’s stated assumption begs the question.

Nevertheless, although Hayek’s (or his editor’s — see footnote 3) ahistorical treatment of capitalism in this book as a spontaneously emerging system rather than the creation of power is laughable, his critiques of social engineering and hubristic attempts to schematically remodel society — in addition to its inadvertent usefulness as a critique of many of the institutions of capitalism itself — is also genuinely useful for envisioning the general outlines of a post-capitalist society. Specifically, he attacks social engineering (“the notion that man can consciously choose where he wants to go”) and constructivist rationalism (“the… interpretation of systems of law and morals according to which their validity and meaning are supposed to depend wholly on the will and intention of their designers”).34

Useful to us, in particular, is “the astonishing fact, revealed by economics and biology, that order generated without design can far outstrip plans men consciously contrive.”35

…[O]ur values and institutions are determined not simply by preceding causes but as part of a process of unconscious self-organisation of a structure or pattern. This is true not only of economics, but in a wide area, and is well known today in the biological sciences. This insight was only the first of a growing family of theories that account for the formation of complex structures in terms of processes transcending our capacity to observe all the several circumstances operating in the determination of their particular manifestations. When I began my work I felt that I was nearly alone in working on the evolutionary formation of such highly complex self-maintaining orders. Meanwhile, researches on this kind of problem  — under various names, such as autopoiesis, cybernetics, homeostasis, spontaneous order, self-organisation, synergetics, systems theory, and so on — have become so numerous that I have been able to study closely no more than a few of them.36

And elsewhere: “There can be no deliberately planned substitutes for such a self-ordering process of adaptation to the unknown.”37 For Hayek, this means we do not “create” a self-ordering system through conscious design, but — based on what limited knowledge we possess of the structures of existing self-ordering systems — create the optimal conditions under which such a system can create itself. “For in fact we are able to bring about an ordering of the unknown only by causing it to order itself.”38 “In order to induce the self-formation of certain abstract structures of inter-personal relations, we need to secure the assistance of some very general conditions, and then allow each individual element to find its own place within the larger order.”39

In short: “The difference between the two kinds of rules is the same as that between laying down a Rule of the Road, as in the Highway Code, and ordering people where to go; or, better still, between providing signposts and commanding people which road to take.”40

This dovetails considerably with the general body of thought in the field of complexity theory on emergent, self-organizing systems. Everywhere we look we see systems characterized by modular, building-block architectures because such a structure (M. Mitchell Waldrop writes)

transforms a system’s ability to learn, evolve and adapt…. Once a set of building blocks… has been tweaked and refined and thoroughly debugged through experience… then it can generally be adapted and recombined to build a great many new concepts… Certainly that’s a much more efficient way to create something new than starting all over from scratch. And that fact, in turn, suggests a whole new mechanism for adaptation in general. Instead of moving through that immense space of possibilities step by step, so to speak, an adaptive system can reshuffle its building blocks and take giant leaps.” 

A small number of building blocks can be shuffled and recombined to make any number of complex systems.41

Starting from a large number of modular individuals, each capable of interacting with a few other individuals, and acting on other individuals according to a simple grammar of a few rules, under the right circumstances it’s possible for the modular individuals to undergo a rapid phase transition. According to systems theorist Stuart Kauffman: “The growth of complexity really does have something to do with far-from-equilibrium systems building themselves up, cascading to higher and higher levels of organization. Atoms, molecules, autocatalytic sets, et cetera.”42

Hayek frames the superiority of emergent, self-organizing orders as an indictment of “socialism,” because for him — as for all right-libertarian polemicists since Mises and Rand — socialism equates to government ownership and central planning. For most of the libertarian commentariat, the more stuff government owns and controls, the more socialist it is.43 

Nevertheless, all of this has a high degree of relevance to interstitial models of post-capitalist transition that see a socialist successor system as the emergent product of a wide range of present-day building blocks that are gradually developing and coalescing in a self-organized manner.

I contrast this model of post-capitalist, post-state society not only to socialist models that assume high degrees of centralized coordination and planning, but to all schools of anarchism or socialism that envision systematically new-modeling society on the basis of any uniform organizational template — whether it be syndicates, councils, markets, municipal assemblies, agro-industrial communes, or whatever. 

The latter models, although gratifying to the world-building instincts of anyone — including myself! — with a utopian imagination, are what Marx dismissed as “writing recipes for the cook shops of the future.” And they’re fundamentally misguided, when contrasted with any realistic understanding of how systemic transition is likely to take place.

Corporate-state capitalism is highly unlikely to be replaced by any coherently-designed successor system, in a transition process brought about by converting everybody to the same political ism or getting everyone to agree on the same organizational template as a basis for constructing the new society. A successor society is much more likely to emerge as the sum total product of the myriad of spontaneous actions people take, out of necessity, to survive the crisis tendencies of the present one. A thousand different organizational expedients and forms of praxis, distributed throughout the interstices of the present society, are the seeds of the successor society.

A polymathic Twitter commentator who goes by the handle yungneocon expressed a similar approach in an extended thread. After stating his preference for a “negative” approach — i.e. starting out by eliminating the most extractive institutions that define the character of the present system — he continues:

I don’t mean this in some “yeah destroy everything” infantile way — but where coercive and extractive structures exist, that function by suppressing or eliminating pre-existing, or, dare I even say ”’natural”’ positives, their elimination IS literally positive.

A bad faith critic would be inclined to say I am all negative (by focussing on ending extraction, enclosure, retribution, prisons, and private land monopoly), but this isn’t fair — I’m simply an agnostic/pluralist about what the positive post-emancipation project would be

There are many social systems, when stated in ‘ideal’ terms, I would be fine living with, for the most part — gift economies, communization, FALSC, mutualist hobby markets + common ownership, Parecon/Participatory Planning, cybernetic socialism, council communism, etc.

Would I be comfortable positing any of these as the final state? or sufficient? or perfect? or superior to the other alternatives presented? or the only available options? absolutely not on all counts.

I also trust people, and do not think we can, let alone need, to figure out every detail ahead of time — such arrogant confidence in the ability to predict, plan, control, and address contingencies, localities, novelties, etc, is fatal to success & emancipation.

If I were to somewhat mis-use the terminology of complexity & systems, I think our positive projects are best seen as ‘attractors’ — focal points around which dynamic systems adapt & to which they tend; catalysts & resources for action, but not pre-determined outcomes….

Thinkers, ranging across eras, disciplines & ideologies as Aristotle, Ibn-Khaldun, Smith, Darwin, Kropotkin, Hayek, Taleb, Ostrom, Meadows, Bookchin, Scott, Polanyi, Collins, Sahlins, Ward, Graeber & others, emphasize complex, evolved, decentralized, organic systems.

These emerge in time & space through slow plodding, tacit knowledge, learning, trial & error, cooperation, evolution, selection, internalization, canalization, and so on, without unitary top-down planners global/universal in time & space.

Obviously, what the Smith, Hayek, Taleb, style crew ignores is that these systems DO involve planning — indeed, even central planning, at times — but they do so in a piecemeal, often local, temporary, evolved, contingent, and, if not spontaneous, at least novel fashion.

Now, in the cases where systems have built up, by trial and error, habits, norms, practices, knowledge, skills, traditions, cultures, histories, systems, and so on, over a long period of time, it is the case that these systems will tend to be more robust, adaptable & unique

When someone comes in and tosses out these decentralized, evolved tacit traditions, and attempts to impose grids & order, they often end up doing devastating damage, sometimes losing incredibly robust knowledge irreparably44

The “I trust people” comment, in particular, echoes the stated approach of David Graeber: “When people ask me what sorts of organization could exist in an anarchist society,” 

I always answer: any form of organization one can imagine, and probably many we presently can’t, with only one proviso—they would be limited to ones that could exist without anyone having the ability, at any point, to call on armed men to show up and say “I don’t care what you have to say about this; shut up and do what you’re told.”45

I’m less interested in figuring out what sort of anarchist I am than in working in broad coalitions that operate in accord with anarchist principles: movements that are not trying to work through or become governments; movements uninterested in assuming the role of de facto government institutions like trade organizations or capitalist firms; groups that focus on making our relations with each other a model of the world we wish to create. In other words, people working toward truly free societies. After all, it’s hard to figure out exactly what kind of anarchism makes the most sense when so many questions can only be answered further down the road. Would there be a role for markets in a truly free society? How could we know? I myself am confident, based on history, that even if we did try to maintain a market economy in such a free society— that is, one in which there would be no state to enforce contracts, so that agreements came to be based only on trust—economic relations would rapidly morph into something libertarians would find completely unrecognizable, and would soon not resemble anything we are used to thinking of as a “market” at all. I certainly can’t imagine anyone agreeing to work for wages if they have any other options. But who knows, maybe I’m wrong. I am less interested in working out what the detailed architecture of what a free society would be like than in creating the conditions that would enable us to find out.46

Instead of central planning and development according to a centralized design, we should pursue something like the decentralized development of a pattern language, in which a very large set of basic building blocks — an alphabet — is endlessly combined and recombined into an infinity of molecular forms by local initiative, according to a basic grammar. Instead of redistribution, or distribution by planning bureaucracies, we have predistribution — primarily through the definition of basic property rules. As opposed to redistribution, predistribution designs the system for optimal distribution in the first place.

Chris Dillow, a Marxist economist who is adamantly anti-managerialist, equally adamant about the value of distributed knowledge, and open-minded about the role of markets, advocates models of socialism along such lines. He challenges neoliberal arguments that inequality is the product of an efficiently functioning market and reflects differences in marginal productivity, and argues instead that inequality is “a symptom of malfunctioning markets — that… ‘the system is rigged.’”47 His proposals for predistribution include initially defining property rights so as to build workers’ bargaining power and broad claims to income streams directly into the system. Under such a model, equality of distribution automatically results from the the distribution of bargaining power and property rights, rather than requiring the ongoing intervention of a managerial state. Among the examples Dillow himself suggests are “increasing unions’ strength; encouraging the growth of worker coops; and a citizens basic income sufficiently high to allow people to reject low wages and poor working conditions.”48

Alongside the above provisions Dillow mentions, which are all aimed at increasing the bargaining power of labor, we might add industrial co-determination on the German model as a transitional measure. Or, since we’re envisioning full-blown post-capitalism, perhaps the entire elimination of absentee firm ownership and, in its place, automatic ownership of the firm by its workforce. This is the focus of David Ellerman’s large body of left-libertarian scholarship, as well as a major organizational component of left-libertarian utopias ranging from Callenbach’s Ecotopia books to Robinson’s Mars Trilogy to Yaris Varoufakis’s Another Now.

Other changes in property rules might include abolishing intellectual property in order to reflect the non-scarce and non-rivalrous nature of information — a measure Hayek himself considers worthy of consideration, as we shall see below — and commons-based ownership of land and natural resources through community land trusts, Ostromite commons governance of natural resources, etc.

Dillow also notes that such predistribution through redefined property rights would have the advantage of increased productivity, which stands to reason given that the existing definition of property rights largely reflects the role of the rentier classes in state policy, with property rules mostly designed to enable rentiers to extract unearned surpluses from the productive — to increase the size of the rent-extractors’ slice of the pie, in other words — rather than to maximize productivity.

As Dillow argues, not only do existing property rules under capitalism decrease efficiency at the point of production, but the resulting inequality diverts resources into wasteful and irrational avenues.

…[A]ctually-existing capitalism itself contains many dysfunctional incentives — ones that constrain innovation and encourage rent-seeking….

One such bad incentive is that high inequality gives the rich stronger incentives to protect their privilege by investing in methods which keep or increase their share of the economic pie without much increasing it. Sam Bowles and Arjun Jaydev show that unequal countries employ more “guard labour” — policemen, security guards, supervisors and so — than egalitarian ones. They say:

“A significant portion of an economy‘s productive potential may be devoted to the exercise of power and to the perpetuation of social relationships of domination and subordination.”

A similar thing applies to innovation. Capitalists have incentives to invest in power-biased technical change — devices such as CCTV, Worksnaps or tachographs that help bosses monitor workers. Such technologies reduce the need for efficiency wages and so boost profits. But it’s not clear they are good for aggregate output.49

Socialist models based on predistribution and the initial definition of property rights have, among other things going for them, the fact that “marginal productivity” is a largely circular concept. That is, since the marginal productivity of a factor input or market actor is whatever its remuneration adds to the final price of a commodity, its marginal productivity really amounts to whatever it’s able to charge for its “services.” In other words, “marginal productivity” follows power. 

Predistribution is about changing the distribution of power — arguably in ways that are more rational, insofar as they vest it in parties that make the highest contribution to productivity, possess the most vital knowledge, or have the highest monitoring costs, as per New Institutionalists like Oliver Williamson — and then stepping back and letting the system run itself.

As testimony in favor of a socialist system based on the automatic application of abstract, general rules rather than ongoing planning, we have Hayek himself.

The question then is how to secure the greatest possible freedom for all. This can be secured by uniformly restricting the freedom of all by abstract rules that preclude arbitrary or discriminatory coercion by or of other people, that prevent any from invading the free sphere of any other…. In short, common concrete ends are replaced by common abstract rules. Government is needed only to enforce these abstract rules, and thereby to protect the individual against coercion, or invasion of his free sphere, by others. Whereas enforced obedience to common concrete ends is tantamount to slavery, obedience to common abstract rules (however burdensome they may still feel) provides scope for the most extraordinary freedom and diversity.50

And again: “…[T]here is a difference between following rules of conduct, on the one hand, and knowledge about something, on the other…. The habit of following rules of conduct is an ability utterly different from the knowledge that one’s actions will have certain kinds of effects.”51

The advantages are in part practical, of course — i.e. in superior efficiency of coordination. “The state” — or, as anarchists, we should say “society”

should confine itself to establishing rules applying to general types of situations, and should allow the individuals freedom in everything which depends on the circumstances of time and place, because only the individuals concerned in each instance can fully know these circumstances and adapt their actions to them.52

But a society organized around general rules rather than administrative coordination also permits a much greater degree of day-to-day freedom. A free society, Hayek argues, requires the Rule of Law, in the sense of a set of conditions in which people can confidently make life decisions based on an understanding of the general principles that govern them, with a high degree of assurance that they will not be subject to interference by arbitrary and unpredictable action by the authorities.

Stripped of all technicalities this means that government in all its actions is bound by rules fixed and announced beforehand — rules which make it possible to foresee with fair certainty how the authority will use its coercive powers in given circumstances, and to plan one’s individual affairs on the basis of this knowledge…. While every law restricts individual freedom to some extent by altering the means which people may use in the pursuit of their aims, under the Rule of Law the government is prevented from stultifying individual efforts by ad hoc action.55

Economic planning of the collectivist kind necessarily involves the very opposite of this. The planning authority cannot confine itself to providing opportunities for unknown people to make whatever use of them they like. It cannot tie itself down in advance to general and formal rules which prevent arbitrariness. It must provide for the actual needs of people as they arise and then choose deliberately between them. It must constantly decide questions which cannot be answered by formal principles only, and in making these decisions it must set up distinctions of merit between the needs of different people. When the government has to decide how many pigs are to be reared or how many  buses are to be run, which coal mines are to operate, or at what prices boots are to be sold, these decisions cannot be deduced from formal principles, or settled for long periods in advance. They depend inevitably on the circumstances of the moment, and in making such decisions it will always be necessary to balance one against the other the interests of various persons and groups. In the end somebody’s views will have to decide whose interests are more important; and these views must become part of the law of the land, a new distinction of rank which the coercive apparatus of government imposes upon the people.54

He cites, as an example of universally binding, abstract, and impersonal rules, Hume’s “three ‘fundamental laws of nature’ : ‘the stability of possession, of its transference by consent, and of the performance of promises’.”55 Since this simple ruleset — a society based on alienable, fee-simple property with secure absentee title, and enforceable contracts — was imposed in considerable part through conscious design, we shouldn’t fall too far afoul of Hayek in imposing a similarly small and simple set of rules for a socialist society, leaving the specifics to work themselves out as an emergent property of those rules. 

Then too, Hayek’s speculation on the forms of experimental tinkering he regarded as permissible for adapting property rules to ongoing experience included radically scaling back or eliminating patents and copyrights altogether.56 In fact he viewed a considerable number of measures we would consider quasi-socialist to be, at least theoretically, compatible with his liberal order.

There is… a strong case for reducing this inequality of opportunity [resulting from inheritance] as far as congenital differences permit and as it is possible to do so without destroying the impersonal character of the process by which everybody has to take his chance and no person’s view about what is right and desirable overrules that of others.57

He also acknowledged that the provision of some minimum guaranteed income to all through a welfare state, “outside of and supplementary to the market system,” was compatible with individual freedom.58>/sup>

And this throwaway observation is especially intriguing, even though Hayek himself raises the possibility and dismisses it:

That the ideal of justice of most socialists would be satisfied if merely private income from property were abolished and the differences between the earned incomes of different people remained what they are now, is true. What these people forget is that in transferring all property in the means of production to the state they put the state in a position whereby its action must in effect decide all other incomes.59

He dismisses it for illegitimate reasons:  namely his conflation of abolishing private income from property with nationalization and centralized governance of property, and his inability to imagine alternatives like a regime of distributed communal property owned by people on a local basis as members of land trusts, coliving complexes, worker cooperatives, stakeholder-governed public services and platforms, and the like.

The structure of the new society should be the outgrowth of seeds already developing in the present one, and the precise form it takes should be worked out in large part stigmergically, through collective, distributed intelligence. 

No less a radical than Marx saw the communist society of the future as something already existing, in embryonic form, in the capitalist society of his day, preparing to “burst out of its capitalist integument” when it reached the proper stage of development and could no longer progress within the bounds of its old cocoon. And aside from tentative transitional programs in the Communist Manifesto and Critique of the Gotha Program, and a piece of occasional writing in which he treated the Paris Commune as illustrating likely features of a future proletarian dictatorship, he mostly avoided writing “recipes for the cook shops of the future.”  

Hayek makes a convincing argument for a polyarchic system, even if it’s not the capitalist one he has in mind.

It is only because the control of the means of production is divided among many people acting independently that nobody has complete power over us, that we as individuals can decide what to do with ourselves. If all the means of production were vested in a single hand, whether it be nominally that of “society” as a whole, or that of a dictator, whoever exercises this control has complete power over us.60

The proper approach is to achieve the goals of distributive justice, not through the conscious and ongoing direction of a central authority, but by the initial distribution of property rights between a large number of self-governing entities — the land trusts, cooperatives and other institutions we enumerated above — operating according to general and impersonal rules which prevent property from becoming concentrated into a small number of hands or becoming a source of economic rents. Once these preconditions are established, the specific forms of coordination between the various entities is a secondary matter. It matters little whether they coordinate their mutual relations through socialist markets, through horizontal and reciprocal planning between nodes in a network, or through some combination of the two.

The Use of Knowledge in Society. At the outset of this article, Hayek states the nature of the problem facing any would-be central planner: that the sum total of knowledge needed for rational planning is not available to any one decision-making center.

The peculiar character of the problem of a rational economic order is determined precisely by the fact that the knowledge of the circumstances of which we must make use never exists in concentrated or integrated form, but solely as the dispersed bits of incomplete and frequently contradictory knowledge which all the separate individuals possess. The economic problem of society is thus not merely a problem of how to allocate “given” resources — if ”given’ is taken to mean given to a single mind which deliberately solves the problem set by these “data.” It is rather a problem of how to secure the best use of resources known to any of the members of society, for ends whose relative importance only these individuals know. Or, to put it briefly, it is a problem of the utilization of knowledge not given to anyone in its totality.61

…This is not a dispute about whether planning is to be done or not. It is a dispute as to whether planning is to be done centrally, by one authority for the whole economic system, or is to be divided among many individuals. Planning in the specific sense in which the term is used in contemporary controversy necessarily means central planning-direction of the whole economic system according to one unified plan. Competition, on the other hand, means decentralized planning by many separate persons.62

Hayek posits a contrast between theoretical and practical knowledge essentially identical to that James Scott draws between techne and metis

Today it is almost heresy to suggest that scientific knowledge is not the sum of all knowledge. But a little reflection will show that there is beyond question a body of very important but unorganized knowledge which cannot possibly be called scientific in the sense of knowledge of general rules: the knowledge of the particular circumstances of time and place. It is with respect to this that practically every individual has some advantage over all others in that he possesses unique information of which beneficial use might be made, but of which use can be made only if the decisions depending on it are left to him or are made with his active cooperation. We need to remember only how much we have to learn in any occupation after we have completed our theoretical training, how big a part of our working life we spend learning particular jobs, and how valuable an asset in all walks of life is knowledge of people, of local conditions, and special circumstances. To know of and put to use a machine not fully employed, or somebody’s skill which could be better utilized, or to be aware of a surplus stock which can be drawn upon during an interruption of supplies, is socially quite as useful as the knowledge of better alternative techniques.63

He argues, ironically, that such distributed practical knowledge is looked down on because of intellectuals’ disdain for “commerce,” and it is believed that such knowledge should be replaced by universally available knowledge.

It is a curious fact that this sort of knowledge should today be generally regarded with a kind of contempt, and that anyone who by such knowledge gains an advantage over somebody better equipped with theoretical or technical knowledge is thought to have acted almost disreputably. To gain an advantage from better knowledge of facilities of communication or transport is sometimes regarded as almost dishonest, although it is quite as important that society make use of the best opportunities in this respect as in using the latest scientific discoveries. This prejudice has in a considerable measure affected the attitude toward commerce in general compared with that toward production. Even economists who regard themselves as definitely above the crude materialist fallacies of the past constantly commit the same mistake where activities directed toward the acquisition of such practical knowledge are concerned-apparently because in their scheme of things all such knowledge is supposed to be “given.” The common idea now seems to be that all such knowledge should as a matter of course be readily at the command of everybody, and the reproach of irrationality leveled against the existing economic order is frequently based on the fact that it is not so available. This view disregards the fact that the method by which such knowledge can be made as widely available as possible is precisely the problem to which we have to find an answer.64

But to bring back our friend Chris Dillow, the premier example of central planning in our post-Berlin Wall world is not Gosplan, but the capitalist corporation. To quote Dillow, “if you want to find people who still believe in central planning today, you should look not among Marxists but in company boardrooms. It’s bosses who believe complex systems can be controlled well from the top down….”65 And elsewhere: “My support for worker democracy owes less to Marx – who wrote little about post-capitalism – than it does to Hayek.”66

Production workers’ distributed knowledge of the production process, and the human capital involved in their work relationships, is in fact the main source of value added. And the dominant approach of management, in both the capitalist corporation and the state socialist planned economy, has been to attempt to reduce metis to forms of knowledge which are legible to managerial hierarchies through deskilling strategies like Taylorism.

Authority relations of the sort that exist within the managerial hierarchies of capitalist corporations, likewise, are the main barriers to aggregating the distributed knowledge of those directly engaged in the production process. When superior rungs of a hierarchy do not represent the lower rungs, and have interests opposed to theirs, those on the lower rungs have an incentive to hoard knowledge and to economize on effort. They know very well that any contribution they make to increased efficiency will be used against them in the form of downsizings, speedups, and increased management compensation. The capitalist managerial hierarchy, by its very nature, exists in order to extract value from those at the bottom; any gains in productivity will be appropriated by those in a superior position of power.

Hierarchies exist, not because of their superior efficiency at aggregating dispersed information, but because of their superior efficiency at extracting a surplus from people who have a fundamental conflict of interest with the people they’re working for. A hierarchical organization is designed to trade suboptimal performance for ease of surplus extraction. It imposes standardized work rules, even at the cost of reducing the discretion of those with the most situational knowledge, because the latter cannot be trusted with the discretion to use their knowledge with the greatest effectiveness. They have no personal interest in the goals of the organization, and no interests in common with those running it. 

The situation is explained by the anarchist Shevek, in a conversation with an elderly conservative, in Ursula LeGuin’s The Dispossessed:

Atro had once explained to him how this was managed, how the sergeants could give the privates orders, how the lieutenants could give the privates and the sergeants orders, how the captains . . . and so on and so on up to the generals, who could give everyone else orders and need take them from none, except the commander in chief. Shevek had listened with incredulous disgust. “You call that organization?” he had inquired. “You even call it discipline? But it is neither. It is a coercive mechanism of extraordinary inefficiency — a kind of seventh-millennium steam engine! With such a rigid and fragile structure what could be done that was worth doing?” This had given Atro a chance to argue the worth of warfare as the breeder of courage and manliness and weeder-out of the unfit, but the very line of his argument had forced him to concede the effectiveness of guerrillas, organized from below, self-disciplined. “But that only works when the people think they’re fighting for something of their own — you know, their homes, or some notion or other,” the old man had said. Shevek had dropped the argument. He now continued it, in the darkening basement among the stacked crates of unlabeled chemicals. He explained to Atro that he now understood why the Army was organized as it was. It was indeed quite necessary. No rational form of organization would serve the purpose. He simply had not understood that the purpose was to enable men with machine guns to kill unarmed men and women easily and in great quantities when told to do so.67

It follows, therefore, that the ideal “method by which such knowledge can be made as widely available as possible” is to eliminate the conflicts of interest inherent in the authority relationship. This means to place the role of coordination production in the hands of those directly responsible to those who possess distributed knowledge and create value through it, and to guarantee that all productivity gains produced by effective use of distributed knowledge are fully internalized by its possessors.

So we wind up with yet another argument from Hayek in favor of decentralization — in this case its superior aggregation and utilization of dispersed, or tacit, knowledge — in addition to those in The Road to Serfdom and The Fatal Conceit. As he argues,

the sort of knowledge with which I have been concerned is knowledge of the kind which by its nature cannot enter into statistics and therefore cannot be conveyed to any central authority in statistical form. The statistics which such a central authority would have to use would have to be arrived at precisely by abstracting from minor differences between the things, by lumping together, as resources of one kind, items which differ as regards location, quality, and other particulars, in a way which may be very significant for the specific decision. It follows from this that central planning based on statistical information by its nature cannot take direct account of these circumstances of time and place, and that the central planner will have to find some way or other in which the decisions depending on them can be left to the “man on the spot.”

If we can agree that the economic problem of society is mainly one of rapid adaptation to changes in the particular circumstances of time and place, it would seem to follow that the ultimate decisions must be left to the people who are familiar with these circumstances, who know directly of the relevant changes and of the resources immediately available to meet them.68

Hayek goes on to argue, in the second half of the article, that his “men on the spot” in turn need a way of obtaining the dispersed knowledge of others which they are lacking. Within the firm, as I have argued, this means management that represents and reflects the interests of all those in possession of the knowledge. 

So far this essentially corresponds to what Harvey Liebenstein called “X-efficiency.” The concept of allocative efficiency, to which neoclassical economics pays far greater attention, treats the internal workings of the enterprise for all intents and purposes as a black box, and focuses instead on the most efficient combination of gross inputs that can be allocated to the firm. X-efficiency, on the other hand, concerns the best use of resources that are available within the firm — in other words things like the best placement of machines, and other details of the work process.69

But in regard to production inputs from outside the firm — allocative efficiency — the aggregation of dispersed knowledge also requires knowledge as to the relative scarcity and cost of production of such inputs, and which to economize on. And in regard to outputs, it requires knowledge of relative demand for competing products. 

Hayek uses this as the jumping-off point for essentially restating Mises’ version of the economic calculation argument, based on the need for an ordinal ranking system of cost and benefit — namely price. There has to be private property in producer goods like machinery and raw materials, Mises argued, in order for a system of market prices to develop that convey information about the relative scarcity and costs of the inputs, and the comparative value of returns from the alternative uses to which they might be put.

Now, as I already suggested, I’m agnostic on the relative efficiency of market pricing and horizontal planning, in a decentralized libertarian socialist economy.

But I would also add that the value of prices as a source of information for the allocation of resources is only as good as the quality of the process by which the prices are generated. The “Garbage In, Garbage Out” rule applies. And the quality of input pricing under capitalism is almost entirely garbage. “Market pricing,” as such, does not result in calculational rationality if the prices are themselves irrational. 

We have to keep in mind that, however much apologists for capitalism imply otherwise, property rules do not arise through the market; rather, the market presupposes them. And no particular set of property rules is self-evident. Rather, the definition of property rules is logically prior to the functioning of the market; market-clearing prices are established given a pre-existing set of property rules, and the equilibrium prices that result will vary greatly depending on which among many possible alternative rule sets exists. As I have written elsewhere:

Whether “strong property rights” facilitate or impede economic progress depends on the specifics of how they’re drawn up and who they’re assigned to…. There is a wide range of possible property rights, with varying effects. Some forms of property rights are conducive to economic progress, and some forms are a drain or impediment. The optimal design of property rights is the subject of a whole field of institutional economics, perhaps best exemplified by Oliver Williamson.

If property rights are well-designed — if they’re assigned to stakeholders who create the bulk of value, and/or whose contractual performance is hardest to verify and control under the terms of an incomplete contract — they will facilitate progress.

If they’re badly designed, they will siphon productive resources into high-cost management surveillance, guard labor, economic rents, and waste production. Badly designed property rights benefit rentiers at the expense of producers, and disincentivize productive activity by the latter. And economic rents — that is, returns greater than needed to bring services to market — will, by definition, not incentivize additional output.70

Indeed, if a system of property rules is badly designed, so as to misrepresent the relative scarcity or abundance of material inputs, or create information and incentive problems in the governance of the enterprise, the resulting price signals will create as much calculational chaos as any socialist planning system Mises could imagine.

So we find that, if Mises’ calculation proves anything with regard to existing capitalism, it proves too much — far too much. For the property rules we have now could not have a greater distorting effect had they actually been designed for that purpose.

We already discussed the informational and incentive problems caused by the existing model of property rights and governance in the firm. 

In addition, property in information makes it artificially scarce and expensive. It erects toll-gates to knowledge sharing that hinder collaboration and innovation, and impede the “shoulders of giants” effet. And generally speaking, it prevents the use of knowledge and technique to their full effect.

But our system of property rights in land and natural resources, in contrast, makes material inputs artificially abundant and cheap to the propertied classes (the heirs and assigns of the past expropriators and enclosers of said resources), and artificially scarce and expensive to everyone else.

So on the one hand we’ve had centuries of a capitalist growth model based on the extensive addition of more artificially cheap material inputs. The imperialist powers fight resource wars, install governments friendly to extractive industry, encourage economic development in the Global South based on the export of raw materials, and resort to eminent domain and liability caps to maximize the supply of energy and mineral inputs.  

Corporate agribusiness is so inefficient in terms of output per acre, compared to small-scale intensive forms of cultivation, because it treats land as a free good. Latin American haciendas hold almost 90% of their ill-gotten land out of cultivation, while neighboring land-poor peasants must resort to working for them as wage laborers. And the U.S. government pays farmers to hold land out of use, so that sitting on idle land becomes a real estate investment with a guaranteed return. Patented “Green Revolution” seed varieties are designed to be used on giant plantation farms built on stolen and enclosed land, with access to enormous amounts of heavily subsidized irrigation water and other inputs. 

Indeed the very metrics of capitalism — “marginal productivity,” corporate accounting rules, and GDP — all treat the expenditure of resources, as such, as the creation of value. And capitalism’s chronic tendencies towards surplus capital and idle capacity create an imperative for subsidized waste — through planned obsolescence, military spending, suburbanization and car culture, etc. — in order to avoid Depression.

And on the other hand, there’s an artificially high degree of surplus labor extraction in the wage system because the working class was forcibly separated from the land. Access to land for housing and subsistence is artificially expensive thanks to the appropriation and enclosure of vacant and unused land, and continuing landlord title to unused buildings.

But what if we start from the assumption of a socialist system in which prices accurately reflect actual scarcity and cost, and property rules in the firm maximize efficiency in aggregating and utilizing knowledge? For example, we make all information Free and Open Source. We in effect reverse the enclosures, incorporating residential, commercial, and agricultural land into land trusts, and place natural resources under the kind of commons governance bodies that Elinor Ostrom envisioned. We reorganize utilities and public services (including platforms like Amazon, Twitter, Uber, and Airbnb) as stakeholder cooperatives, and convert manufacturing firms into self-managed worker co-ops.

Given such property rules as the starting point, the market price system would be likely to operate quite effectively in conveying information between the various decentralized local bodies constituting the economy. It would, ironically, be exactly the kind of market socialism whose practicability Hayek denied in his debates with Lange, on the grounds that it could not meaningfully price inputs.

Conclusion. So we see that, far from being the unassailable critiques of socialism or defenses of capitalism he imagined, Hayek’s arguments are in fact not only quite helpful in thinking through the outlines of a future libertarian socialist society, but fairly devastating as critiques of capitalism itself. Not only are the corporate hierarchies and authoritarian employment relationships that exist under capitalism directly counter-productive to the transmission and aggregation of information, but a self-managed and cooperative socialist system in which decision-making power is vested in those who possess the relevant knowledge and contribute the effort would be ideal for putting distributed knowledge to work. Rather than facilitating rational economic calculation, it is more accurate to say that the prevailing property rights under capitalism render it impossible; the pricing of inputs enabled by decentralized cooperative and social control of resources would come the closest to accurately conveying information of any available alternative. Not only did he fail in his purpose of justifying capitalism or ruling out socialism, but Hayek actually demonstrated the non-viability of any society founded on authority, hierarchy, or class. For this anarchists owe him a debt of gratitude.

Only one thing stands in the way of replacing Mises’ statue in the future socialist planning ministry with one of Hayek: A libertarian socialist society will have no need for such a ministry.

  1.  Friedrich A. Hayek, “History and Politics.” Introduction to Hayek, ed., Capitalism and the Historians (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1954), pp. 3-4.
  2. Ibid., p. 7.
  3.  In the interest of both accuracy and charity (given my especially harsh language toward Hayek regarding this book in particular), I should mention that there seems to be some controversy over whether The Fatal Conceit is, at least in its entirety, the work of Hayek himself.
    • Jeffrey Friedman writes:

      In 1986 I served as research assistant to W. W. Bartley, III, Hayek’s officially designated biographer and the “editor” of the book while it was being written — apparently by Bartley, with little noticeable input from Hayek, who was mortally ill. What Bartley characterized as confused and mostly unusable notes and passages written by Hayek, some of which ended up in the book’s Appendices, apparently served as the basis of Bartley’s efforts to complete a manuscript; the products of Bartley’s labors were allegedly reviewed by Hayek.And Friedman raises some questions as to whether Hayek played any significant role in reviewing the final product. I had noticed independently that the general tone of this book is much more right-wing than that of Hayek’s books from the 1940s. Whether that reflects Hayek’s own intellectual evolution over the years, or Bartley’s idiosyncrasies, I can’t say. In any case it’s an open question just how much the text reflects Hayek’s considered views. 

      Jeffrey Friedman, “What’s Wrong With Libertarianism,”Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society (1997), pp. 463-464n <https://sci-hub.do/10.1080/08913819708443469>. I’m grateful to Roderick Long for bringing this to my attention.

    • Greg Ransom, of the Hayek Center, stated on the Center’s Twitter account regarding Hayek’s role in writing the book:

      @hamandcheeseHayek wrote extensive drafts of the book — most of the documents are in the Hayek archive.

      August 31, 2015 <https://twitter.com/FriedrichHayek/status/638381661957197828>.

      I’ve read the various typescripts of *The Fatal Conceit* found in the Hoover Archive and I can vouch that most of it is written by Hayek — but we do need a scholars edition which identifies the sentences and word added by @bryan_caplanand William Bartley.

      June 8, 2019 <https://twitter.com/FriedrichHayek/status/1137447393358516224>

      We know that Hayek wrote a draft of *The Fatal Conceit* which James Buchanan hated because Buchanan was a Locke / rationalist and Hayek was a Hume / Burke / Coke / Darwin evolutionary whig. Bartley & Caplan “modernized it” with eg references to Foucault & a bit of Bartley/Popper.

      June 8, 2019 <https://twitter.com/FriedrichHayek/status/1137448220672479232>.

  4. Friedrich A. Hayek, The Fatal Conceit: The Errors of Socialism. The Collected Works of F.A. Hayek, Vol. 1. Edited by W.W. Bartley III (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988), p. 6.
  5. Ibid., p. 29.
  6. Ibid., pp. 35-36.
  7. Ibid., pp. 29-31.
  8. For an examination at length of such nursery fables and just-so stories in capitalist ideology, see Kevin Carson, Capitalist Nursery Fables: The Tragedy of Private Property, and the Farce of Its Defense (Center for a Stateless Society, 2020) <https://c4ss.org/content/53305>.
  9. Hayek, The Fatal Conceit, p. 33.
  10. Ibid., p. 76.
  11. Ibid., p. 82. Of course none of this anti-conspiracism stops him from accusing American socialists of “deliberate deception” in “appropriating” the term “liberalism.” Hayek, The Fatal Conceit, p. 100.
  12. J. L. and Barbara Hammond, The Village Labourer (1760-1832) (London: Longmans, Green & Co., 1913) 27-8, 35-6.
  13. Hayek, The Fatal Conceit, pp. 123-124.
  14. Ibid., p. 82.
  15. Ibid., p. 92.
  16. Ibid., p. 104.
  17. Thorstein Veblen, quoted in John R. Commons, Institutional Economics (New York: Macmillan, 1934),p. 664.
  18. Henry George, Jr., The Menace of Privilege: A Study of the Dangers to the Republic from the Existence of a Favored Class (London: Macmillan, 1905), p. 411.
  19. Dobb, Political Economy and Capitalism: Some Essays in Economic Tradition. Second revised edition (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd, 1940, 1960), p. 66.
  20. Hayek, The Fatal Conceit, p. 131.
  21. Anyone curious for more specifics on these claims can start with Silvia Federici’s Caliban and the Witch: Women, the Body and Primitive Accumulation (New York: Autonomedia, 2004), and Kropotkin’s treatment of the early modern period in The State: Its Historic Role (London: “Freedom” Office, 1898).
  22. Hayek, The Fatal Conceit, p. 6.
  23. Karl Marx, Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy. Translated with a Foreword by Martin Nicolaus (London, New York, Victoria, Toronto, Auckland: Penguin, 1973), p. 495.
  24. Ibid., pp. 503, 507.
  25. Ibid., p. 510.
  26. Hayek, The Road to Serfdom (London and New York: Routledge, 1944), pp. 26-27.
  27. Ibid., p. 26n.
  28. Murray Bookchin, “What Is Social Ecology?” in M.E. Zimmerman, ed., Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1993). Hosted at Anarchist Archives <http://dwardmac.pitzer.edu/Anarchist_Archives/bookchin/socecol.html> (accessed November 25, 2020).
  29. Hayek, The Road to Serfdom, p. 70.
  30. Ibid., p. 66.
  31. See, for example, William Blum, Killing Hope: U.S. Military and C.I.A. Interventions Since World War II. Revised edition (London: Zed Books, 2014).
  32. Hayek, The Fatal Conceit, p. 27.
  33. Ibid., p. 3.
  34. Ibid., pp. 51, 52.
  35. Ibid., p. 8.
  36. Ibid., p. 9.
  37. Ibid., p. 76.
  38. Ibid., pp. 82-83.
  39. Ibid., p. 83.
  40. Ibid., p. 78.
  41. M. Mitchell Waldrop, Complexity: The Emerging Science at the Edge of Order and Chaos (New York, London, Toronto, Sydney, Tokyo, Singapore: Simon & Schuster, 1992), pp. 169-170.
  42. Ibid., pp. 316-317.
  43. For an especially egregious display of this tendency, see Jacob Hornberger’s series “Socialism, American Style,” in Future of Freedom. In Part 1 of that witless series, he writes “A 100 percent socialist society is one in which the state owns everything — the businesses, industries, houses, farms, and all other personal and real property. In a purely socialist society, everyone is a government employee.” “Socialism, American Style, Part 1,” Future of Freedom, May 2020, p. 2 (online at <https://www.fff.org/explore-freedom/article/socialism-american-style-part-1/>).
  44. Twitter, September 26, 2018. Thread beginning at Sept 26 2018 <https://twitter.com/yungneocon/status/1045047763258535951>.
  45. David Graeber, The Democracy Project: A History, a Crisis, a Movement (Spiegel & Grau, 2013), pp. 187-188.
  46. Ibid., pp. 192-193
  47. Chris Dillow, “Begging the inequality question,” Stumbling and Mumbling, April 30, 2014 <https://stumblingandmumbling.typepad.com/stumbling_and_mumbling/2014/04/begging-the-inequality-question.html>.
  48. Dillow, “Predistribution — Good, Bad & Unoriginal,” Stumbling and Mumbling, September 6, 2012 <https://stumblingandmumbling.typepad.com/stumbling_and_mumbling/2012/09/predistribution-good-bad-unoriginal.html>.
  49. Dillow, “Capitalism’s bad incentives,” Stumbling and Mumbling, October 7, 2017 <https://stumblingandmumbling.typepad.com/stumbling_and_mumbling/2017/10/capitalisms-bad-incentives.html>.
  50. Hayek, The Fatal Conceit, pp. 63-64.
  51. Ibid., p. 78.
  52. Ibid., p. 79.
  53. Hayek, The Road to Serfdom, pp. 75-76.
  54. Ibid., p. 77.
  55. Hayek, The Fatal Conceit, p. 34.
  56. Ibid., pp. 36-37, 69.
  57. Hayek, The Road to Serfdom, p. 102.
  58. Ibid., p. 120.
  59. Ibid., p. 103.
  60. Ibid., p. 104.
  61. Friedrich Hayek, “The Use of Knowledge in Society,” The American Economic Review XXXV:4 (September 1945), pp. 519-520.
  62. Ibid., pp. 520-521.
  63. Ibid., pp. 521-522.
  64. Ibid., p. 522.
  65. Dillow, “Bad arguments against Marxism,” Stumbling and Mumbling, May 23, 2016 <https://stumblingandmumbling.typepad.com/stumbling_and_mumbling/2016/05/bad-arguments-against-marxism.html>.
  66. Dillow, “Diversity: a rightist ideal,” Stumbling and Mumbling, August 3, 2018 <https://stumblingandmumbling.typepad.com/stumbling_and_mumbling/2018/08/diversity-a-rightist-ideal.html>.
  67. Ursula LeGuin, The Dispossessed (New York: Harper Paperbacks, 1974), pp. 305-306.
  68. Hayek, “The Use of Knowledge in Society,” p. 524.
  69. Harvey Leibenstein, “Allocative Efficiency vs. ‘X-Efficiency’,” American Economic Review 56 (June 1966).
  70. Kevin Carson, “‘Economic Calculation,’ ‘Strong Property Rights,’ and Other Lies Koch-Funded Libertarian Commentators Told Me,” Center for a Stateless Society, August 3, 2019 <https://c4ss.org/content/52310>.
Stigmergy - C4SS Blog
C4SS Writer Kelly Wright Needs Our Support!

Hey everyone, thanks for all the ways in which you’ve supported our team and our writers over the years. Mutual aid is the foundational principle behind much of what we do, and it’s encouraging to see how far such a simple concept can take us.

Supporting each other through good or ill, we’re stronger together than we are on our own. Even in my own life, this community has helped me through a good few tough spots. One of the people who was always there to help was C4SS writer Kelly Wright.

Now, Kelly needs us to pay it back! She’s pursuing gender-affirming surgery that, as most probably know, tends to be prohibitively expensive and a difficult process to navigate. Click here or below to donate!

Kelly has long been a part of our network and she’s a powerful writer on transgender rights, police brutality, and militarism. You can see her work for C4SS, including a recent piece on Facebook’s ban of anarchist users and groups, here.

Here’s Kelly’s call for support:

Creating this fundraiser was probably inevitable, though I put it off as long as I could in the hopes of self-funding this major life milestone. Unfortunately navigating the bureaucracy of my insurance company is time-consuming and soul-deadening, and so I humbly turn to the philanthropic impulses of my social network.

Ideally my insurance company will eventually reimburse me for some of the costs associated with bottom surgery, but in the meantime I am on the hook for a considerable portion of the cost, including a $2,000 deductible.

The money generated through this fundraiser will go toward paying for my deductible, as well as other ancillary costs that my insurance company won’t pay for, like hygiene products and other costs associated with my recovery. I am already in the hole ~$800 as I am forced to pay out of pocket for electrolysis hair removal in advance of bottom surgery which is the primary roadblock standing between me and a surgery date. My insurance company is doing everything in its power to slow walk the reimbursement process and it will likely be months before I see that money.

Should I eventually get reimbursed by my insurance company, the funds will be reallocated toward other transition related costs, such as prescriptions, compensating various caretakers for their time and energy, copays, and therapy, among other costs.

I am anticipating actually having bottom surgery at some point in 2021, likely in the summer or early fall. I won’t have a definite surgery date on the schedule for a few more weeks, but will update this fundraiser as the timeline develops.

Any amount helps, and if you can’t contribute sharing on your social networks is greatly appreciated!

Major thanks to @AllyMenthol for help with the thumbnail 🙂

Italian, Stateless Embassies
Ecocidi col Sigillo di Stato

Joseph Parampathu. Originale: How the State Enables Ecocide. Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.

In questo primo anno di quarantena costante, turbato ovunque da disordini sociali, la tropicalizzazione del clima e l’inettitudine diffusa degli stati, è chiara l’incapacità totale, la riluttanza, delle classi di governo ad operare un qualche cambiamento sostanziale. Nessun aiuto per le persone, nessuna remissione dei debiti. La mercificazione degli animali ha creato le condizioni perfette per la mutazione e la diffusione delle malattie zoonotiche, ma le misure per la riduzione del danno adottate con la pandemia offuscano il rischio, l’industria dell’allevamento diventa di “importanza vitale”, necessaria agli interessi economici della classe capitalista. Sacrificate la vostra etica, è arrivato il momento di mettersi sull’altare e offrirsi in dono al mercato; o almeno quel guscio di mercato rappresentato dall’alta finanza.

Visto che affronteremo le conseguenze dell’ecocidio per generazioni, ci chiediamo: finché c’è lo stato, che speranze abbiamo? Quando ai lavoratori si offre l’occasione di assumere il controllo del proprio ambiente e porre fine allo spreco di risorse naturali che produce montagne di rifiuti tossici dietro casa, ecco che interviene lo stato, per proteggere l’interesse del denaro da responsabilità nei confronti della comunità indipendente.

Quando i fumi della fabbrica intasano i polmoni dei tuoi figli, quando la multinazionale ti ruba il diritto all’acqua, quando il conglomerato agricolo avvelena la tua terra, ecco che lo stato fa sì che tu rimanga invischiato in lunghe battaglie legali, in processi legislativi che durano finché non hai più niente da salvare.

Domanda frequente tra gli anarchici: come fermare il cambiamento climatico senza azioni drammatiche, coraggiose? La risposta è che non si può. Lo stato non ha mai fatto azioni drammatiche e coraggiose, e non le farà mai. La classe ricca, nella sua ignoranza, pensa ancora di poter estrarre l’ultimo grammo di ricchezza e squagliarsela. Fantasticano di fughe via dalla terra, pensano di lasciare il pianeta (e voi) in una sorta di colonia al contrario, per continuare ad arricchirsi.

E lo stato non solo li lascia fare, ma li aiuta anche… e con i vostri soldi. Che l’abbiate capito o meno, la classe capitalista sa di essere in guerra con voi. Sono pronti ad usare tutta la forza dello stato per il controllo di ciò che resta delle risorse. Se c’è qualcosa che la pandemia ha portato alla luce, è che sono talmente imbevuti delle loro fantasie di grandeur che non sono disposti a cambiare nulla del loro stile di vita o delle loro strutture sociali per andare oltre il capitalismo. Non c’è alcun passaggio morbido dalla democrazia liberale ad un socialismo democratico. O, perlomeno, se un tempo c’era, ora, a livello pratico, è troppo tardi.

Non c’è alcuna magica tecnologia verde, nessuna pallottola d’argento in grado di fermare l’estinzione di massa. È chiaro che la classe capitalista è pronta ad eliminare voi piuttosto che ridurre il proprio osceno stile di vita. Eliminare lo stato è un passaggio obbligato per indebolire la classe capitalista. Forse un conflitto frontale potrebbe abbattere lo stato, ma l’azione più sovversiva resta l’astensione. Agendo fuori dallo stato, rafforzando attività comunitarie parallele ma autonome si indebolisce il potere dello stato su di noi. Privi di risorse e di lavoratori da sfruttare, lo stato e i suoi padroni capitalisti non hanno più potere. Organizzandoci in modo indipendente per fare quello che lo stato non farà mai, possiamo contrastare l’attuale ecocidio, la catastrofe climatica, direttamente, riorganizzando la comunità e cambiando il nostro rapporto con l’ambiente.

I ricchi, con la loro semplice esistenza, distruggono le risorse naturali con le armi dell’inefficienza e dello sfruttamento. Una comunità che provvede alla propria gestione autonoma ha un’ovvia responsabilità nei confronti delle persone che rappresenta, ha interesse a far sì che le risorse siano disponibili il più a lungo possibile. Cooperare per aiutarsi reciprocamente significa rafforzare il legame in quanto assicura il bene per entrambe le parti. Senza lo stato che fa pendere la bilancia da una parte, al posto di una lotta tra parti che competono per la distruzione della terra per la temporanea gloria dell’accumulazione di capitale avremmo una collaborazione tra persone che agiscono di concerto per un fine che premia tutti. Possiamo ancora fermare la corsa all’ecocidio, ma per farlo dobbiamo decidere come gestire le nostre società, non come interagire con lo stato.

Portuguese, Stateless Embassies
Contra o Sistema Penal, Parte I: Ninguém Jamais Deveria Ser Punido

Jason Lee Byas. Título original: Against the Criminal Justice System, Pt. I: No One Should Ever Be Punished. Traduzido por Gabriel Serpa.

Enquanto toda dor, todo o sofrimento e todos os custos elevados, ocasionados pela justiça criminal, se agravam e fogem do nosso controle, mais e mais pessoas se posicionam em favor de uma reforma deste sistema. Até mesmo o governador do Texas, Rick Perry — que já afirmou, cheio de orgulho, nunca ter se preocupado com questões como a pena de morte —, passou a defender uma redução no número de prisões.

No entanto, mais do que nunca, o que precisamos é de uma medida mais radical do que uma simples reforma do sistema penal: nós devemos extinguir toda e qualquer instituição punitiva e voltada à criação de mais leis penais, incluindo nosso sistema carcerário escravocrata, e substitui-los por um sistema legal baseado na defesa e na restituição.

Cada um destes pontos citados acima requerem um tratamento cuidadoso de suas peculiaridades. Por isso, esta será uma série de escritos — em vez de um monobloco —, e começaremos pelos motivos que deveriam fazer dos libertários ferrenhos opositores do punitivismo.

O libertarismo tem como ponto de partida a noção básica acerca do que é (e do que não é) o uso aceitável da violência. Em situações corriqueiras da vida, tendemos a afirmar que uso de violência só é justificável em legítima defesa, sendo esta limitada pelo princípio da proporcionalidade. Se ao tentar te matar, eu acabo morto por você, pois esta é a única forma que você tem de me impedir e se defender, seu ato é justificável. Se eu pisar no seu pé, você tem todo o direito de me dar um chega pra lá. Entretanto, não é razoável que você me mate, ou que me apague, por um pisão no pé. Se eu furto sua televisão, você pode me forçar a devolvê-la, já que se eu mantiver seus pertences para mim, estarei cometendo um ato lesivo contra você.

Mesmo assim, este princípio de não-agressão está totalmente em desalinho com o punitivismo. Enquanto que proteger e restituir são justificáveis nos casos de violação de direitos — tomar forçosamente dos agressores uma reparação que indenize as vítimas —, o mesmo não se aplica às punições. Elas vão além ao submeterem os transgressores a um novo processo de violência que em nada se relaciona com a defesa da vítima e a restituição de suas perdas. Pelo menos em uma primeira mirada, isto faz do castigo um novo ato de agressão. Assim, para que libertários justifiquem o punitivismo, devem fazê-lo justificando a própria violência.

Dissuasão e Reabilitação

​​Uma maneira comum de se justificar o emprego de punições é pela necessidade da dissuasão. Esta pode se apresentar de duas formas: tanto genérica — punir um criminoso para que outros sejam dissuadidos de cometer o mesmo crime que ele —, quanto específica — punir um criminoso para que ele seja dissuadido de incorrer no mesmo crime futuramente.

Pode-se pensar que os libertários favoráveis ao punitivismo apelariam facilmente às práticas dissuasivas. Afinal, se a autodefesa é uma hipótese legítima para o uso da violência, e o uso da dissuasão potencialmente nos protegeria de uma agressão futura, logo, seria legítimo que medidas dissuasivas fossem empregadas violentamente.

Contudo, desconsidera-se por essa lógica que o emprego da violência só é verdadeiramente defensivo quando para deter uma certa pessoa de cometer uma agressão específica, que de outra forma não seria impedida. Ampliar a noção de defesa ao ponto de incluir a prática da dissuasão nos levaria a conclusões absurdas. A saber, se o uso da violência dissuasiva for justificável, o será também contra inocentes.

No caso da dissuasão genérica, bastaria que o público em geral acreditasse que um suposto criminoso fosse culpado, e não que ele fosse de fato. Isso, porque se uma pessoa é inocente, mas todas as outras não acreditam que ela seja, puni-la ainda terá um efeito dissuasivo. Assim sendo, para que apontemos para a inaceitabilidade desta punição, devemos determinar que a dissuasão genérica não é um caso à parte que justifique o uso da violência.

Já para a dissuasão específica, bastaria que uma punição qualquer detivesse alguém de um suposto crime futuro — não que esse alguém já o tivesse cometido. Imagine um mundo em que as práticas de assustar de antemão (do original, scared-straight) fossem um pouco mais extremas: se alguém pudesse ser encarcerado apenas por haver demonstrado que talvez estivesse prestes a seguir o mau caminho — não que ela tivesse feito algo de errado —, só para que já sentisse um pouco na pele a punição que estaria lhe aguardando. Se essa espécie de prática dissuasiva for legítima, então a hipótese citada acima seria aceitável.

Afirmações semelhantes podem ser aplicadas à reabilitação de presos como forma de punição. Se for legítimo que se aprisione criminosos para regenera-los, então por que não pegar, diretamente das ruas, pessoas que possivelmente cometeriam crimes no futuro para fazer o mesmo?

Justiça Retributiva

Outro problema é que tanto a dissuasão quanto a reabilitação não oferecem as bases para o princípio da proporcionalidade. Isto é, elas não explicam porque a punição deve ser proporcional ao crime, ou o que isso significa. É por essa razão que muitos defensores do punitivismo voltam suas atenções à justiça retributiva. Estes acreditam que é justo infligir ao criminoso o que quer que ele tenha infligido à sua vítima. Um benefício deste sistema retributivo seria seguir as diretrizes da exata proporcionalidade: olho por olho. Desta forma, estariam justificadas as penas excessivas para crimes brutais.

Ao mesmo tempo, se levarmos a sério esta forma de proporcionalidade que o retributivismo nos oferece, chegaremos a conclusões nada diferentes das que nos trouxeram a reabilitação e a dissuasão. Por exemplo, ela não apenas permite, mas obriga que assassinos brutais sejam assassinados brutalmente e de maneiras específicas; que estupradores sejam estuprados; e aqueles que atacam e saqueiam sejam torturados. Se aceitarmos a justiça retributiva, nossa reação a execuções mal-sucedidas (do original, botched executions), que resultam em mortes extremamente dolorosas, não deveria ser de terror, e sim de alívio, já que a justiça teria sido feita.

Voltando para as noções que normalmente nos trazem ao libertarismo, este tipo de proporcionalidade não é do que precisamos. Num caso comum de conflito interpessoal, entendemos a violência apenas como legítima na medida em que é necessária para repelir um ataque, ou para proteger outra pessoa. Se eu tento socar sua cara, você pode bloquear meu soco, me dar uma chave de braço, ou se valer de medidas razoáveis para se defender de mim. O que normalmente não aceitamos é que você me ataque após o término da briga, quando já lhe dei as costas para ir embora. Podemos até entender racionalmente, mas não defendemos moralmente esta prática. Muito menos que ela seja executada diretamente pela justiça. Nossas noções comuns acerca dos conflitos interpessoais são contrárias às retributivas.

Mas Eles Não Podem Se Safar Assim!

Então, se nos livrarmos do punitivismo, isso significa que não faremos nada quando alguém praticar uma agressão? Não, apenas significa que não aplicaremos um castigo. Em vez disso, o infrator é obrigado a restituir ou indenizar a sua vítima, para que se repare os danos que puderem ser reparados. Isso transforma o direito criminal em direito civil. No próximo texto, examinaremos no que consiste essa mudança.

Stigmergy - C4SS Blog
Agoric Cafe: Interview With Sheldon Richman (Part 1)

In episode no. 13 of Agoric Cafe and in Part 1 of this 2-part interview, Roderick Long chats with Sheldon Richman about his youthful enthusiasm for the Swamp Fox and his guerilla fighters; the Constitution as a betrayal of the American Revolution and the Articles of Confederation; defying YAF with Karl Hess at the March to the Arch; the positive externalities achievable by sitting next to Dave Barry; using Koch money to fight big business; Robert Bidinotto’s dark anarchist past; the perils of publishing Kevin Carson; going crazy for Thomas Szasz; the identity of Filthy Pierre; how to smoke like Gandalf; an atheist’s favourite Bishop; and which prominent Austrian economist experimented on Sheldon’s newborn infant. Watch here or below.

Mutual Exchange Radio, Podcast, Stigmergy - C4SS Blog
Mutual Exchange Radio: Aurora Apolito and William Gillis, Part I

This episode is Part I of a two-part interview with Aurora Apolito and William Gillis, two of the lead contributors to our summer symposium on Decentralization and Economic Coordination.

Listen to Part II here. 

Aurora Apolito is a mathematician and theoretical physicist. She studied physics in Italy and mathematics in Chicago, and later worked for various scientific institutions in the US, Canada, and Germany. She also works on mathematical linguistics, and on mathematical models for neuroscience and has authored six books on various aspects of this work. I should also note that Aurora Apolito is a pen name meant to differentiate this research from her work in other fields.

Our other guest is someone most listeners will be familiar with, William Gillis. Will currently acts as technology coordinator at C4SS and was formerly our coordinating director. Will is a second-generation anarchist who’s worked as an activist in countless projects and capacities since getting involved in the lead-up to N30 (also known as the “Battle in Seattle”). Gillis studies high energy physics and has held a deep fascination with the egalitarian potential of markets since 2003. Their writing can be found at C4SS.org and humaniterations.net.

Here are both Will & Aurora’s essays in the summer Symposium: 

Portuguese, Stateless Embassies
Uma Hipótese Anarquista para a Renda Básica Universal

Original: An Anarchist Case for UBI, de Logan Marie Glitterbomb. Traduzido para o Português por Gabriel Serpa.

​A Renda Básica Universal (RBU) tem ganhado os holofotes durante esta corrida eleitoral, graças a Andrew Yang e seus apoiadores. Desde que ele começou sua campanha em favor dela, outros candidatos têm sido questionados sobre a possibilidade de apoiarem esta ideia – e vários têm se mostrado simpáticos, ainda que com ressalvas. Lamentavelmente, alguns, como Bernie Sanders, se posicionaram de maneira cética quanto à RBU e preferiram anunciar medidas como o aumento do salário mínimo e programas federais de emprego. Tais propostas estão enraizadas em concepções econômicas retrógradas e só contribuem para nos acorrentar ao status quo capitalista. Um programa de RBU, por outro lado, nos ofereceria maior liberdade contra a opressão econômica e a burocracia estatal, ao mesmo tempo em que, possivelmente, nos direcionaria a uma situação muito mais vantajosa, economicamente, do que esta em que nos encontramos.

Em primeiro lugar, vamos começar por desconstruir as soluções mais comumente propostas antes de aprofundar nas críticas feitas à RBU. Tradicionalmente, a resposta que se tenta dar aos salários de fome são leis que estabelecem salários mínimos maiores. Eu já escrevi a respeito do lute por $15 (movimento social que reivindica o aumento do salário mínimo para U$15 a hora, nos EUA) e dos porquês de ser mal orientado; e de como estas legislações não passam de uma distração enquanto, efetivamente, são só um paliativo para os nossos problemas, na melhor das hipóteses. Essas leis que se estendem a todos servem apenas para beneficiar alguns trabalhadores – em detrimento de outros, que são jogados para fora do mercado por inúmeros motivos.

Certamente que um programa federal de empregos teria a capacidade de resolver todos esses problemas, não é? Um aumento do salário mínimo teria um efeito positivo caso ninguém fosse tirado do mercado, devido ao programa do governo que garantiria trabalho para todos. E obviamente existem muitas atividades a serem realizadas. A criação de empregos em torno de energia limpa, infraestrutura e setores do tipo proporcionaria mais oportunidades de trabalho, mas seria o suficiente para assegurar trabalho a todos, sem exceção? Com a prevalência dos empregos de fachada (em inglês, bullshit jobs) e a crescente automação, parece bastante improvável que haja emprego produtivo o bastante para que se promova uma garantia universal desta natureza. Assim, as únicas maneiras de se realizá-la seria pela produção em massa, gerando um inevitável excedente de resíduos, ou pela operação ineficiente da produção, exigindo trabalho extra e, consequentemente, produzindo uma pegada de carbono maior; sendo ambas as formas contraproducentes para com as metas ambientais de seus proponentes. Além do mais, ninguém se sente verdadeiramente satisfeito realizando atividades sem sentido – estando ciente disso.

Por que a RBU é uma alternativa melhor? Porque ela auxilia a todos, a despeito da situação de emprego – ou desemprego – de cada um, sem inferir que alguém vale estritamente aquilo que produz, ao mesmo tempo em que compensa aquelas atividades não-remuneradas, como cuidar de casa, criar os filhos e realizar trabalhos comunitários voluntariamente. Entretanto, não faltam detratores e sua miríade de críticas a esta proposta. Algumas são mais dignas de serem levadas em consideração do que outras, mas farei o melhor para rebatê-las com os mais diversos pontos de vista.

As críticas mais comuns à RBU giram em torno da sua estreita relação com o nosso atual modelo de assistência social. Os conservadores temem uma expansão demasiada do estado de bem-estar, amontoando mais este benefício sobre todos os outros, sem que haja cortes de gastos de qualquer sorte; ao passo que os progressistas temem o exato oposto: a RBU poderia ser usada como desculpa para se cortar outros benefícios sociais, sem ser ela própria suficiente para a satisfação de necessidades básicas pessoais – sendo assim uma troca desvantajosa. Ambos os temores são plausíveis: ninguém quer onerar o sistema até o ponto de um eventual colapso, tampouco deseja-se que o cidadão carente saia prejudicado em razão do corte de auxílios que recebe. No entanto, não há razão para nenhum destes temores. A maioria das propostas de RBU sugerem financiá-la ou por meio do estabelecimento de um novo imposto, ou pela realocação dos gastos já existentes em áreas menos relevantes (isto é, gastos militares, gastos com burocracia, etc), ou ainda, mais comumente, uma mistura de ambas as medidas. Portanto, a RBU não se misturaria aos benefícios que já existem, mas seria proposta como uma alternativa a eles.

Como alternativa ao nosso sistema atual de bem-estar, a RBU seria muito menos burocrática e onerosa para se administrar. Hoje, existem mais de setenta programas de assistencialismo. Isto inclui desde o auxílio a locatários, passando pelo vale-refeição, até a assistência médica. Mas estes programas apresentam inúmeros requisitos, exigindo que o candidato se enquadre em tais e quais critérios para que possa receber os benefícios. O problema deste modelo é que ele restringe oportunidades de crescimento individual. Para que alguém se encaixe perfeitamente nos requisitos é preciso que esta pessoa administre sua vida de tal forma que nunca aceite uma proposta para subir na carreira, ou que mantenha suas atividades profissionais totalmente por baixo dos panos, condição esta que também acaba limitando as chances de crescimento no trabalho. Para completar, os benefícios vêm com infinitas restrições. Uma pessoa que receba duzentos dólares mensais de vale-refeição não pode usar este dinehiro para investir em uma eventual oportunidade de negócio, que lhe renderia muito mais que apenas duzentos dólares em alimentação – poderia lhe garantir maior estabilidade dali em diante. Alguém que receba vale-refeição sequer pode usá-lo legalmente para comprar comidas prontas, o que não faz qualquer sentido se considerarmos os desabrigados que recebem este benefício.

Portanto, aglutinar todos esses programas de assistência em apenas um, para o qual todos os cidadãos se qualificam, independentemente de sua renda ou de qualquer outro critério, não apenas permitiria maior mobilidade econômica, mas também lhes ofereceria liberdade na hora de gastar o dinheiro. É certo que isto prejudicaria aqueles que hoje recebem mais em benefícios do que a RBU lhes proporcionaria, no entanto já foi proposta uma solução para este problema. Andrew Yang sugeriu que ao invés de substituirmos completamente um sistema pelo outro, déssemos a opção às pessoas de aderir a um ou a outro sistema. Desta forma, eles não seriam empilhados, uns em cima dos outros, custando uma fortuna para os cofres públicos. Em vez disso, poderiam escolher entre os já conhecidos benefícios, cheios de restrições, ou dinheiro vivo sem quaisquer amarras. Contanto que a RBU fosse estabelecida em um patamar digno, a maioria das pessoas, muito provavelmente, optariam por ela, enquanto o sistema de benefícios cairia em desuso. Conciliar a renda básica universal a outras medidas nas áreas de saúde e educação também pode ser uma boa saída para assegurar que ninguém seja excluído.

Outra grande crítica vinda da esquerda é a de que deveríamos fortalecer nosso poder de negociação, enquanto a RBU serviria mais ao propósito de transformar os cidadãos em meros consumidores passivos. Tal crítica funda-se em um modo de produção cada vez mais ultrapassado. Embora sempre haja trabalho a ser feito, os programas de treinamento e reciclagem de profissionais já se provaram extremamente ineficazes em preparar trabalhadores manuais, sejam eles qualificados ou não, para assumirem cargos que envolvam alta tecnologia, como codificação. Considerando a taxa atual de automação, a ideia de haver propriedades coletivas de trabalhadores dentro do sistema econômico atual parece favorecer que um punhado de capitalistas detenham fábricas totalmente automatizadas, enquanto o restante de nós ficamos desempregados e famintos. É evidente que não são todos os setores industriais que podem ser automatizados assim, mas com a ameaça da automação destituindo trabalhadores de seus postos, focar apenas no poder de negociação serve só aos empregados ainda não familiarizados com a automação. Para todos os outros, restaria torcer para que o poder de negociação daqueles trabalhadores fosse usado em benefício de toda a classe operária (incluindo os desempregados), e não apenas deles próprios e de seus colegas.

Mas a noção de que a RBU não oferece um incremento na capacidade de negociar do trabalhador é de todo falsa. A principal razão para que muitas pessoas optem por não se sindicalizarem é o medo de perderem seus empregos, como forma de retaliação. Este medo poderia ser atenuado pela renda básica universal, que permitiria às pessoas atenderem a suas necessidades mais imediatas. Isto significaria maior liberdade para a classe trabalhadora do que ela jamais teve. E para aqueles que não desejassem se submeter a um patrão, seria possível que juntassem suas RBUs e se organizassem em cooperativas, propriedades coletivas e parcerias colaborativas. Com um movimento trabalhista recém-alforriado e uma nova base de capital, os trabalhadores estariam menos sujeitos aos desmandos de seus patrões e mais livres para seguir seus desejos – como jamais conseguirão sob o nosso modelo econômico atual.

Por fim, a RBU tem sido criticada por retirar o incentivo das pessoas de trabalhar. Enquanto ela atenua os aspectos coercitivos do trabalho – já que permite que você atenda a suas necessidades básicas e não se veja em um dilema entre trabalhar ou morrer –, isto não pode ser visto como algo ruim. Tal coerção é totalmente dispensável. Implementar uma RBU facilitaria a tarefa de livrar o mercado dos empregos de mentira e na busca por atividades mais significantes. As pessoas seguirão trabalhando na solução de problemas em suas comunidades, por sermos seres gregários e por isso gerar melhorias em nossas vidas; as pessoas farão tudo que for necessário para garantir sua própria sobrevivência e de seus entes queridos e, na condição de seres comunitários, sabemos que é menos custoso sobreviver coletivamente. Na realidade, havendo menos pessoas que dediquem seu tempo a empregos de faz de conta, teremos mais gente concentrando esforços naquilo que realmente importa. Mais pessoas se sentirão inspiradas para criar novas tecnologias, como comprovam as iniciativas adeptas do código aberto. Estas coisas não acontecem pela coerção, mas pelo interesse que temos nelas e pelo prazer que extraímos disso. E certamente testemunharemos uma grande mudança em toda produção de massa; em vez de bens sem sentido, o foco estará em itens de primeira necessidade, no conforto e no luxo, e na produção artística. Livres do dilema coercitivo entre trabalhar e morrer de fome, os bens e serviços que valoramos influenciarão na oferta e na demanda, de modo que o mercado há de corresponder naturalmente a isso. Em outras palavras, um mercado livre de coerção tenderá a uma leitura mais precisa das conjunturas e funcionará melhor. Afinal, quanto mais livre é o mercado, mais livre é o povo.​

Assim sendo, a RBU nos oferece os meios para encolher o estado de bem-estar social (possivelmente o orçamento militar e outros setores inchados também), concede aos trabalhadores maior autonomia e poder de negociação e ainda nos aproxima mais de um mercado livre. Este pode não ser o seu objetivo final, mas é uma ferramenta útil de transição da qual dispomos aqui e agora. É uma proposta que não deve gerar desconforto em nenhum anarquista que venha a defendê-la.

Italian, Stateless Embassies
Riprendere Internet Creando internet con la Minuscola

Tech Learning Collective. Originale: How we can win back the Internet by creating lowercase internets, 11 novembre 2020. Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.

Ad aprile del 2001, cinque mesi prima dell’undici settembre, Bram Cohen mise a punto un protocollo di condivisione dei file che, di per sé, cambiò l’industria discografica, televisiva e cinematografica del ventennio seguente. La tecnologia in sé non era una novità assoluta. Altre tecnologie, come il file transfer protocol (ftp), usato per trasferire file tra computer, esistevano già. Ciò che rendeva così potente questo protocollo era il fatto che rifletteva la struttura spontanea frammentata del mezzo sottostante: Internet.

Invece di considerare il file una unità indivisibile, questa nuova tecnologia lo divideva in tanti pezzi, di dimensioni simili, e trattava ogni pezzo individualmente. A differenza di altre tecnologie come l’ftp, questa nuova tecnologia “peer-to-peer” poteva recuperare i singoli pezzi da chiunque li possedesse, anche se questi non avevano il file intero, come richiesto dai server tradizionali.

La nuova tecnologia fu chiamata BitTorrent, e il suo sistema di trasferimento a pezzi è ancora oggi il tormento delle industrie che vivono di copyright come l’industria discografica e la cinematografica. Il successo di BitTorrent è dovuto al fatto che riflette la natura decentrata della rete in cui si sviluppa, ovvero Internet. BitTorrent e Internet sono tecnologie che non richiedono particolari permessi o attrezzature per connettersi, condividere o ricondividere. Basta un computer con un sistema operativo e un software TCP/IP istallato, un qualunque moderno Windows, Mac o GNU/Linux, per estendere Internet. Basta collegare il computer ad un altro computer già connesso.

C’è ancora qualcosa da imparare a vent’anni dal successo di BitTorrent? Se vogliamo accettare la libertà “offerta da Internet”, immaginata allora con ottimismo, dobbiamo (re)imparare un’importante lezione: Internet è un fatto tangenziale. Noi dobbiamo creare un internet.

Internet, con la maiuscola, è il nome di una particolare rete. Internet “ospita” computer con nomi come Google, Facebook e il Wall Street Journal. La parola internet, con la minuscola, indica invece una qualunque rete di reti interconnesse. L’internet può ospitare qualunque cosa.

È importantissimo distinguere. Per connettere il proprio computer a Internet bisogna sborsare denaro ad una società come Comcast, Verizon o Rogers. Oltre a questo, però, ci sono anche tanti internet a cui ci si può connettere gratis, come Guifi in Spagna o NYCMesh a New York. A differenza di quanto accade con Internet, ognuno può creare un proprio internet per conto proprio, magari connettendolo ad un qualunque altro internet disposto a connettersi a sua volta.

Prima di diventare Internet, era semplicemente internet. Per riappropriarci di Internet, strappandolo alle forze che soffocano la libertà online, dobbiamo puntare a edificare nuovi internet: dobbiamo fare a pezzi Internet e il modo in cui è concepito, come fa BitTorrent che segmenta i file per farne uno nuovo grazie alla collaborazione. Così facendo abbatteremo quella quota di mercato, e metaforicamente anche di cervello, che i monopoli hanno acquisito.

Sembrerebbe una fatica immane, ma gran parte del lavoro è già fatto. Le risorse, in termini di costi e strumenti, sono minime e sempre più diffuse. Non c’è bisogno di scrivere aggiungere righe di codice o fare nuove applicazioni. Abbiamo tutte le risorse che servono. Ciò che manca è l’impegno diffuso dei vicini o della comunità.

Cosa serve per creare un internet? Computer, ovviamente, ma non particolarmente potenti o costosi. Come dice Homebrew Server Club, “un portatile può diventare un buon server casalingo, dato che è alla portata di tutti, relativamente potente e consuma poco.” Accendiamo due portatili connessi tra loro con un normale cavo Ethernet (RJ-45) e abbiamo un primo abbozzo di internet. Aggiungiamo un terzo portatile, o magari un Raspberry Pi, e si può già gestire un servizio dedicato, come un sito web, un indirizzario condiviso o un’agenda elettronica. Si può anche creare una piccola connessione wi-fi per passanti (magari il nostro mini internet è in un infoshop), tutto senza connettersi ad Internet vero e proprio.

Dopodiché serve immaginazione. Questo primo internet magari è piccolo, ma può crescere, così come il primo internet è cresciuto fino a diventare l’Internet che conosciamo oggi. Si pubblica un sito di poesia rivoluzionaria come parte di una collezione di libri digitali (è un infoshop, dopotutto) e qualche vicino sensibile gli dà più di un’occhiata. Aggiungi un altro cavo Ethernet e collega il computer, non servono carte di credito.

Esistono già molti internet del genere. Abbiamo detto di Guifi in Spagna e NYCMesh a New York, ma ci sono anche internet di quartiere che offrono servizi locali allo stesso modo. Alcuni, come NYCMesh, sono anche connessi a Internet, così che oltre ad un servizio esclusivamente locale offrono anche l’accesso al tradizionale Internet. Un sistema del genere è come la rete wi-fi che connette assieme diversi computer in una casa: si paga per una sola connessione, ma a quella connessione possono essere collegati centinaia di computer, o più, simultaneamente.

Tecnologie di internet come BitTorrent si basano sul principio per cui singoli segmenti, ognuno con un suo indirizzo individuale, possono essere uniti fino a formare nuovamente il file originario. Né il sistema di trasferimento di file di Internet né BitTorrent è un tutt’uno monolitico. Questo significa che non occorre chiedere il permesso a qualcuno o a qualche azienda, né servono licenze o prodotti commerciali per creare il proprio servizio, connetterli ad altri pari e offrire qualcosa di utile. È tempo che smettiamo di pagare per connetterci e cominciamo a mettere su il mondo in cui vogliamo vivere.

E se uno vive lontano dall’infoshop estremista citato prima? Creare nuovi internet non è un aut-aut, né un gioco a somma zero. Gli internet fisicamente distanti tra loro possono sfruttare la connessione Internet con la maiuscola per formare una rete tra loro utilizzando tecnologie di rete come il Virtual Private Network (VPN) e/o Tor (servizio Onion). È proprio così che reti separate di comunità o gestite in cooperativa, come quelle citate, vengono ricollegate tra loro. Basta connettere un certo numero di internet – ovvero, aggiungi un altro cavo Ethernet all’edificio accanto, e poi all’altro, e all’altro ancora – ed ecco un nuovo “Internet” che fa concorrenza a quello attuale. Con l’eccezione che questo è nostro e l’accesso non è a pagamento.

Il flusso di dati attraverso le linee telefoniche è molto simile a quello dell’elettricità in un filo o dell’acqua in un tubo, non solo meccanicamente ma anche in termini di dipendenza dall’uomo. La rete elettrica non esisterebbe senza elettricisti. In casa non ci sarebbe l’acqua corrente senza un buon idraulico. Per creare e tenere in funzione un insieme di internet indipendenti come quelli descritti servono amministratori e tecnici di rete, non programmatori, code bootcamp o novità Big Tech. Anzi, è proprio l’autonomia di queste infrastrutture, come le reti di cavi, il primo passo da fare per riprendere possesso di Internet togliendolo dalle mani dei padroni aziendali e governativi. Insomma, ci sono troppi programmatori e pochi amministratori di sistema perché le aziende capitaliste hanno bisogno di programmatori, mentre gli amministratori di sistema servono a mettere su una comunità rivoluzionaria per un futuro giusto ed equo.

È per questo che istituzioni didattiche radicali come Tech Learning Collective puntano più sulle infrastrutture che sul codice, così che gli studenti possano apprendere quelle fondamentali capacità di fare internet spesso trascurate dai programmi che puntano al posto di lavoro subito propri del binomio scuola-azienda. Ed è per questo che anche progetti come Shift-CTRL Space Library, che offrono collezioni preconfezionate di software per la condivisione facile di libri digitali (pdf, riviste e altro), si basano su software libero ampiamente disponibile a discapito della tradizionale offerta di Internet con la maiuscola.

Possediamo già la forza, gli strumenti e la voglia di lottare per riprenderci Internet. Ma non possiamo cominciare dall’ultimo passo che consiste nel fare (ancora più) “nuove” applicazioni. Dobbiamo cominciare dal primo passo: il possesso di un’infrastruttura.

Stigmergy - C4SS Blog
Virtual Reading Group: Individualist Anarchism in 19th Century America

Tuckered Out? Feeling Greene? Get a Spoonerful of de Cleyrification here!

So says Roderick T. Long! Coming up in January, he’ll be hosting a virtual reading group together with Cory Massimino on individualist anarchism in 19th-century America.

As you might guess from the tagline, they’ll be covering the big names in the American individualist tradition, folks like Benjamin Tucker, Lysander Spooner, and Voltairine de Cleyre. Here’s the full intro video from the Agoric Cafe YouTube channel: 

The application deadline is January 12th, and sessions are tentatively scheduled for Tuesday evenings, starting January 19th. You can find more details and the application form here.

Stigmergy - C4SS Blog
Agoric Cafe: Interview With James Bradley

In episode no. 12 of Agoric Cafe, Roderick Long chats with biologist James T. Bradley about the future of, and ethical issues surrounding, biotechnology and nanotechnology; global and civic responsibilities of scientists and of laypeople; intimations of immortality from William Godwin to Ray Kurzweil; the importance of interdisciplinary education, and of instruction in evolutionary biology; the 15th-century (trans)humanism of Giovanni Pico della Mirandola, and the perils of invoking the Pope; Bradley’s three-week plan for solving a pandemic; the potential parallels between central planning for sociopolitical systems and central planning for ecosystems; the cosmological theories of Crosby, Stills, Nash, and Young; that time the National Science Foundation awarded Bradley and Long a $200,000 grant (but they had to spend it all on, like, course stuff); how the universe uses stardust to become self-conscious; and the waning allure of cricket ovaries. Watch here or below.

Portuguese, Stateless Embassies
Como podemos reconquistar a Internet criando internets em letra minúscula

Tech Learning Collective. Original: How we can win back the Internet by creating lowercase internets. Traduzido para o português por Iann Zorkot.

Em abril de 2001, cinco meses antes do 11 de setembro, Bram Cohen começou a projetar um novo protocolo de compartilhamento de arquivos que mudaria quase sozinho a face das indústrias de música, TV e cinema nas próximas duas décadas. A tecnologia em si não era uma ideia completamente nova. Afinal, tecnologias semelhantes, como o conhecido File Transfer Protocol (FTP), já haviam sido projetadas e implantadas para copiar arquivos entre computadores. O que o tornou tão potente foi a maneira como ele refletiu a estrutura orgânica fraturada de seu meio subjacente, a própria Internet.

Em vez de tratar cada arquivo como um único todo indivisível, essa nova tecnologia separou cada arquivo em um conjunto de peças de tamanhos semelhantes e tratou cada peça independentemente de qualquer outra. Ao contrário das tecnologias cliente-servidor anteriores, como o FTP, esta nova tecnologia “ponto a ponto” poderia recuperar qualquer parte do todo de qualquer outro ponto que já tivesse uma cópia dessa parte, mesmo que esse ponto não tivesse todas as partes como um servidor tradicional faria.

Essa nova tecnologia foi chamada de BitTorrent, e sua tecnologia de transferência de arquivos segmentados é, até hoje, a ruína de guardiões corporativos como a Record Industry Association of America (RIAA) e a Motion Picture Association of America (MPAA). O BitTorrent teve sucesso porque espelhou a natureza descentralizada da rede na qual foi implantado, a Internet. O BitTorrent e a Internet são tecnologias que não requerem nenhuma permissão especial ou produto para se conectar, interoperar ou estender. Se você tiver um computador executando um sistema operacional com uma pilha de software TCP / IP instalada, como qualquer Windows, macOS ou distribuições GNU / Linux modernos, poderá ampliar a Internet. Tudo o que você precisa fazer é conectar seu computador a outro computador já pré-conectado a ela.

Ainda podemos aprender com o sucesso do BitTorrent vinte anos depois? Se quisermos aceitar a “oferta de liberdade da Internet”, como previsto por gerações anteriores otimistas, devemos (re) aprender esta lição vital: a Internet é tangencial. Precisamos apenas criar uma internet.

A Internet (com I maiúsculo) é o nome de uma rede específica. A Internet “hospeda” computadores com nomes como Google, Facebook e Wall Street Journal. Em contraste, a palavra internet (com i minúsculo) descreve qualquer rede de redes interconectadas. Uma internet pode hospedar tudo.

Essa distinção é absolutamente crítica. Para conectar seu computador à Internet, você deve desembolsar moeda fiduciária para uma empresa como a Comcast, Verizon ou Rogers. Existem, no entanto, muitas internet às quais você pode se conectar gratuitamente, como o Guifi na Espanha ou o NYCMesh aqui na cidade de Nova York. Ao contrário da Internet, você pode até criar uma nova internet por conta própria, opcionalmente conectando-a a qualquer outra internet que deseje e possa se conectar a você.

Antes da Internet ser A Internet, ela era simplesmente uma internet. Para reconquistar a Internet das forças da industrialização que sufocam a promessa de liberdade online, devemos nos concentrar primeiro na construção de novas internets: devemos quebrar a Internet e nosso entendimento dela em pedaços, assim como os arquivos segmentados do BitTorrent, para que possamos colaborativamente reconstruí-la e, no processo, ameaçar o literal percentual de mercado e o metafórico percentual de mentes que esses monopólios atualmente têm sobre nós.

O que é preciso para construir uma internet? Precisamos de computadores, é claro, mas não especialmente poderosos ou caros. Como o Homebrew Server Club explica, “laptops pessoais são bons servidores caseiros, pois estão amplamente disponíveis, são relativamente poderosos e economizam energia”. Conecte dois laptops usando um cabo Ethernet comum (RJ-45) e você terá o início de uma internet. Adicione um terceiro laptop, ou talvez um Raspberry Pi, e você poderá executar um serviço dedicado, como um site da Web ou um catálogo de endereços ou calendário compartilhado. Você pode até criar uma conexão Wi-Fi para clientes em roaming (talvez sua nova internet minúscula esteja em um infoshop*), tudo sem nunca se conectar à Internet propriamente.

Em seguida, precisamos de imaginação. Sua internet pode ser pequena agora, mas pode crescer, assim como a internet original cresceu e se tornou A Internet que conhecemos hoje. Talvez você publique um site de poesia de resistência como parte de uma coleção de e-books (afinal, você está em um infoshop) e seus vizinhos despertos também queiram navegar pela coleção. Obtenha outro cabo Ethernet e conecte-os, sem necessidade de cartão de crédito.

Já existem internets como essas. Mencionamos o Guifi na Espanha e o NYC Mesh na cidade de Nova York, mas também há bolsões menores de internets em escala de bairro que oferecem serviços locais exatamente dessa maneira. Alguns até mesmo se conectam de volta à Internet (como o NYCMesh faz), para que possam oferecer simultaneamente serviços apenas locais, bem como acesso à Internet mais tradicional. Uma maneira de pensar sobre esses bolsões de computadores interconectados é a mesma que você pensaria sobre os vários computadores conectados à rede Wi-Fi em sua casa: você só paga por uma conexão, mas pode conectar centenas, se não mais, computadores naquela conexão ao mesmo tempo.

As tecnologias de interligação de redes, como o BitTorrent, são construídas na noção de partes menores, cada uma delas segmentos endereçáveis individualmente, que podem ser compostas juntas para criar um todo maior. Nem a Internet nem as transferências de arquivos BitTorrent são monólitos de fato. Isso significa que não precisamos da permissão de qualquer pessoa ou empresa, chave de licença ou produto comercial para criar o nosso próprio, para interconectá-los aos nossos pares e para executar e manter serviços úteis para eles. Já passou da hora de pararmos de pedir ou pagar pela permissão para construir o mundo em que queremos viver.

E se você morar longe do infoshop radical do nosso exemplo acima? Acontece que criar novas internets não é uma dicotomia, nem um jogo de soma zero. As internets que estão fisicamente distantes uma da outra ainda podem pegar carona com segurança em uma conexão de Internet – com I maiúsculo – existente para se unir usando as tecnologias de rede Virtual Private Network (VPN) e / ou Tor (serviço Onion). Novamente, é exatamente assim que partes fisicamente desarticuladas de redes pertencentes à comunidade e operadas de forma cooperativa, como aquelas que mencionamos anteriormente, são reconectadas. Una um número suficiente de internets operadas individualmente – isto é, passe outro cabo Ethernet para o próximo prédio, e o próximo, e o próximo – e teremos uma “Internet” recém-criada para rivalizar com a atual. Exceto que, desta vez, nós a possuiremos completamente, em vez de alugar o acesso a ela.

O fluxo de dados por links de telecomunicações é muito parecido com o fluxo de eletricidade por um fio ou água por um cano, não apenas em sua mecânica técnica, mas também em suas dependências humanas. A rede elétrica não poderia existir sem eletricistas. Água corrente em seu apartamento não seria possível sem encanadores competentes. Administradores de sistemas e engenheiros de rede - não programadores, bootcamps de código ou iniciativas de diversidade Big Tech – são necessários para criar e manter internets independentes como descrevemos aqui. Além disso, são esses componentes mais infraestruturais da autonomia das telecomunicações os primeiros pré-requisitos que devemos tomar para reconquistar a Internet de seus senhores corporativos e governamentais. Dito de outra forma, há muitos programadores mas não administradores de sistemas o suficiente, precisamente porque mais programadores são o que as corporações precisam no capitalismo, mas mais administradores de sistemas são o que as comunidades revolucionárias precisam para um futuro justo e equitativo.

É por isso que os esforços radicais de educação em tecnologia, como os do Tech Learning Collective, se concentram na infraestrutura em vez do código, onde os alunos aprendem habilidades de interligação de redes fundamentais esquecidas pelos “programas de corrida ao emprego” de várias “escolas de preparação para a corporação”. É por isso que projetos como a Shift-CTRL Space Library, que oferece uma coleção pré-empacotada de software para compartilhar mais facilmente coleções de e-books (PDFs, zines e mais), são construídos usando Software Livre amplamente disponível e independente de acesso à Internet – com I maiúsculo – como é tradicionalmente.

Já temos o poder, os materiais e o motivo para lutar e reconquistar a Internet. Mas não podemos começar pela última etapa, a construção de (ainda mais) aplicativos “novos”. Temos que começar com a primeira etapa primeiro: possuir nossa própria infraestrutura.

Nota do Tradutor:

* Infoshop é uma vitrina, banca ou centro social que serve como ponto de distribuição de informação anarquista, tipicamente na forma de livros, zines, adesivos e cartazes. Infoshops também servem como espaços de encontro e distribuição de recursos para grupos ativistas locais (Fonte: Wikipedia).

Commentary
Political Intellectuals Discouraging Political Intellect

Many intellectuals[1] lament the supposed apathy, stupidity, or ignorance of the average person. Some start from a charitable idea: e.g., people don’t care about issues of greater political implication for rational (economic) reasons. However, an end point for many is to conclude that it’s better if the idiots around them don’t engage in political activities — those with less-informed opinions are a burden to political processes because they don’t understand the policy issues at play. Those who fancy themselves politically learned tend to chart (what they view as) the wrong, mistaken, and insufficient opinions of others as just that and go no further. What they miss are the positive tendencies of inquiry that can be engaged with and built upon. By not constructively engaging with these tendencies, intellectuals become the enemy of their own standards by taking approaches to political discussion which actively discourage others from improving their thinking. This elitism isn’t helping anyone.

Thankfully, it does seem that many, if not most, people do think it desirable if the issues that come with living in communities and under the regime of a state are not completely ignored or pushed to the side. In the face of conversations, which can be seen as opportunities for sympathetic thought, it seems natural for people to take an interest in the facts of life beyond their narrowest sense of self-interest or personal activities — if not from a position of intricate principles, at least from some basic tenets of human solidarity and mutual respect. Make no mistake, some sort of pure form of altruism is not what I am describing here. Adam Smith’s insight on pursuing and improving your own affairs as a course of action which overlaps with the general good comes to mind. Understood properly, this concept goes beyond the implications of a businessperson seeking profit: those who engage in public affairs  to improve conditions within their own interest can end up doing things that benefit many others.

True, a major factor discouraging many from putting more time into political awareness or activity is the very real question of return on investment. For instance, many economists rightly point out that, at a purely individual level, the costs involved in obtaining the information and knowledge required to make your vote[2] a truly informed and confident contribution to the democratic process are not outweighed by the benefits — one vote will almost never sway an election result, and the policy research required to be truly informed is not a small amount. Having virtually no control over the issues and structures that affect you is a depressing thought, to say the least. Being voiceless against classes and groups that influence important economic and social outcomes is a reality most understand already. This fact, consciously or subconsciously understood by most, is a large contributor to a sense of political helplessness for many living in “free” societies. 

Yet, many people still care about the world’s problems even if they don’t have the tools to deal with them on their own, or feel that their voice is small in comparison to the injustices they see. Better yet, most seem to understand that increasing awareness or inciting action on a particular issue is achievable when people join together to form stronger voices or systems of support. This flame is thankfully very hard to extinguish in most people. Every day, I find admiration for the passion and concern of those who are politically aware or active, and this is especially impressive in contexts much less privileged than many of us enjoy in the west. Most have strong opinions on issues they believe in and feel that if their point of view was shared by others universally, it would make the world a better place.

There are exceptions, of course. Not everyone believes one thing or another for the sake of “good,” and evil does exist. However, more often than not, even those I disagree with sharply (or find to have reprehensible opinions or recommendations on a given issue) never fail in one way: At some level their voice is coming from their perception of justice and a yearning for more of it. No matter how misguided one might think another is, you don’t find many people calling for a more unjust world.

All of this is why it’s so disappointing to see many intellectuals (be they academics or self-taught thinkers on a subject) so often display frustration and dismissiveness against levels of political understanding and knowledge below their own, or at those who hold opinions that are — in their view — clearly wrong. We can probably all think of examples here, be it the self-proclaimed capitalist libertarian who has a good laugh at people who honestly think raising the minimum wage will improve the living standards of workers, or anyone who thinks today’s discourse on social justice is simply about sheltering people’s feelings from criticism. Ultimately, whether it’s their modus operandi or simply their more cynical side on display for an instance or two, you can find many thinkers begrudging: mainstream public sentiments for simply existing; universities or disciplines they view as teaching widely accepted yet wrong truths; people voicing opinions on issues when they are so clearly understudied; and so on. Intellectuals may intellectualize these feelings in their essays, books, and conversations, but it becomes clear to anyone who spends more than a few minutes with certain ones that many are just expressing frustration with the “others” who don’t think the way they do — or perhaps even bother to think differently at all. Beneath it all is a raw and not-very-novel form of cynicism for what they view as the stupidity, ignorance, and lack of thoughtfulness of the average person.

That could be the beginning and end of it, but many take their attitude further and treat others as unchanging, static, and ignorant elements in a universe set against them, instead of dynamic people acquiring different bits of knowledge every day that lead them to their own conclusions. By giving into the temptation to think of others this way, intellectuals turn their nose up at those who are simply at one point in their personal journey of critical thinking and knowledge. In this way, intellectuals often miss something very important about people who are (in their view) wrong, misguided, misinformed, or uneducated in one area: They are still displaying an interest or concern on a topic or an eagerness to continue a conversation and explore an issue. In other words, they at least care enough to voice an opinion or engage on the issue because they feel it’s important enough to say something about.

When dealing with others, intellectuals should acknowledge that they enjoy an extremely privileged and fortunate situation. Some of them, at the very least, have opinions actively sought by others to be written down and then paid for. Others are quite literally paid to think as a career, so they publish and teach their area of study, and sometimes are credited with enough trust to teach and speak beyond their area of expertise. A little humility for this fact, along with a reminder that job markets don’t always get who they compensate right or perfect, would do well for those who are tempted to feel superior or display frustration at others they feel simply don’t get it. 

Many lament that “most” people are on the lower rungs of a given ladder of knowledge and familiarity with a subject without at all celebrating that people are at least somewhere on it. Every intellectual started somewhere and by knowing less than they know now. What they had, at least, was a desire to learn more about the world, or some inclination to ask questions and concern themselves with particular issues — the same as every other ignorant-but-curious individual. Unfortunately, constant exposure to your own normal environments and likeminded individuals — whether it be academia or just the groups of friends you surround yourself with that share your supposed level of sophistication or concern on a specific topic — begins to build dead truths into your mind about the world around you, and about your place or degree of superiority in it. It’s too easy for this to inadvertently create a lower tolerance for different opinions or those less learned than you — no matter how much you sell yourself on the idea of your own tolerance and openness. 

The easy thing to do is to comfort oneself with the idea that people don’t have the incentive, or are too stupid, to grasp the bigger issues and form a more sophisticated opinion (like yours, of course). One can certainly post a couple of social posts, share a couple of essays, or even publish a whole book about something and spend the rest of one’s time explaining why everyone else who doesn’t agree with it is dumb. Perhaps that will get people thinking about it and maybe convince some. However, the harder (and perhaps more honorable) way of approaching these topics is found in discussion, teaching, sharing, sympathy, and patience.

I once saw someone I have some degree of respect for on social media — in response to a question put to them on “why XYZ isn’t something more people know more about”— offer a frank explanation: “Because most people are stupid.” That is certainly one way to view things, and certainly not a cosmically impossible state of reality. However, taking a careful look around ourselves makes it fairly easy to see that many are concerned for a wide variety of issues, even if they don’t start by being on the same page — or using the same lingo — as others more studied in the topic. For example, a welder unfamiliar with political terms may have better ideas on much-needed improvements to safety practices and standards in welding, but will come to the discussion differently than someone arriving at it from an outsider’s perspective on the existing set of rules or regulations. In this case, it’s not just the welder’s willingness to discuss the topic and concern that makes it worth engaging with them. They may actually have more knowledge on some of these issues than others, even if  at first glance it’s illegible to the broader discussions about political systems and structures.

Ultimately, some will not have as much time or resources to dedicate to certain issues as others, and many perhaps haven’t found their way to what are widely viewed (in some circles) as the “correct answers.” But, that doesn’t mean the overall cause is lost or that these people should be dismissed — it just means more work needs to be done.

Those who continually remind themselves about how they get it and that others don’t are contributing to the very thing that frustrates them, and are adding to a culture of toxicity that certainly can’t claim the encouragement of higher understanding in a courteous dialogue as a goal. One can, at a base level, assume others do care and share similar concerns, but perhaps haven’t found the time to flesh out higher quality or more informed opinions on the topic. And, if what certain people are really lacking is a forum for honest conversation, engagement, and sympathy on a topic, why wouldn’t that be worth contributing to? That is, of course, assuming one is sincerely dedicated to a cause beyond one’s own ego, as so many who use venom claim they are.

[1] To be absolutely clear: An “intellectual” for the purposes of this essay is anyone who engages (or attempts to engage) in deeper critical thinking, reflection, research, and study on the topic. The term does not necessarily mean people who are formally employed or engaged in political activities or positions related to political thinking (e.g., a university professor).

[2] Note that a single vote to many is often used by many as a representation of the ultimate, or only serious, form of participation in democracy, and this severely limits one’s conception of what democracy is. I think this view is wrong and problematic, but it is not a subject appropriate to take up here.

Anarchy and Democracy
Fighting Fascism
Markets Not Capitalism
The Anatomy of Escape
Organization Theory