Commentary
“Bad Precedents” Are in the Eye of the Beholder

On September 28 the U.S. Senate voted to override President Obama’s veto of a bill permitting American citizens to sue foreign governments for any role in terrorist attacks. Obama warned that the law would have unintended consequences, setting a “dangerous precedent” for other countries. The United States government, he warned, might face lawsuits by foreign countries for its military and intelligence operations overseas, and open U.S.troops and ambassadors to the threat of lawsuits. The bill’s erosion of sovereign immunity might enable “second-guessing our counter-terrorism operations and other actions that we take every day.” And Obama’s Democratic supporters in the commentariat — despite the antiwar noises they make when Republicans are in the Oval Office — have predictably rallied against the override. But in fact this “dangerous precedent” is a good one.

No doubt the vote by the GOP-dominated house was, as Obama accused, politically motivated. It was a way of scoring demagogic points against an officially Islamic regime. And it’s quite unlikely the bill’s sponsors intended to open the sainted Troops and intelligence officials to foreign lawsuits. But the fact of the matter is, the U.S. government’s military and intelligence operations overseas are overwhelmingly in the service of evil. Just limiting ourselves to the period since WWII, the United States has racked up a death toll of untold millions — probably the tens of millions, as a result not only of its own direct military invasions of other countries — but by sponsoring military coups, propping up fascist dictatorships, and funding, arming and training terrorist death squads. America, in total, has probably overthrown and installed more governments than any other empire in history. And this unprecedented war on humanity has been overwhelmingly for the sake of propping up a global political and economic order in which predominantly Western-owned corporations maintain their ownership of stolen land and natural resources, retain monopoly control over supply and distribution chains, and relegate the people of the Global South to supplying sweatshop labor.

Virtually every war the United States has fought overseas has been criminal, and every American President, Secretary of State or other high-ranking “national security” official has been implicated in crimes against humanity in the service of global corporate rule.

For centuries, there has been a legal fiction that murders, brutalizations and robberies carried out as “matters of state” are subject to a different set of standards from those committed by ordinary criminals. This legal fiction needs to end. Every living American President, along with criminal accomplices like Henry Kissinger, Dick Cheney, Paul Wolfowitz and Hillary Clinton, needs to be afraid to set foot outside the United States for fear of being seized and put on trial. The serpents’ nests in U.S. Embassies and CIA Stations abroad need to fear being shut down and put on trial for conspiring against the people of Guatemala, Vietnam, Congo, Indonesia, Brazil, Chile and too many other countries to count. Torturers at Gitmo and Abu Ghraib, and the entire U.S. military chain of command involved in murdering innocent civilians from top to bottom, need to be criminally and civilly liable.

States, in their essence, are criminal. They are the means by which economic ruling classes murder, enslave, rob and terrorize humanity in order to extract surplus labor and live off our sweat and blood. And their crimes are no different morally from those of the ordinary murderer and robber on the street, except in terms of their monstrous scale. I believe C.S. Lewis said the worst criminals in human history have had tailored suits, manicured fingernails and well-modulated voices, and sat behind desks in tastefully appointed offices. It’s time that they were treated as the criminals they are.

Stigmergy - C4SS Blog, Weekly Libertarian Leftist Review
The Weekly Libertarian Leftist Review 140

Sheldon Richman discusses trade as a labor saving device.

Paul Buhle discusses the Vietnam War.

Renee Parsons discusses justice for the victims of 9-11 vs U.S. support for Saudi Arabia.

Peter Van Buren discusses the world his daughter will inherit.

Ann Wright discusses the environmental destruction wrought by the U.S. military.

Robert Fantina discusses Bibi, ethnic cleansing, and Palestine.

Ron Jacobs discusses U.S. war resisters who fled to Canada.

Ann Garrison discusses a U.S. backed genocide.

Jacob G. Hornberger discusses U.S. support for military rule.

Glenn Greenwald discusses the Washington Post’s editorial team’s switch on Snowden.

Anthony Romero discusses why Obama should pardon Snowden.

Paul R. Pillar discusses how our hardliners are helping Iran’s hardliners.

Barton Gellman discusses a report on Edward Snowden.

Peter Maass discusses why Obama should pardon Snowden, Manning, and other leakers.

Ramzy Baroud discusses ending the war in Syria.

Jacob G. Hornberger discusses interventionism in the Middle East and the consequences.

Richard M. Ebeling discusses the ancient Greeks and economics.

Rev. William Alberts discusses the 21st century’s worst war crime.

Kevin Carson discusses deprogramming from the cult of national unity.

W.T. Whitney discusses the U.S. govt and Colombian paramiliarties.

David D. S’Amato discusses Adam Smith, class analysis, and the left-right divide.

Jeremy R. Hammond discusses his top ten reasons why anti=Palestine libertarians piss him off.

Eric Schuler discusses why both Trump and Clinton’s proposals for dealing with terrorism fail.

Tom Engelhardt discusses American foreign policy woes.

Robert Koehler discusses why stop the killing is the path to peace in Syria.

Doug Bandow discusses NATO expansion.

Paul R. Pillar discusses why the U.S. shouldn’t emulate Russia in Syria.

Uri Avnery discusses Shimon Peres.

Christopher A. Preble discusses American politics and fear.

Peter Van Buren discusses the failure to catch terrorists and a solution.

Commentary
The Anarchist’s Dilemma

Last week, the New York Times published their endorsement for President. Unsurprisingly, the “Paper of Record” endorsed Democratic nominee Hillary Clinton over Republican nominee Donald Trump. It is almost impossible to imagine a world where the New York Times – a paper with liberal values and a history of endorsing liberals – would endorse Trump. But, for those for whom this decision may come as a shock, the Times also published an editorial detailing their reasons for not endorsing Ol’ Pickled Tangerine.

Of course, neither the endorsement nor the list of reasons not to vote for Trump mentioned the Libertarian Party candidate, Gary Johnson, but this is also to be expected.

The full list is here, but the Cliff Notes are basically: Trump is a shady businessman with a history of failure; he’s a racist; he’d erode speech and expression rights to benefit him, put journalists and critics he doesn’t like in legal harm’s way, and bolster the already massive police state; he’d be bad for the economy; he’s dangerously blase about issues that affect a wide majority of Americans.

And, relatively speaking, this list is a pretty solid reason not to vote for Trump.

But here’s the anarchist’s dilemma: is the threat of a Trump presidency enough to justify a vote for Clinton? When the 2016 election cycle was in its infancy, an argument might have been reliably made for the standard “Don’t vote, they’re all evil” line of anarchist polemic. Now, with little over a month left before Election Day, the question doesn’t make way for clear answers.

Donald Trump is a material threat to individual liberty. But Hillary Clinton will, guaranteed, inflict pain and misery upon people around the world, both in continuing Bush and Obama’s horrendous war on terrorism and its attendant drone assassination programs, and by maintaining the type of closed-border protectionism that turns undocumented immigrants and refugees from the very war on terrorism she’ll keep fighting into criminals at best, and unmarked bags of bones in the desert at worst.

Donald Trump has spurred a marked rightward trend in all realms of politics, and if he were to become president it is very highly possible that he’d usher in an explicitly proto-fascist or fascist state. His candidacy has inspired cadres of white supremacists and neo-nazis to come out of the shadows and into the daylight. Hillary Clinton would not, obviously, bring about an explicitly authoritarian dictatorship domestically, but for many sectors of the country the distinction between “fascist state” and “status quo” is already too small.

An epidemic of murders of black men and women by police has been occurring for years, and while Clinton’s campaign promises to improve racial justice by “reforming sentencing laws and policies, ending racial profiling by law enforcement, [and] strengthening the bonds of trust between communities and police,” it’s doubtful that will stem the tide of murder, much less resolve a problem that even the State acknowledges – that law enforcement agencies have become saturated by white supremacists in recent years.

These problems would almost certainly be exacerbated by a Trump presidency.

So when it comes to the question of voting for Clinton to keep Trump away from the White House, the answer is not a given “yes,” but it isn’t an understood “no,” either. If one is going to vote for Clinton to keep Trump out of office, one must realize that it is not enough to vote for her; other work must be done as well.

And if one is not going to vote for Clinton, regardless of how the election turns out, it might be a good idea to be engaged in building institutions of counterpower before Trump, or Trumpism, has a chance to take over in the future.

Feature Articles
Make Libertarianism Working Class Again!

Ever since the famous communist Joseph Déjacque coined the political use of the term libertarian in a letter to Pierre-Joseph Proudhon back in 1857 as a way to differentiate his views from those of the authoritarian communists within the anti-capitalist movement, the philosophy of libertarianism has always implied working class rebellion. At least until a few dissenting Republicans tried to make common ground with the anti-authoritarian left, adopted much of their language, but largely left out the class analysis espoused by the likes of Déjacque, Proudhon, Bakunin, Kropotkin, Spooner, Tucker, and so many others before and since.

When Proudhon first laid the groundwork for free-market anarchism, he saw it as a way of achieving socialist goals through mostly anti-statist means. In fact, he was a member of the First International alongside Karl Marx. In the U.S. many early American libertarians and anarchists were important allies within the labor movement, from the fight against slavery to the fight for the 8-hour work day and beyond. It was the anarchists who influenced the Industrial Workers of the World’s libertarian stance as a labor union.

But since then, libertarianism in America is more commonly associated with capitalist business interests and vulgar “free”-marketers. Some, like Konkin, have tried to correct this by reinserting a class analysis into libertarianism and was successful in creating a philosophy re-uniting market libertarianism with the class struggle and feminism. His philosophy has even crossed over into mutualist libertarian circles with ideas of anti-capitalist agorism, similar in many ways to Proudhon’s strategy of dual power. So with Ron Paul and Gary Johnson inspiring more and more people to discover less class-based libertarian ideas, how can those truly concerned about classism bring these new members into the fold and combat a seemingly predominate form of vulgar libertarianism? How can we prove to the left that libertarianism and class struggle can co-exist? In comes the Povertarian Caucus.

“[M]odern expressions of free market principles have everything to do with the state as a weapon of fiscal dominance that masks itself as a free market. A great example of that is the TPP … calling itself ‘free trade’. Libertarians today know this but outside of C4SS it really hasn’t been advanced as a coherent narrative that brings back that revolutionary spirit of economic freedom as a benefit not to business but to the individual,” explained Mikester of the Libertarian Party Povertarian Caucus.

The Povertarian Caucus arose in response to the “poll tax” required for delegates to participate in the Libertarian National Convention. Defenders of the tax tried to discredit them by referring to them dismissively as “povertarians” and claiming that they just wanted a “free lunch” but the tables turned when opponents of the tax took back the insult and formed a caucus out of it dedicated to working class libertarian issues.

Since 2014, they have become known most for their bi-annual pizza party which they throw opposite the high-class banquet held at the LNC. The absurdity of a libertarian event being so inaccessible to the poor and working class would make the founders of the term spin in their graves but the povertarians are there to fill your stomach without draining your wallet. But what’s more impressive than their pizza is their championing of worker’s rights.

“[W]e immediately realized there was an opportunity far beyond the boundaries of internal dynamics about floor fees, since libertarian ideas about markets correct predict that intervention has produced widespread poverty. There is so much opportunity for the party to improve how it speaks to issues of market liberation. The reality of modern society is, there are a lot of poor people, and they’re looking for political solutions that we can offer. And when we sat down and really brainstormed into that space we discovered a variety of issues in that blind spot that we can illuminate: homelessness, felon’s rights, the inhumanity of the welfare state, very tight controls over entry to the independent marketplace, the police/prison state as a sources of compulsory labor, and more.”

Classical libertarian thought formed out of a communist analysis of the state. Many who agreed with communist goals of working class emancipation were critical of the idea that the state could be used to achieve such goals when they were a huge part of the problem in the first place in upholding the unfree capitalist market. These libertarians were libertarian because of their views on working class emancipation, not despite them. And now the povertarians, like the agorists before them, are here to help correct the path of the american libertarian movement by rerooting it in class struggle from a free-market perspective.

When asked about the Povertarian Caucus in relation to classical libertarian thought, Mikester responded about how he, “feel[s] like those roots were obfuscated over time as the american political class rose to replace the aristocracy that came before. The language was placed in service of capital as privileged over labor whereas the revolutionary potential had always been the idea that those are inseparable.” And as far as unions, they are seen as, “voluntary associations and private contracts. Workers and workplaces have a right to combine however to establish whatever agreements they wish. The market can’t be healthy unless every form of association is free to flourish. We only oppose what you might call “crony unions” that are functionally bosses. State controls like the NLRB pervert the concept and place labor in service to the corporation-state and that is not OK.”

Well considering that’s the line more labor anarchists already tow, it seems that the Povertarian Caucus might prove to bridge that gap between those who have discovered libertarianism through party politics and those who discovered it through working class analysis. I for one, despite my aversion to party politics, wish them luck.

Stigmergy - C4SS Blog, Supporter Updates
Media Coordinator Monthly Update: September, 2016

Dear Supporters,

The mission of the Center for a Stateless Society is to introduce left market anarchism to the broader public through education and commentary on the issues of the day. That mission is ongoing, but I am happy to report that in the month of September (8/26-9/25), our writers and Fellows helped further the work along.

As Media Coordinator, I am vested with the responsibility to send commentaries out to newspapers, magazines and Internet publishers, and track our influence in those various spaces.

The following is rough data compiled up to the time of this report’s publication. This information is subject to revision at a later time.

September MVP: Logan Glitterbomb

It’s hard to put more content out per month than Kevin Carson, but in September, Logan Glitterbomb got it done. Her range of work extends from op-eds on anti-fascist graffiti in Germany to examinations of anarcho-syndicalism, agorism and illegalism in her contributions to this month’s Mutual Exchange. As of today, Logan published a grand total of six articles and was picked up 7 times by various publications and online outlets.

Outlets we love: Augusta Free Press

We gave the Augusta, GA Free Press a shout-out in an earlier weekly update, but it cannot be overstated: this local independent paper serving the city and county of Augusta has consistently published our work, and for that we’re thankful.

Another notable outlet in recent weeks has been the Gilmer, Texas Mirror, which has been republishing pieces by our writers with increased gusto.

The Month in Pickups

So, how did C4SS do in terms of commentary publications and pickups? I would say it was a fairly solid month for us. From August 26 to September 23, we put out 15 commentaries – that’s a commentary every other day. While much of the coverage was aimed toward events in the United States, we did have a smattering of coverage of goings-on in the United Kingdom, Spain and Germany from Logan Glitterbomb and Billy Christmas.

Some notable pickups for our articles published in September include:

  • Logan Glitterbomb – “Indigenous Property Rights and the Dakota Access Pipeline,” Counterpunch.
  • Trevor Hultner – “Colin Kaepernick’s Bold Stand,” Antiwar Blog.
  • Meg Arnold – “Responsibility and Freedom: A Defense of Safe Spaces,” Students for Liberty Blog.
  • Kevin Carson – “Why Are the ‘Adults in the Room’ So Awful?” The Libertarian Alliance.
  • Kevin Carson – “Time to Deprogram From the Cult of National Unity,” Counterpunch.

10th Anniversary Essay Contest

C4SS turns 10 years old this October! This is a momentous occasion for us.

Ten years is an immensely long time for any anarchist project to exist, period. Ten years on the Internet? An eternity. We couldn’t have done it without your support, and we’ll be talking more about that in a later Media Coordinator Special Report, but right now, we want to announce something special to celebrate.

If you have ever wanted to write for the Center for a Stateless Society, here is your chance!

Starting today, Sept. 25, we are opening up our article submissions process to all prospective writers who have something to say about anarchism and current affairs in the first-ever C4SS Essay Contest. The desired topic is elections, but you can write about whatever you like.

We will pick three writers to publish as new C4SS contributors starting on October 26. Their essays will be judged on four criteria; clarity, style, relevance and anarchist commitment:

  • Can the writer get their point across clearly?
  • Does the writer have a distinct writing “voice?”
  • Is the writer’s topic timely, relevant or newsworthy?
  • Can the writer explicate their point in an anarchist context?

The winners will be notified by November 6, and their essays will be published as C4SS commentaries through the month of November. Additionally, at the end of our fiscal month for November the winners will receive $25 each and the opportunity to continue writing for C4SS moving forward.

Submissions are open today. Kindly send all essay submissions of 500 to 750 words, comments and queries to trevor@c4ss.org.

Donate! It’s how we get paid – and it’s how we pay others

The Center for a Stateless Society is a 501(c)(3) non-profit organization. Its rotating cast of Fellows and volunteers work tirelessly to bring market anarchist content to all corners of the world. The work we do – writing, translating, setting up discussion fora, tabling at events like the upcoming Students For Liberty Regional Conferences all over the United States, and more – is paid for by your contributions. For the past decade, you have supported us in the act of spreading anarchy and working toward a better world. We look forward to the next ten years.

Click here for more ways you can support C4SS.

Commentary
Angela Davis Defends Animals, Others Oppressed

Writing at RenewAmerica, Cliff Kincaid takes Angela Davis to task for “going vegan” (“Black Power icon goes vegan to save animals,” September 21, 2016). Rather than actually consider the extreme torture and slaughter of animals perpetrated by humans, Kincaid seems wedded to the standard tactics of other animal oppressors — basing his attack solely on innuendo, deflection, guilt by association, and flat out falsehoods.

The very title of the article implies that Davis’s veganism is some new whim she’s seized onto in order to gain relevance. In fact, Davis first alluded to her veganism as far back as 2012 in a speech at the Empowering Women of Color Conference, where she stated that animal liberation is inextricably interwoven with other anti-oppression movements. She simply doesn’t talk much about it, she said.

By implying that Davis has only recently “gone vegan,” Kincaid uses the tried and true approach of distracting from the issue at hand — the plight of non-human animals, who die by the hundreds of billions each year thanks to human greed and bloodlust. Kincaid’s smears don’t stop there. He goes on to list a litany of causes Davis is connected with: communism, Islam, Black Lives Matter, prison abolition, and anti-capitalism. He even goes so far as to call Davis PETA’s new poster-child; PETA, an organization he says “places the rights of animals above human needs,” a laughable claim to anyone remotely familiar with PETA. By spending most of his article tying Davis to movements and entities Kincaid considers disreputable, Kincaid hopes the reader’s takeaway about animal liberation and veganism will remain obscured and uninformed.

Kincaid’s broadside against Davis really isn’t anything to write home about, though. His brand of obfuscation is yet one more contribution to a repugnant and repressive anti-animal worldview held by the masses. Kincaid, however distasteful his Professional Patriot shtick, presents what’s basically the same smokescreen-as-justification that most readers of this article do themselves at the dinner table each night.

Kincaid’s purposeful ignorance of the injustice done to animals — the routinized beating, knifing, raping, burning, boiling, skinning, electrocution and countless other modes of torture and dominance employed — is to be expected. Nobody should be surprised by a racist, climate denying, pro-war, Christian fundamentalist, covering up atrocities against animals. But for anarchists, libertarians, progressives and others of the Left, partaking in or making excuses for the unspeakable crimes committed against animals — who have an interest in their continued existence, their families, and their habitats — is utterly beyond the pale. For those who claim to be passionate about justice for all, while at the same time contributing to the mass slaughter of animals, shame on you. Rutgers law professor Gary Francione aptly labels this “moral schizophrenia.”

No doubt, many will characterize any vegan or animal advocacy as secular zealotry. While animal liberationists are at least tolerated by some on the Left, harsher treatment is reserved for vegans, despite their actions being a far more passive means of protest than outright liberation of confined animals. That is because causing friends, family, and other members of one’s community, to pause and consider, for the briefest moment, the gruesomeness that brings food to their table, is the ultimate spoiler. It is taboo — tantamount to putting a mirror in front of a person who must take a hard look inward.

Would otherwise compassionate social justice activists minimize or mock the oppression of racial, sexual, ethnic or other minorities? Yet when a challenge to the barbarism of one’s dinner plate is put forth, defense by any means necessary is employed by both Right and Left. Says Davis: “The food we eat masks so much cruelty. The fact that we can sit down and eat a piece of chicken without thinking about the horrendous conditions under which chickens are industrially bred in this country is a sign of the dangers of capitalism, how capitalism has colonized our minds. The fact that we look no further than the commodity itself, the fact that we refuse to understand the relationships that underlie the commodities that we use on a daily basis…food is like that.”

Forget about Kincaid and his ilk. They’re beyond reform. It’s time we on the Left stop patting ourselves on the back for yelling loudly about the injustice du jour with a mouth stuffed full of it.

Feature Articles
Neither Democracy nor Elitism

Whenever we libertarians point out democracy’s perverse incentives (as I do here) we risk being accused of elitism. However, those who assume that the only alternative to rule by the people is rule by an aristocracy reveal a tragically incomplete awareness of the choices before us.

Rather than choose among rulers, we should ask why anyone at all must rule. But even if we don’t go quite that far, we could entertain the idea that radically reducing the scale and scope of government, which essentially is the threat of violence, would also drastically reduce the harm produced by those perverse incentives. Elitism isn’t the only available alternative to democracy — and it certainly is not the most desirable one.

Unfortunately, some libertarian critiques of democracy encourage nonlibertarians to believe some form of elitism is the only alternative. Take Georgetown University professor Jason Brennan’s recent op-ed, “Can epistocracy, or knowledge-based voting, fix democracy?” in the Los Angeles Times, which is drawn from his book Against Democracy.

Brennan begins by citing democracy’s systemic flaw:

“The median voter wields great power over what politicians ultimately do. But — and here’s the problem — the median voter would fail economics or Political Science 101.

“For 60 years, political scientists have studied what voters actually know. The results are depressing. Hundreds of different surveys, such as the American National Election Studies, find that the median voter is ignorant or misinformed not only about the social sciences needed to evaluate candidates’ policy proposals, but even of basic facts and trends, such as what the unemployment rate is and whether it’s going up or down.

“This isn’t because public schools fail us. It’s not because Fox News or MSNBC (take your pick) bamboozles poor voters with well-crafted lies. It’s not because people are inherently stupid or unable to think for themselves. It’s because democracy gives us the wrong incentives.

“How we vote matters, but how any one of us votes does not. The chance an individual vote will make a difference is vanishingly small. Thus, we have little incentive to gather relevant information so that we can cast our votes in careful, thoughtful ways….

“While not everything governments do is decided by voters — bureaucracies, parties and officials have significant independence — what voters want makes a difference. And since voters are generally uninformed, we get worse policies that we would with a better-informed electorate.”

I’ll leave for another time Brennan’s debatable contention that this “better-informed electorate” is really better informed where it counts. (When this electorate says it favors “free trade,” does it actually mean neoliberal managed trade through government agreements, which may be what some of the supposedly lesser informed electorate fears?)

Instead, I’ll focus on Brennan’s “alternative to democracy called epistocracy.” He explains: “In a democracy, every citizen gets an equal right to vote. In an epistocracy, voting power is widespread, but votes are weighted: More knowledgeable citizens’ votes count more.”

Brennan lays out several ways to implement epistocracy, insisting that “epistocracies should keep some things — like our basic rights — off the bargaining table. They should make power widespread because concentrating power among the few invites abuse. Epistocracies should have constitutional limits on power, judicial review, checks and balances and a bill of rights — just like representative democracies.” That’s a relief, but can we really trust the informed elite to understand basic rights? (Did the framers of the Constitution get it right? I argue otherwise in America’s Counter-Revolution: The Constitution Revisited.)

Even with his caveat, Brennan’s proposal leaves him open to the charge of elitism. Rod Dreher of The American Conservative writes,

“Restricting the vote to the cognitive elite is no solution. I would rather be ruled by the first thousand people through the gates at the Daytona 500 than the people in that room Friday night with Hillary Clinton and Barbra Streisand. Guess who holds more power already in our society? That’s right: the cognitive elite. That’s how it works in a meritocracy. Prof. Brennan’s epistocracy would only give them more — for our own good.”

Brennan certainly does not blunt the elitism charge when he writes:

“Some would object that epistocracy is essentially inegalitarian. In an epistocracy, not everyone has the same voting power. But what’s so wrong with that? Only some people have plumbing or hairdressing licenses because we accept that only some people are qualified to fix pipes or cut hair. Perhaps only some people, rather than everyone 18 and over, are truly qualified to decide who will lead the most powerful country on earth.”

Need I point out that it is astonishing for a libertarian to cite licensing in defense of his plan for an unequal distribution of voting power? Formally, licensing is the state’s way of determining who may and may not engage in occupations supposedly in the interest of consumers. Actually, licensing is how incumbent practitioners of occupations exclude competition and hamper innovation in order to support the monopolistic incomes to which they have become accustomed. It’s a system of privilege. Why hitch political reform to it?

The public-choice problems with any form of epistocracy have long been noted, and Brennan is familiar with them. For example, who would compose the test to determine who gets extra votes? Even if we assume that Brennan has good ideas about making any test fair, public-choice analysis gives us reason to doubt that his ideas would be adopted.

Another problem with testing relates to Gilbert Ryle’s distinction between “knowing how” and “knowing that.” Someone could be ignorant of the facts asked for on a test — what’s the unemployment rate? what party controls Congress? Etc. —  but have perfectly libertarian instincts about what the government ought not to be able to do to him. Why should that person have fewer votes than, say, Paul Krugman or George Will?

The shame here is the Brennan needn’t have gone down this road. He needed only to spell out the flaws in democracy, contrast stupid “public” action with reasonably intelligent private action, and call for a substantial shrinking of government — if not its abolition. Why invite the elitist charge with a call for an epistocracy?

Albert Jay Nock had it right in the opening of his classic book, Our Enemy the State:

“If we look beneath the surface of our public affairs, we can discern one fundamental fact, namely, a great redistribution of power between society and the State. This is the fact that interests the student of civilization. He has only a secondary or derived interest in matters like price fixing, wage fixing, inflation, political banking, ‘agricultural adjustment,’ and similar items of State policy that fill the pages of newspapers and the mouths of publicists and politicians. All these can be run up under one head. They have an immediate and temporary importance, and for this reason they monopolize public attention, but they all come to the same thing; which is, an increase of State power and a corresponding decrease of social power.

“It is unfortunately none too well understood that, just as the State has no money of its own, so it has no power of its own. All the power it has is what society gives it, plus what it confiscates from time to time on one pretext or another; there is no other source from which State power can be drawn. Therefore every assumption of State power, whether by gift or seizure, leaves society with so much less power. There is never, nor can there be, any strengthening of State power without a corresponding and roughly equivalent depletion of social power.” (Emphasis added.)

 Social power is Nock’s term for the web of peaceful consensual relations — market and otherwise — among free individuals. Thus the people’s best political framework is neither democracy nor epistocracy but original liberalism, or what we today call libertarianism.
Italian, Stateless Embassies
Liberate Chelsea Manning Oggi!

[Di Kaile Hultner. Originale pubblicato su Center for a Stateless Society il 21 settembre 2016 con il titolo Free Chelsea Manning Today! Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.]

Fin dai primi giorni del primo mandato di Obama, gli Stati Uniti hanno messo in pratica un’accanimento legale nel punire gli informatori. Se qualcuno può essere identificato come fonte di una rivelazione, e se quel qualcuno è sotto la giurisdizione degli Stati Uniti o dei suoi tribunali militari, allora può essere perseguito per crimini contro lo stato e la “sicurezza nazionale”.

È in questa atmosfera che l’Associazione Americana per le Libertà Civili (ACLU) ha annunciato la richiesta della grazia, piena e incondizionata, per Edward Snowden, l’ex dipendente di una società d’appalto nello spionaggio che rivelò informazioni segrete, riguardanti le intercettazioni della National Security Agency e la raccolta di informazioni private, a Glenn Greenwald e ai quotidiani UK Guardian e Washington Post.

“Grazie all’atto di coscienza di Edward Snowden, abbiamo fatto enormi passi avanti nella lotta per la riforma dei sistemi di sorveglianza e per il miglioramento della sicurezza informatica,” ha detto la settimana scorsa il direttore della ACLU Anthony D. Romero. “È per questo che oggi, in anticipo sull’uscita del film ‘Snowden’ di Oliver Stone, annunciamo i nostri sforzi chiedendo al presidente Obama di graziare chi ha svelato le attività dell’NSA.”

Qualcuno è rimasto scontento della chiamata all’azione dell’ACLU, come la redazione del Washington Post, il giornale che ha contribuito a pubblicare le rivelazioni, che poi ha dichiarato lesive della sicurezza nazionale all’estero. Inutile dire che l’ACLU ha smosso le acque attorno al problema.

Stranamente, però, nel dibattito sulla grazia a Snowden non si parla della situazione di Chelsea Manning.

A luglio scorso, l’informatore ventottenne ha tentato il suicidio durante una condanna a 35 anni, da scontare nel carcere militare di Fort Leavenworth per aver violato la legge sullo spionaggio, la stessa legge di un secolo fa che gli Stati Uniti vogliono usare contro Snowden. All’inizio di settembre la Manning ha iniziato uno sciopero di protesta contro il suo trattamento, dichiarando di non ricevere trattamenti appropriati alla sua disforia di genere: tra l’altro, le hanno vietato di farsi crescere i capelli ed è soggetta a intimidazioni da parte del personale carcerario.

“Oggi ho deciso che non mi lascerò più impaurire da questo carcere, o da chicchessia nello stato americano,” ha detto la Manning. “Non chiedo altro che quella dignità e quel rispetto concessi ad ogni essere umano, atti che io credevo fossero garantiti.”

È questa la ragione per cui la Manning dovrebbe tornare in libertà; la ragione per cui tutti, in particolare questa persona, dovrebbero essere liberati. Finché starà in carcere, le negheranno la dignità e il rispetto che cerca. Lo stato le ha tolto dignità e rispetto apposta, per mandare un messaggio a chi volesse fare lo stesso.

Chelsea Manning è stata condannata per aver sfidato lo stato mentre era in corso un conflitto. In un certo senso, un senso strano e perverso, potrebbe considerarsi criminale di guerra. Ma ha solo aiutato le famiglie di due fotoreporter della Reuter trucidati, Saeed Chmagh e Namir Noor-Eldeen, a capire l’accaduto (i due furono uccisi nel 2007 con un attacco dall’alto), e ha aiutato americani e non di tutto il mondo a capire l’enormità delle disgraziate avventure militari americane in Afganistan e più in generale in Iraq.

L’accusa di essere un “criminale di guerra” è una boutade se pensiamo a personaggi come Henry Kissinger, che oltre ad essere il ganzo di Hillary Clinton è anche quello che sta dietro molte note atrocità come i campi di sterminio dei Khmer Rossi in Cambogia, il golpe e la dittatura di Augusto Pinochet in Cile, e praticamente tutto il lungo e sanguinoso conflitto in Vietnam. E che tuttora è a piede libero.

E però la Manning è costretta a pagare un debito che non le appartiene: anni della sua vita, la tranquillità, la possibilità di muoversi e di frequentare chi vuole. E questo perché ha avuto un cambio di coscienza mentre serviva una delle più grandi forze assassine e oppressive del pianeta.

La Manning ha sospeso lo sciopero della fame il 13 settembre, dopo aver appreso che i medici militari avevano approvato la sua richiesta di sottoporsi a cambiamento di sesso. Da allora, a parte il tweet in cui il fondatore di Wikileaks Julian Assange prometteva la sua costituzione se Obama avesse dato la grazia alla Manning, i media si sono chiusi nel silenzio.

Ora, se ci raccogliamo attorno ad Edward Snowden e cominciamo una campagna chiedendo la grazia per lui, è più che giusto che facciamo lo stesso per Chelsea Manning. Liberatela oggi, incondizionatamente!

Italian, Stateless Embassies
Deprogrammiamo il Culto dell’Unità Nazionale

[Di Kevin Carson. Originale pubblicato su Center for a Stateless Society il 17 settembre 2016 con il titolo Time to Deprogram From the Cult of National Unity. Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.]

La gente non ama che si bestemmino le sue divinità, e la reazione furiosa al rifiuto di Colin Kaepernick di stare in piedi durante l’inno nazionale ha rivelato la natura completamente religiosa del patriottismo americano.

Tomi Lahren, le cui opinioni in materia razziale sono più o meno quelle che ti aspetti da un “opinionista conservatore” su TheBlaze di Glenn Beck, è offeso da quando l’atteggiamento di Kaepernick è finito in prima pagina. Mentre si diffonde la protesta di chi si siede, s’inginocchia o alza il pugno durante l’inno nazionale, sui social Kate Upton si è unita alla campagna di Lahren per fare del football un luogo sicuro per patrioti ipersensibili. Com’era intuibile, la protesta ha raggiunto il massimo l’undici settembre. Alla decisione di alcuni giocatori dei Dolphins di inginocchiarsi durante l’inno, la Upton ha replicato sgridandoli: “Dovreste essere orgogliosi di essere americani. Soprattutto l’undici settembre, quando dovremmo sostenerci a vicenda.” Ma il commento più pacchiano, che va dritto al cuore del culto dell’unità nazionale, è quello di Lahren: “Noi non siamo bianchi & neri, noi siamo rossi, bianchi & blu.” “Siamo americani e dipendiamo l’uno dall’altro.”

Howard Zinn ha abilmente smontato questa idea secondo cui la nostra identità comune di americani è in qualche modo più importante delle differenze razziali o di classe:

“[I nostri attuali leader] ci bombardano con espressioni come ‘interesse nazionale’, ‘sicurezza nazionale’, e ‘difesa nazionale’, come se tutti questi concetti si potessero applicare ugualmente a tutti noi, bianchi o neri, ricchi o poveri, come se gli interessi della General Motors e della Halliburton coincidessero con i nostri, come se George Bush avesse gli stessi interessi del giovane o della giovane che manda in guerra.

“Certo, tra tutte le bugie dette alla popolazione, questa è la più grande. Tra tutti i segreti celati alla popolazione americana, il segreto più grande è che in questo paese ci sono classi con interessi diversi. Ignorare ciò, non sapere che la storia del nostro paese è una storia di schiavisti contro schiavi, possidenti contro fittavoli, aziende contro lavoratori, ricchi contro poveri, significa essere disarmati di fronte alle più piccole bugie che ci dicono quelli al potere.”

Il culto dell’unità nazionale è vecchio, e se esiste ancora c’è una ragione. Si accorda con molti altri miti patriottici americani rafforzandoli. Tra questi il mito dell’“Eccezionalismo Americano”: dire che l’America è la “nazione indispensabile”, unica, che promuove “pace e libertà” in tutto il mondo, e pertanto ha il diritto di avere un apparato militare più grande del resto del mondo messo assieme, e in virtù del suo ruolo benefico può definire unilateralmente “minaccia” o “aggressore” chiunque osi sfidare i diktat americani.

Un altro mito associato al culto dell’unità nazionale è l’American Dream. Si nota da come la maggioranza degli americani pensano di essere “classe media”. Spinge gli americani a credere che la ricchezza sia semplicemente una questione di lavoro duro e ingegno, a identificarsi con il “53%” di “contribuenti” e di “chi produce opposto a chi consuma” contro chi fa lotta di classe come Occupy. Sperando di azzeccare il colpo un giorno o l’altro.

Ma solitamente compare anche connesso al culto dei militari come guardiani delle “nostre libertà”, come illustrato dai commenti Instagram della Upton a proposito dell’undici settembre. L’inno, dice, “significa onore ai tanti uomini e donne coraggiosi che sacrificano e hanno sacrificato le loro vite ogni singolo giorno per proteggere le nostre libertà.”

Anche se la pura verità è che la stragrande maggioranza delle guerre americane sono state combattute per assicurare l’accesso dei capitalisti a nuovi territori, alle risorse naturali e ai mercati mondiali, così che i ricchi possano accumulare gran parte delle loro ricchezze estraendo rendita da tutti noi con l’aiuto dello stato.

L’America è “eccezionale” tra i paesi occidentali sviluppati perché la schiavitù ha avuto un ruolo nella sua economia, e perché è il più grande paese colonizzatore, creato da colonizzatori europei che scacciarono e sterminarono le popolazioni indigene a livello continentale. Forse anche per queste ragioni, sono eccezionali le dimensioni del suo sistema carcerario e la cultura che glorifica polizia e soldati. È “eccezionale” solo finché il mito della “Città Scintillante Sopra un Monte” e di una “Società Senza Classi” viene inculcato nella popolazione. Questi miti oscurano la realtà criminale del ruolo americano nel mondo; la realtà americana è nascosta dietro la facciata idealistica ufficiale.

Grazie a questo insieme di ideologie semiufficiali, l’America ha guadagnato lo status unico di poliziotto globale del potere di classe. Unica è anche nel celare l’esistenza stessa del conflitto di classe agli occhi di una parte significativa della sua popolazione.

Fortunatamente, come evidenziato dall’ascesa di Occupy e Black Lives Matter, e dal movimento di protesta ispirato da Kaepernick, l’incantesimo del culto patriottico sta sfumando. In fin dei conti, il potere dipende dal consenso. E il consenso dipende dall’inganno e dall’ignoranza. Quando la gente riuscirà a vedere l’inganno dietro queste ideologie legittimanti, allora il sistema sarà condannato.

Commentary
Dismantle the Police

Last week, Tulsa, Oklahoma police officer Betty Shelby fatally shot 40-year-old stranded motorist Terence Crutcher in the back after another officer tased him to the ground. The database killedbypolice.net lists Crutcher as the 825th individual to have been shot and killed by a cop in 2016.

At this point, it’s clear that nothing short of a complete dismantling of the police force is necessary to stop them from killing black men and women.

There are simply no more justifications to be made here. No more claims of “bad apples,” no more room to use the officer safety argument. Police feel vested with the power to kill anyone they please, and they absolutely know it. This isn’t even the first time an unarmed black man has been killed in Tulsa County within the last two or three years. Either we take the entire system apart or this keeps happening. There are no alternatives.

According to the Associated Press, “Shelby’s attorney, Scott Wood, said Crutcher was not following the officers’ commands and that Shelby was concerned because he kept reaching for his pocket as if he was carrying a weapon.”

Disobeying a police officer is not grounds for murder. Handling potentially volatile situations with a cool head and a relaxed trigger finger is ostensibly why we even keep police around in the first place. If we can’t even trust them to keep that commitment, how can we trust them to reasonably keep our communities safe?

No, it’s time to wipe the slate clean and start over. The time is high for us to have a conversation about what proper community protection looks like. We should be attempting to put those new ideas into practice, and we should be doing so while every officer turns in their badge and gun.

Some may find that to be overly harsh. That’s fine. Those are likely the same individuals who misconstrue Colin Kaepernick and dozens of high school and college football teams’ kneeling protest during the national anthem as being “unpatriotic.” No. The fact is, they’re protesting this. They’re protesting the fact that this keeps happening while the people who perpetrate these crimes get away with it, nearly always consequence-free. It should be astoundingly easy for even the most casual layman to see that.

It’s time to dismantle law enforcement.

Full stop.

Feature Articles
“Libertarian” DAPL Shill Defends “Property Rights” of Robbers

I keep thinking I couldn’t be any more repulsed by right-libertarian apologists for big business. And every time, I run across something like William F. Shughart II’s crude apologetic for the Dakota Access Pipeline at the so-called “libertarian” Independent Institute (“Environmentalists’ Questionable Tactics in North Dakota,” Sept. 12). Since the beginning of capitalism, its propagandists have used the rhetoric of “property rights” to defend the enormous piles of stolen loot that the propertied classes sit on top of — loot whose robbery was foundational to capitalism as a historic system. Shughart’s sorry commentary is very much in the grand capitalist tradition of “OK, no more stealing, starting…NOW!”

“Anyone who wants low-cost power and a more diversified U.S. energy portfolio,” Shughart begins, adopting the mealymouthed voice of a typical concern troll, “should be shocked by recent events on privately owned land near the Standing Rock Sioux reservation in southern North Dakota.” Shughart’s reasons for shock are considerably different from those of us who have been following frontline accounts of the confrontation on social media for the past few weeks. “Over the past weekend, four security guards and two guard dogs were injured by protesters interfering with construction of one of the largest and most important U.S. energy projects, the Dakota Access Pipeline (DAPL).”

This is a bit like the statement in the satirical 1066 And All That that the Pope and his bishops seceded from the Church of England. Anyone following direct accounts of the protests, with the graphic imagery in photos and video, has probably come away with something like a scene straight out of a Billy Jack movie: poorly trained wannabe Pinkerton thugs hired by the pipeline project, siccing dogs on unarmed, largely non-violent protestors (including pregnant women). Not Shughart, though. Just “four security guards and two guard dogs” injured.

His description of the “economic benefits” of the pipeline reads like something written by a paid DAPL flack: The pipeline, “a monumental engineering feat,” will transport approximately 470,000 barrels of oil a day, and “will create between 8,000 to 12,000 good-paying jobs.”

First of all, a lot of really evil projects have created jobs. So does the US military-industrial complex. So did the Nazi death camps.

And those rosy estimates of the pipeline’s capacity neglect inconvenient facts — for instance, the coagulation temperature of that oil is higher than even the average temperature in North Dakota, let alone average winter lows.

And the most disingenuous part of Shughart’s piece is the heart of it — his hand-wringing over “property rights”: “Peaceable assembly and freedom of speech are constitutionally protected rights, but so are the private property rights that are so essential to liberty and a civil society.”

You’d almost get the idea that the pipeline wasn’t being built almost entirely on stolen land. Shughart denies claims that First Nations weren’t consulted by the Army Corps of Engineers before construction, but the fact that the project was even considered in the first place, let alone treated as a matter of debate, is a gross injustice. The sacred land and burial sites on the pipeline’s route are already protected by treaty. The pipeline route comes within a half mile of a Hunkpapa reservation, and actually occupies land which itself was stolen from its indigenous inhabitants. By any standard of justice, the ACE’s jurisdiction for private land giveaways should be considered null and void.

The project — like all pipeline projects — has also relied heavily on eminent domain, and could never have even existed without the delegated power to condemn land by force. Farmers throughout the Midwest have had their farms seized against their will by the DAPL project. What does it say about a “libertarian” publication like the Independent that it runs a pro-DAPL puff piece that bloviates about “property rights” without even mentioning eminent domain, and someone has to go to liberal sites like Think Progress and Democracy Now to see the issue even discussed?

Another property rights issue is the grave threat the possibility of a pipeline rupture presents to the drinking water of the First Nations along its route, and the irreversible, irremediable nature of the devastation that will result. We regularly see news stories of oil pipeline leaks all around the United States. We had one here in Arkansas, and there’s one going on in Alabama right now. In case you didn’t know, the liability for oil pipeline leaks is legally capped at an amount less than the cost of proper safety measures to prevent it. In any just, legitimate libertarian regime, the right of a community to take direct remedial action against immediate threats to the water commons in their environs would be considered an inalienable “property” right. And the people taking direct action to prevent construction of a pipeline, built on stolen land, that poses an immediate and unaccountable threat to the safety of their water, are entirely justified in doing so.

All of Shughart’s love for the project boils down to the fact that it provides “cheap energy,” as if an economy built on cheap, subsidized energy had a natural right to continued cheap energy inputs regardless of the land theft, environmental degradation and brutalization of human beings that went into it. “The inconvenient truth is that fossil fuels now and for the foreseeable future are our most economical energy sources.”

The real inconvenient truth is that our economy has developed in extremely wasteful and irrational directions, and treated energy as a free input rather than something to be economized on, because the economy is built on subsidized energy and raw material inputs provided by the state in collusion with extractive industries. DAPL or no DAPL, we are at or near the point of Peak Fossil Fuels, and our economy will have to develop along a different path whether Shughart likes it or not. That means, among other things, a return to cities and towns where people live within walking, bike or public transit distance of the places where they work and shop, and the replacement of global supply and distribution chains with small-scale manufacturing for local consumption.

Shughart also clutches his pearls over the projects’ economic losses resulting from the “disruption” of the project, including $1 million in damage to pipeline equipment from suspected arson at three locations, and delays from protestors chaining themselves to equipment.

All I can say is, good! I’m only sorry that anything less than every single bit of construction equipment was destroyed, and that the costs resulting from delay fall short of every cent its backers put into it. But God willing, that will be remedied in the days to come.

Commentary
Police Discrimination?

In part of a hopefully rising trend, five police officers were denied service at a Taco Bell in Louisville, Kentucky recently. The owner has since apologized and promised that the employees will be retrained to be more respectful to all customers, including law enforcement. But this is just one domino in an entire series of worker rebellions against cops. As movements against police militarization and systematic racism gain traction across the political spectrum, general distrust of the police is becoming more confrontational.

Just this past February in Irondale, Alabama, one of the armed fascists attempted to buy food at a Krystal drive thru but was completely ignored. After about 10 minutes, “the officer went inside to order. But the police chief says the workers who were inside walked away.” Another Taco Bell in Phenix City, Alabama made the news after a woman in Auburn posted that a local deputy had been told that they, “don’t serve cops.” One of the employees was fired after two more deputies were denied service in July. That same month at a Sunoco service station in Miramar, Florida, a pig pulled up with one of his kidnapping victims chained up in the back seat. Instead of ringing the officer, the clerk questioned him as to why he had arrested “his boy.” When the kidnapper refused to explain himself, the cashier turned him away stating, “you know why.” A  group of officers at a Dallas-based Genghis Grill were told that they couldn’t eat there because they might frighten other customers, for which the manager apologized. And in a more hilarious display, a cook at a Virginia-based Noodles & Co. exclaimed, “You better pull me off the line, because I’m not serving that,” resulting in the pig she was motioning at leaving in a huff.

And then there’s the even bolder employees who make cops feel unwelcome through more controversial methods such as spiking officers’ meals with extra spicy hot sauce or the employees who allegedly put glass in a cop’s sandwich sending him to the hospital. And while those actions may be questionable, they are but more examples of the general resentment of cops among wage workers. There’s even the surprising story of the actual owner at Lucky’s Teriyaki in Sedro-Woolley, Washington who not only informed two officers and their Chief Deputy that they were not allowed to eat there anymore, saying that their customers didn’t like law enforcement there, but also told them to spread the word that any and all law enforcement officials are no longer welcome.

But such business owners are in the minority. Most strive for good relations with the local departments both out of fear of rocking the boat and out of a perceived need for their protection in case of a robbery or other incident. “Disrespectful” employees are fired or disciplined, public apologies are made, and Blue Lives Matter messages plaster business windows in a logic-bending attempt to compare the refusal to service the armed enforcers of the state with racial bigotry. Police departments and their supporters are labeling such practices discrimination.

Luckily for us, police are not listed in any non-discrimination act in the nation, unlike actually marginalized communities systematically discriminated against by class, race, gender identity, religion, ability, or sexuality. Libertarians question the effectiveness of state non-discrimination acts in their ability to achieve admittedly sympathetic goals, and also raise possible unintended consequences of them, such as the hypothetical scenario of the Jewish baker forced to bake a Nazi cake. So it ought not be a question whether libertarians should stand up for the right of any business to refuse service to the boys and girls in blue. Hell, as Red and Black Cafe shows, it’s our duty as anarchists to keep the police out of our businesses. We should encourage this behavior and engage in it ourselves where possible.

On a personal note, I have only been so daring as to spit in a cop’s milkshake when I was forced to serve one at a Dairy Queen back in my rebellious teenage years. It wasn’t very practical or effective, but today’s rebel-workers inspire me to strive to do more in making the police feel unwelcome in my community.

And while some may continue to compare the ostracization of these armed terrorists to forms of bigotry and discrimination, others will simply point out that most businesses do not allow animals. And while many pigs will claim that they are service animals, obviously these employees and many more seriously beg to differ about the usefulness of the so-called “services” they provide.

Feature Articles
US Rewards Israel’s Bad Behavior

Benjamin Netanyahu has been perhaps the most anti-Palestinian Israeli prime minister of a large rogue’s gallery dedicated to driving the aggrieved Palestinians out of the land they and their ancestors have lived in and worked for millennia. This oppression — which has included ethnic cleansing, savage war on the people of the Gaza Strip, routine brutality and humiliation, and expanding illegal Jewish settlements on land conquered through aggressive war — has been underwritten and encouraged by the U.S. government since 1948. It has been rare indeed for an American president to express opposition or even irritation with an official Israeli act of brutality — and even then the consequences have varied between the symbolic (and short-lived) and nonexistent. The lip-service calls for Israel finally to leave occupied Palestinian land (the two-state solution), like President Barack Obama’s latest, count for nothing because no one believes the U.S. government is an honest broker that cares about injustices against the Palestinians. (Obama did not mention the Palestinians in a meeting with Netanyahu this week.)

It is no exaggeration to say that the U.S. government rewards Netanyahu for his regime’s bad behavior. For example, as Zaid Jilali reports at The Intercept, “Shortly before Netanyahu took office, 474,000 Israeli settlers were living in these territories. By the end of 2014, the last time the Israeli government released comprehensive statistics on the matter, that number had grown to around 570,000.” Yet U.S. military aid to Israel not only continues; it increases.

Israel’s rulers have no intention of recognizing the rights of Palestinians to their lives, liberty, and property. Past efforts that appeared conciliatory, such a Yitzhak Rabin’s Oslo Accords, were actually aimed at thwarting proposals to have the Palestinians in the occupied territories become citizens of the self-declared state of the Jewish People (the one-state solution). The other alternative to the two states, formal apartheid, is deemed as politically inexpedient.

Today the U.S. government continues to stand firmly in Israel’s corner, regardless of what the right wing says. The U.S. government has given Israel more than $3 billion a year in military aid for decades, though this basic assistance was often exceeded for alleged special reasons. Now the Obama administration has agreed to pay Israel a record $38 billion over 10 years. Much of this money, unsurprisingly, benefits the American military-industrial complex, and soon all of it will go to American firms.

Ironically Israel probably has never been so secure (which is not to say it ever faced an offensive existential threat). The Palestine Liberation Organization, Arab League, Iran, and arguably Hamas long ago offered to recognize Israel. (Netanyahu moved the goalpost by demanding that they recognize Israel as the state of the Jewish People.) The chaos in the Levant serves the Israeli state’s interests, which is why Netanyahu has long been receptive to American neoconservative proposals to undermine secular Arab governments with the anticipation that jihadists would prosper in the resulting instability. Top Israeli officials have not been shy about expressing their preference for violent Sunni sectarians (yes, al-Qaeda) over Shiite Iran and its secular Syrian ally Bashar al-Assad. (Until recently, Obama has shared that preference to an extent.) This is telling in light of the incontrovertible fact that Iran, which has an old Jewish community that freely practices its religion, is no threat to Israel whatever. Iran has had no nuclear-weapons ambitions and has signed a strict anti-nuclear-weapons agreement with the West in order to have decades-old sanctions lifted. Israel, meanwhile, is the Middle East’s monopoly nuclear-weapons state, which (unlike Iran) refuses to sign the Nuclear Non-Proliferation Treaty and thus (again unlike Iran) is subject to no international inspections. Moreover, recently leaked emails from former Secretary of State Colin Powell reveal that Israel’s 200 nuclear warheads are targeted at Iran. It is Israel that threatens Iran, not vice versa. (See my writings on Iran here.)

The upshot is that no good grounds exist for U.S. military aid to Israel, much less a significant increase. Nevertheless, instability and the invention of an Iranian threat are useful to the powers that be because the more dangerous the Middle East appears, the more forgiving Americans are likely to be about Israel’s daily dehumanization of the Palestinians.

Israel of course remains an American political football, with Democrats and Republican trying to outdo each other in their slavish allegiance to the (so-called) Jewish State. (Zionism is nationalism masquerading as Judaism.) Republicans, with Donald Trump leading the way (his AIPAC speech rivals that of the most fanatical Zionist), brand Obama the most anti-Israel president ever — which one can see is an absurd lie. So it’s no surprise that Republican Senators pledge to increase aid to Israel over its record level. (For the typical complaints about the new aid package, see this.) Meanwhile, a big group of Democratic senators, including Elizabeth Warren and Hillary Clinton’s running mate, Tim Kaine, joined Republicans (88 senators in all) in signing a letter published by AIPAC, the chief Israel lobby, urging Obama to veto any “one-sided” UN Security Council resolutions regarding “settlements or other final status issues.” The letter said such resolutions would “make it more difficult for Israelis and Palestinians to resolve the conflict,” but that concern is phony since Israel has repeatedly scuttled negotiations by insisting that it has a right to keep taking the very Palestinian land that is supposedly the subject of negotiations. According to Haaretz, the senators’ letter was “initiated and sponsored” by AIPAC, “apparently spurred by the Prime Minister’s Office in Jerusalem and Israel’s ambassador to the U.S., Ron Dermer.” Israel and its American lobby fear that after the U.S. election Obama might move for a Security Council resolution on Israel-Palestine.

The American ruling elite’s support for Israel is driven by imperial political and economic interests, as well as electoral financial considerations. But it aligns neither with the freedom and security of the American people (a growing number of American Jews do not identify with Israel) nor with the cause world peace and justice.

Recommended reading:

Jeremy R. Hammond, Obstacle to Peace: The US Role in the Israeli-Palestinian Conflict

Jeremy R. Hammond, The Rejection of Palestinian Self-Determination

Jeremy R. Hammond, The Myth of the U.N. Creation of Israel

David Hirst, The Gun and the Olive Branch: The Roots of Violence in the Middle East

Ilan Pappe, Ethnic Cleansing in Palestine

Sheldon Richman, “On Israel’s ‘Right to Exist'”

Sheldon Richman, “‘Ancient History’: U.S. Conduct in the Middle East Since World War II and the Folly of Intervention”

Shlomo Sand, The Invention of the Jewish People

Shlomo Sand, The Invention of the Land of Israel: From Holy Land to Homeland

For an attempt at a libertarian justification for the founding of the state of Israel (failed in my view), see Walter Block, Alan G. Futerman, and Rafi Farber, “The Legal Status of the State of Israel: A Libertarian Approach”

For critiques of this paper, see Jeremy R. Hammond, “Top Ten Things That Piss Me Off About Anti-Palestinian Libertarians”; “On Libertarianism and the Jews’ 2,000 Year Old Claim to Palestine”; and “On Libertarianism and Land Ownership in Historic Palestine”

Hammond debated Farber on the Tom Woods Show. Listen here.

Italian, Stateless Embassies
Perché “Riformare” il Copyright Significa Ucciderlo

[Di Kevin Carson. Originale pubblicato su Center for a Stateless Society il 21 agosto 2016 con il titolo Why “Reforming” Copyright Will Kill It. Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.]

Electronic Frontier Foundation ha recentemente presentato un esposto contro la sezione 1201 della Digital Millennial Copyright Act (DMCA) su basi costituzionali. Secondo l’esposto, la sezione, che criminalizza non solo chi aggira la protezione della Gestione dei Diritti Digitali (o DRM) ma anche chi condivide informazioni su come fare, va contro il diritto di espressione riconosciuto dal Primo Emendamento. Su Defective by Design, Zag Rogoff sostiene (“This lawsuit could be the beginning of the end for DRM,” 17 agosto) che l’abolizione della sezione 1201 potrebbe significare la fine del DRM. “Quando la 1201 non esisterà più, si spera, gli strumenti per aggirare il DRM si diffonderanno a macchia d’olio, e bloccare gli utenti sarà così difficile che le aziende smetteranno di provarci.”

Questo significa eliminare il modello capitalistico, in campo informatico, basato sulla “barriera DRM”, un sistema di sfruttamento economico e di potere di classe che, affidandosi alla soppressione del libero flusso informativo, ricorda i privilegi burocratici della vecchia Unione Sovietica. Significa anche distruggere il fulcro dell’attuale concetto di copyright: i raid, le leggi che alla terza infrazione tolgono la connessione a chi scarica illegalmente, e il sequestro del dominio dei siti di condivisione.

Ma come nota Cory Doctorow (Courtney Nash, “Cory Doctorow on legally disabling DRM (for good),” O’Reilly Media, 17 agosto), tutto ciò non distruggerà soltanto il regime draconiano di quella che è solitamente considerata l’industria informatica (musica, cinema, software, ecc.) ma anche l’uso sempre più invasivo del software protetto da copyright per imporre schemi proprietari e modelli aziendali a beni fisici. Per imporre, per esempio, pezzi di ricambio e accessori originali (come le cartucce di stampa) ricorrendo a software che scarta prodotti di terze parti.

“È un problema sentito in molti ambiti. Lo si ritrova nelle pompe di insulina, nelle macchine per votare, nei trattori… Diversi ricercatori nel campo della sicurezza hanno inoltrato un dossier in cui si parla di difetti gravi in prodotti che vanno dalle macchine per votare alle pompe insuliniche alle automobili, difetti non rivelati, su consiglio dei loro legali, perché così facendo potrebbero aiutare qualcuno a bypassare le protezioni DRM incorrendo così in denunce civili e penali.”

In breve, eliminare l’imposizione legale dei DRM (imposizione ottenuta, badate bene, ricorrendo a leggi criminali, non civili) distruggerebbe l’intero modello aziendale basato sull’informatica proprietaria, sia nella “industria digitale” vera e propria che nella produzione di beni fisici. Da notare che proprio queste sono le fonti primarie di profitto dell’attuale industria corporativa mondiale.

È interessante notare che intellettuali come Doctorow e Lawrence Lessig dichiarano di non essere contro il copyright: vogliono soltanto riformarlo e renderlo più giusto. Considerato quanto detto sopra, però, se il copyright sopravviverà in qualche forma, anche minima, dipenderà da interventi polizieschi come il DMCA e le clausole sulla “proprietà intellettuale” contenute in trattati sul “libero commercio” come il TTIP.

Questo non significa che il copyright cesserebbe di esistere o che non sarebbe più applicabile in alcuna forma. Ma ciò che resterebbe, tolta la possibilità di arrestare o denunciare per il reato di condivisione, sarebbe il copyright d’antan degli anni settanta. Il suo principale effetto concreto sarebbe impedire la stampa su larga scala di versioni non autorizzate di libri coperti da copyright, o di registrazioni acquistate in negozio. E questo sarebbe molto meno significativo, per lettori e ascoltatori, di quanto non lo fosse negli anni settanta, quando l’inconveniente della bassa qualità delle fotocopie e delle cassette era la minaccia principale per le industrie editoriali e discografiche. A quei tempi l’importanza del copyright come strumento per estrarre rendita era relativamente marginale rispetto alle altre fonti di profitto del capitalismo.

Il modello capitalistico che conosciamo noi, basato sul software proprietario alla base della rendita delle multinazionali, dipende completamente dall’azione dello stato di polizia come la criminalizzazione di chiunque cerchi di aggirare il DRM, l’arresto (senza processo di alcun genere) per violazione presunta dei contenuti online e il blocco di domini web e relativi server senza dovuto processo. Senza questi poteri, il copyright semplicemente collassa.

Ma fortunatamente questo modello capitalistico è condannato, a prescindere dal risultato dell’azione legale della EFF (e mi auguro che passi!). Anche allo stato attuale le tecnologie progrediscono così rapidamente che film e canzoni private del DRM solitamente compaiono sui siti torrent lo stesso giorno in cui escono sul mercato, mentre la condivisione dei file per i più giovani è una cosa scontata. L’idea che le protezioni si debbano aggirare si sta ora allargando all’editoria accademica grazie a SciHub. Quanto passerà prima che si diffonda ai ricambi originali e ai software di diagnostica?

Come sempre, come dice l’amico Charles Johnson del C4SS (“Counter-Economic optimism,” Rad Geek People’s Daily, 7 febbraio 2009), un’oncia di aggiramento vale una libbra di lobby.

Commentary
Of Flags and Football

The football hooligans are at it again but this time instead of street riots and violence, they are raising hell with flags and fundraisers. With the recent news of Colin Kaepernick refusing to stand during the U.S. national anthem and Gabby Douglas not placing her hand over her heart during the anthem at the 2016 Summer Olympics, the question of whether or not politics and sports should mix has been on a lot of minds. While it is really only a debate over etiquette in the United States, the mixing of politics and sports is actually a punishable offense in Ireland.

During a recent soccer game between Ireland’s Celtics and Israel’s Hapoel Be’er Sheva, fans of the Celtic team waved Palestinian flags and cheered on the Celtics against the Israelis. This obviously carried with it an overt political message of not only standing against the Hapoel Be’er Sheva in the Champions League qualifier, but also against Israel’s violent oppression of the Palestinian people. For this action, the Celtic Football Club was fined by the Union of European Football Associations (UEFA) for violating their ban against, “gestures, words, objects or any other means to transmit any message that is not fit for a sports event, particularly messages that are of a political, ideological, religious, offensive or provocative nature.”

In response, a group of fans calling themselves the Green Brigade set up a crowdfunding campaign on GoFundMe to #MatchTheFineForPalestine. Together they have collected more than £130,000 to donate to Palestinian charities, including Medical Aid Palestine, which provides medical care for those injured or harmed “by conflict, occupation and displacement”, and the Lajee Centre, an effort to help Palestinian children in the Aida refugee camp start their very own soccer team to compete in the Bethlehem Youth League, which they have affectionately dubbed the Aida Celtic as a thank you.

Since then, many Palestinians have filmed thankful response videos for the Celtic show of support in defiance of the UEFA, proving that sports and politics can mix in ways that are helpful for those who are oppressed by governments worldwide, “from Ferguson to Palestine,” as the saying goes, even if it pisses off a few overly-patriotic sports fans in the process. Oh, and to add the icing to the cake: the Celtics swept the floor with the Hapoel Be’er Sheva, beating the Israeli team 5-2 in the home victory. And soon, thanks to their Irish comrades, I’m sure we’ll see the Aida Celtic winning a number of symbolic victories as well on their way towards freedom.

Italian, Stateless Embassies
Ripensare i Mercati: Anarchismo, Capitalismo e lo Stato

[Di Chris Shaw. Originale pubblicato su Center for a Stateless Society il 31 maggio 2016 con il titolo Rethinking Markets: Anarchism, Capitalism, and the State. Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.]

Scarica una copia PDF dell’intero studio di Chris Shaw per C4SS: Rethinking Markets

Generalmente si immaginano i mercati come bastioni del capitalismo, qualcosa che unge le ruote che permettono l’accumulazione e l’organizzazione del capitale, che crea le relazioni di classe tipiche del moderno capitalismo, stabilisce vincenti e perdenti, e tramite il meccanismo della distruzione creativa e della competizione muove lavoratori e padroni come pedine. Tutto ciò rimescola la proprietà concentrandola in un numero di mani sempre più piccolo, mettendo i vincenti in alto in qualità di proprietari di mezzi di produzione e capitali, e i perdenti in basso in qualità di salariati e lumpenproletariat, sottoposti allo sfruttamento e al dominio.

Ma questa visione ignora le potenzialità dei mercati. I mercati non sono necessariamente strutture limitate al capitale o allo stato, ma sistemi formati e determinati da chi ci opera dentro, controllati e distribuiti volontariamente. Ovvero, uniti nella collettività e eterogeneità di un ordine sociale anarchico. Laddove per anarchico intendo “una tendenza ben definita nello sviluppo storico dell’uomo, tendenza che, al contrario dell’autorità intellettuale di tutte le istituzioni clericali e governative, lotta perché si esprimano liberamente, senza costrizioni, tutte le energie individuali e sociali della vita”.

Da questo punto di vista, io considero i mercati un esempio di arrangiamento anarchico, che permette ai suoi attori, in quanto liberi ed eguali, di determinare il proprio futuro e raggiungere obiettivi e valori. Questa definizione, per sua natura, richiede la liberazione dei mercati dai ceppi dello stato e del capitalismo. Questi ultimi offrono una percezione di sé come di qualcosa affine, rispettivamente, al governativo e al clericale. L’istituzione statale comprende il regno della legge e dell’ordine, e il monopolio della forza, essenziali al mantenimento dell’istituto della proprietà privata e delle relazioni di potere del capitalismo. Il capitalismo, al pari delle istituzioni clericali, crea coscienze, patologie e ideologie che permettono il mantenimento delle stesse organizzazioni capitalistiche. Assieme, queste due istituzioni formano la struttura socio-economica del mondo moderno.

Queste due potentissime forze, quella clericale e quella governativa, sono un fenomeno recente. Io spero che nella mia analisi si possa vedere la via verso un cambiamento di questo sistema, qualcosa che permetta di passare da un sistema di sfruttamento ad uno di collaborazione volontaria, ad un’economia che sia parte del sociale. Un’economia eterogenea e decentralizzata. Come dice Paul Mason, “È più che possibile mettere su gli elementi del nuovo sistema, molecola dopo molecola, all’interno del vecchio. Nelle cooperative, nel credito cooperativo, nelle reti da pari a pari, nelle imprese acefale e nelle economie parallele e subculturali questi elementi già esistono.”

Italian, Stateless Embassies
Perché gli “Adulti nella Stanza” Sono Così Odiosi?

[Di Kevin Carson. Originale pubblicato su Center for a Stateless Society il 14 settembre 2016 con il titolo Why Are the “Adults in the Room” So Awful? Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.]

È normale sentire centristi che, opponendosi agli “estremisti di destra e sinistra”, si definiscono “adulti razionali” in grado di fare un compromesso e concludere qualcosa. La metafora dell’“adulto razionale” è spesso associata alla “Teoria del Ferro di Cavallo”, secondo cui buon senso e ragionevolezza appartengono al centro politico e ogni deviazione significa “estremismo” tanto più accentuato quanto più ci si allontana dal centro.

Perciò Michael Arnovitz (“Thinking About Hillary — A Plea for Reason,” The Policy, 12 giugno) sostiene che, essendo sinistra e destra critiche verso la Clinton per ragioni opposte e reciprocamente incoerenti, entrambe sono nel torto; e presumibilmente questo significa che, eliminando le differenze, entrambe le parti si ritrovano nel grembo di mamma orsa, esattamente al centro, nel “giusto”.

Il problema è che il centrismo come tale non ha contenuto. Non significa nulla in un sistema bipartitico, se non in relazione al territorio conteso tra i due principali partiti in un dato momento. La realtà, però, è che le posizioni dei due partiti non si integrano né si escludono a vicenda. E la stragrande maggioranza dei temi su cui concordano (presupposto strutturale fondamentale del capitalismo clientelare e dell’egemonia mondiale americana) non vengono mai alla luce perché neanche sono messi in discussione.

Le “due parti” riflettono l’ampiezza del disaccordo accettabile all’interno di una classe di governo che condivide gran parte degli interessi e delle ipotesi. A dire il vero, basta parlare di classe di governo, o dire che la struttura di base del nostro sistema riflette gli interessi di questa classe di governo, perché Chris Matthews (giornalista televisivo, es) precipiti nella disperazione come davanti ad un branco di fissati.

Questo significa che sia “centrismo” che “estremismo” sono definiti in termini di status quo. Un centrista è uno che accetta implicitamente la normalità e la legittimità del sistema esistente e della sua struttura di potere. Qualunque critica radicale e strutturale che indaghi sul ruolo degli interessi di classe o di razza, sul sesso privilegiato o sull’esercizio di un potere irresponsabile nella creazione di tale legittimità, è “estremismo”.

È considerato “moderato” tutto ciò che aderisce, più o meno profondamente, ad un sistema considerato normale, naturale e inevitabile nella sua natura fondamentale, mentre è più o meno “estremista” tutto ciò che si allontana da ciò.

Qualunque “riforma” che si limiti a modifiche superficiali di una struttura di potere senza cambiarne le fondamenta, e che possa essere messa in pratica dalla stessa classe di persone che gestisce il sistema presente, è considerata “moderata”. Qualunque proposta che implichi il cambiamento della struttura di potere dalle fondamenta, togliendo potere all’attuale classe di governo, è detta “radicale”.

Chi analizza radicalmente la struttura dell’attuale stato delle cose non pensa che “è così e basta”, o che “è quello che la maggioranza vuole”. Vede l’esercizio del potere per quello che è: qualcosa che va a profitto di qualcuno a spese di altri. Per questo è etichettato “estremista” dai “centristi” che hanno il potere.

Alcuni dei centristi più convinti, come l’untuoso Chris Mattews, liquidano queste critiche strutturali di fondo come “complottismi”. Nel 2010, durante un suo programma, un ospite contrario sia ai nuovi scanner aeroportuali che all’alternativa della perquisizione personale disse che gli scanner erano inefficaci e che molti funzionari di alto livello della Homeland Security possedevano azioni delle società che producevano le macchine. Matthews quasi rischiò l’infarto nel denunciare questo “complottismo”, e ciò nonostante i suoi spot su MSNBC che citavano Eisenhower e il Complesso Militare-Industriale.

Alla fine ci ritroviamo con un’élite di governanti che si limitano ad una gamma di alternative che vanno da M a N, governanti succubi di quello che C. Wright Mills chiamava “Realismo Strambo”. Come dice Buckminster Fuller, loro cercano di risolvere i problemi con la stessa mentalità che li ha creati. Ivan Illich descrive l’approccio di queste persone come il “tentativo di risolvere una crisi ricorrendo all’escalation.”

In quest’ultimo caso, un buon esempio è la pianificazione urbana, che cerca di risolvere il problema del traffico causato dalla monocultura dell’automobile costruendo nuove autostrade e raccordi… che non fanno altro che creare altro traffico da e verso i nuovi sobborghi e i shopping center che spuntano ogni due metri sulle nuove autostrade finanziate dallo stato. Oppure la sicurezza nazionale, che affronta il terrorismo (ovvero la reazione a precedenti interventi dell’impero) con nuovi interventi, che generano ancora più terrorismo.

Oltre a considerarsi gli unici “adulti nella stanza”, quelli che sanno cosa fare e non si tirano indietro, i centristi si vantano di essere gli unici “veramente” umani e idealisti. Citando Michael Lofgren:

Il lato positivo del realismo strambo è che la solita prudenza che consiglia di evitare le guerre può essere definita tanto come un sentimentalismo sciatto e irrealistico quanto come il menefreghismo di una superpotenza in un mondo pericoloso. Nella sua forma raffinata, il realismo strambo si camuffa da idealismo: le invasioni militari che mirano davvero alle missioni umanitarie, diffondono la democrazia o tutelano la pace. In questi casi, il realista strambo può arrivare a toni moralistici: Esistono persone assennate che vogliono che Saddam Hussein resti presidente dell’Iraq? O Bashar el Assad della Siria? O l’Hitler del giorno?

Il centrismo è totalmente incapace di autocritica perché non si riconosce come parte di un’ideologia legittimante. Ogni sistema di potere ha in sé un apparato riproduttivo culturale che tende a creare quel genere di “risorse umane” che accettano come normale e scontata la struttura di potere in cui vivono.

Essendo parte di un’ideologia legittimante, la teoria centrista del ferro di cavallo è responsabile, come nota l’amico @NerbieDansers su Twitter, “dell’occultamento costante della violenza di cui il centro, moderato e razionale, è responsabile”, violenza inversamente proporzionale “alla distanza che la separa da un mitico e pacifico centro”. Non è solo che il sistema rappresentato dal centro è “responsabile” della violenza; è che la creazione e il mantenimento del sistema di potere che i centristi considerano normale richiede un uso massiccio della violenza.

L’attuale sistema non è un fatto naturale o inevitabile che “semplicemente accade”, o qualcosa che si fa perché è la cosa più sensata da fare. Ha un’origine e una storia sua; e (chiedendo scusa a Marx) è una storia scritta a lettere di sangue e fuoco. Così ho scritto altrove:

Badate che lo stato corporativo non è un fenomeno spontaneo o naturale. È il prodotto del potere politico imposto consciamente e massicciamente negli ultimi 150 anni.

A partire dalla Gilded Age, lo stato è intervenuto pesantemente nel mercato per creare una società dominata da organizzazioni gigantesche e centralizzate, come le agenzie governative e le società per azioni, per poi proseguire con l’istruzione pubblica centralizzata, le grandi università e le fondazioni no-profit. Quando questa economia industriale centralizzata, creata e sostenuta dallo stato, andò in crisi per eccesso di capacità produttiva e calo dei consumi, lo stato si diede da fare per tenerla in piedi. Tra le altre cose, lo stato alimentò un’economia nazionale incentrata sulla spesa pubblica per assorbire i capitali in eccesso tramite enormi progetti di spesa pubblica, come il sistema autostradale, il complesso militare-industriale che assorbiva grosse fette della produzione industriale in eccesso, e una politica estera mirante a combinare i mercati e le risorse planetarie per poi usarle come discarica per i capitali e le produzioni in eccesso.

Quando lo stato impose questo sistema, ci fu una grossa resistenza da parte della popolazione in generale, che non accettava la situazione. Dal 1870 circa alla prima guerra mondiale, gran parte della popolazione rifiutò come normale una situazione che prevedeva un loro lavoro salariato dipendente da grosse strutture gerarchiche autoritarie. Movimenti come quello populista degli agricoltori e i Knights of Labor erano poco meno che insurrezioni, mentre misure come la repressione dopo i fatti di Haymarket e la soppressione dello sciopero alla Pullman voluta da Cleveland furono una vera e propria controrivoluzione.

Soffocata l’insurrezione, i colletti bianchi che controllavano le strutture gerarchiche statali e corporative adottarono un sistema educativo che mirava a produrre persone che accettassero come normale la nuova struttura di potere. Il movimento ufficiale per l’istruzione pubblica, i sostenitori del “100% americanismo”, e altro simile, puntavano a creare “risorse umane adulterate” che accettassero autorità e gerarchia come la norma, “adeguandosi” agli ordini degli uomini di apparato seduti ad una scrivania: che fosse un’aula scolastica, una fabbrica o un ufficio governativo.

Ma non c’è bisogno di guardare alla storia per capire quanta violenza è contenuta nel sistema che questi “centristi raziocinanti” danno per scontato. Il sistema necessita di molta violenza per preservarsi. Basta prendere una copia di KILLING HOPE, di William Blum, e vedere la serie di invasioni, governi rovesciati, sostegni a golpe militari e squadroni della morte operata dagli Stati Uniti dopo la seconda guerra mondiale. Anche il consenso bipartisan sulla politica estera prevalente negli ultimi decenni è stato definito in termini di legittimità dell’interventismo. E anche i cosiddetti “liberal” condividono l’idea secondo cui, come dice Chomski, “l’America è il padrone del mondo”.

I “centristi raziocinanti”, dal canto loro, sono soliti appoggiare spudoratamente questo consenso e gli interventi sanguinari che ne seguono. I notiziari sono pieni di esempi di quale pattume umano siano in realtà questi “adulti nella stanza”.

Su Business Insider, Josh Barro (“Donald Trump  and the GOP’s crisis,” 3 maggio) contrappone Trump a “adulti nella stanza” come Jeb Bush. Secondo Barro, i primi tre tradimenti di Trump delle presunte ortodossie della classe benefattrice sono: “l’opposizione al libero commercio, la promessa di proteggere dai tagli i diritti acquisiti, [e] la messa in dubbio delle alleanze militari americane.” La quarta, ovvero l’opposizione alla crescente accettazione dei transgender, è comune a gran parte dei repubblicani. In pratica, la differenza principale tra gli “adulti nella stanza” repubblicani e Trump consiste nel suo rifiuto dell’ortodossia neoliberale riguardo l’egemonia americana sulla politica mondiale e l’ordine corporativo che tale egemonia impone, non le sue odiose idee in campo sociale.

Neera Tanden (capo del Center for American Progress e alleato di Hillary Clinton, che lo ha nominato al Comitato per la Piattaforma del Partito Democratico) dichiarò nel 2013 su Twitter a proposito della Siria che “non voglio essere il poliziotto mondiale, ma un mondo senza poliziotti è un pericolo. Credo che gli Stati Uniti siano l’ultimo adulto nella stanza rimasto.”

La stessa Clinton, ideale perfetto di adulto nella stanza per gran parte dei centristi, si rifà a personaggi come Rahm Emanuel, che da capo del Comitato per la Campagna Nazionale Democratica del 2006 negò i fondi elettorali a quei candidati che si opponevano alla guerra d’Iraq, e come sindaco di Chicago ha offerto copertura politica ad un centro di detenzione illegale della polizia e ha promosso le scuole charter (private ma con fondi pubblici, es) come nessun’altra città eccetto New Orleans. Fu lei a votare l’autorizzazione alla guerra di Bush contro l’Iraq, a rigurgitare le sue bugie a proposito delle “armi di distruzione di massa” al fine di preparare la propria carriera politica. Coerentemente, come segretario di stato di Obama, fu la sostenitrice più convinta dell’intervento militare come strumento politico; fu la voce più influente, dietro la riluttanza di Obama, favorevole all’intervento in Libia, e ancora oggi si rammarica di non averlo persuaso ad intervenire massicciamente in Siria. E recentemente, non solo ha difeso Netanyahu dall’accusa di aver commesso crimini contro l’umanità a Gaza, ma ha promesso di portare le relazioni dell’America con Netanyahu (non semplicemente con Israele, ma con Netanyahu) ad “un livello più alto”.

E più di recente ha dedicato un intero comizio (dopo aver elogiato chi la ospitava, l’associazione dei reduci, nata come struttura paramilitare di destra che combatteva i sindacalisti di sinistra nelle strade) all’autocelebrazione untuosa dicendo che “gli Stati Uniti si oppongono ai dittatori” e promettendo che avrebbe continuato a sostenere la più grande armata mondiale per fronteggiare tutte le “minacce” del mondo esterno. Questo nonostante il suo appoggio fattivo ad un colpo di stato della destra militare in Honduras, e nonostante sia orgogliosa dell’approvazione ricevuta dal suo compagno di vacanze Henry Kissinger, a sua volta parte attiva nel rovesciamento di Allende da parte di Pinochet, e responsabile dell’ondata di dittature militari in tutto il Sud America, oltre che dell’invasione e del genocidio operato a Timor Est.

Quanto alle “minacce”, Tanden e la Clinton condividono le stesse ipotesi operative di Henry Kissinger e del resto dell’establishment bipartisan della National Security; un insieme di ipotesi riassunte più su da Chomski: “l’America è il padrone del mondo”. Dunque spetta all’America stabilire unilateralmente di quante forze armate necessita un paese per le proprie “legittime necessità difensive”, mentre le proprie necessità “difensive” sono definite in termini di capacità di attaccare ovunque, invadendo e sconfiggendo qualunque paese. Sarebbe compito dell’America dire cosa è o non è “aggressione” in qualunque parte del mondo, definire “minaccia” la capacità di difendersi da un attacco americano, e definire “difesa” l’accerchiamento con basi militari offensive di un paese dall’altra parte del mondo.

Gli Stati Uniti sono la potenza egemonica che sostiene un ordine politico, economico e militare globale così come stabilito alla fine della seconda guerra mondiale, ordine che serve ad incorporare i mercati e le risorse naturali del Sud del Mondo con i bisogni del capitale corporativo occidentale; e, nelle parole dell’élite della National Security, chiunque osi sfidare quest’ordine uscendone è una “minaccia”.

In nome del sostegno a questo ordine globale contro le “minacce”, dalla seconda guerra mondiale in poi gli Stati Uniti hanno invaso più paesi e/o rovesciato più governi di ogni altro impero nel corso della storia, appoggiando colpi di stato e squadre della morte con un bilancio di milioni di morti.

Questo è ciò che hanno fatto i vostri “adulti nella stanza”. Hanno eretto un sistema di potere, prima in patria e poi nel mondo, con l’intento principale di estrarre pluslavoro da noi e alimentare i redditieri da loro rappresentati. Nell’imporre questo sistema di potere hanno causato milioni di morti, e non hanno problemi di coscienza a causarne altre. Gli “adulti nella stanza” sono mostri. È ora di togliere loro questo giocattolo, lo stato americano, che loro hanno usato per portare distruzione e caos nel mondo. E che nessuno se ne serva più.

Commentary
Free Chelsea Manning Today!

Since the early days of President Barack Obama’s first term, the United States has pursued a high-octane policy of punishing whistleblowers to the fullest extent of the law. If an individual can be identified as having been the source of a leak, and if that individual falls under the jurisdiction of the US or its military, they can be prosecuted for crimes against the State and “national security.”

It is in this atmosphere that the American Civil Liberties Union announced that they were calling for a full, unconditional pardon for Edward Snowden, the former intelligence industry contractor who leaked classified information about the National Security Agency’s wiretapping and data collection activities to Glenn Greenwald, the UK Guardian and the Washington Post.

“Thanks to Edward Snowden’s act of conscience, we’ve made historic strides in our fight for surveillance reform and improved cybersecurity,” ACLU Executive Director Anthony D. Romero said last week. “That’s why today, ahead of this week’s release of the Oliver Stone movie ‘Snowden,’ we’re unveiling a major effort calling on President Obama to pardon the NSA whistleblower.”

Some weren’t happy with the ACLU’s new call to action, including the editorial board for the newspaper that helped to publish his leaks, the Washington Post, who claimed his leaks hurt national security overseas. Needless to say, the ACLU has created a lively debate around the issue.

Oddly missing from the discussion over Snowden’s pardon prospects, however, is any mention of Chelsea Manning’s situation.

Back in July, the 28-year-old whistleblower attempted to take her own life while serving her 35-year sentence at Ft. Leavenworth Correctional Barracks for violating the Espionage Act, the same early-20th-century law the United States wants to use against Snowden. In early September, she went on hunger strike in protest of her treatment; Manning said in a statement that she has not been receiving appropriate treatment for her gender dysphoria, including being allowed to grow her hair out, and that prison officials have been subjecting her to a campaign of bullying.

Today, I have decided that I am no longer going to be bullied by this prison – or by anyone within the US government,” Manning said. “I have asked for nothing but the dignity and respect – that I once actually believed would be provided for – afforded to any living human being.”

This, in fact, is why Manning should be let go – why all prisons should be emptied, as a matter of fact, but given the scope of the argument, specifically why she should be set free. As long as she is a prisoner, the dignity and respect she desires will continue to be held just out of her reach. The state has taken that from her, on purpose, as a message to other would-be whistleblowers.

Chelsea Manning was convicted of a crime against the state during an active conflict. In a sense, a strange, twisted sense, she could be considered a war criminal. But what she did helped bring closure to the families of slain Reuters photojournalists Saeed Chmagh and Namir Noor-Eldeen – the two were killed by an American airstrike in Baghdad in 2007 – and helped US citizens and individuals around the world understand the extent of the US military’s reckless adventure in Afghanistan and Iraq more generally.

Her status as a “war criminal” is an utter joke, when compared characters like Henry Kissinger – Hillary Clinton’s bestie and the man behind such illustrious atrocities as the Khmer Rouge’s killing fields in Cambodia, Augusto Pinochet’s coup and authoritarian stranglehold over Chile, and just about the entire long, bloody conflict of the Vietnam War – who continue to walk free.

And yet, Manning is being forced to pay a debt she shouldn’t owe — years of her life, peace of mind, the ability to walk freely and associate with whom she pleases – because she had a shift in conscience while serving one of the largest forces of murder and oppression on the planet.

Manning ended her hunger strike on Sept. 13, after receiving notice that military doctors had approved her for sex reassignment surgery. Since then, and aside from Wikileaks founder Julian Assange tweeting that he’d turn himself in if President Obama granted Manning clemency, the media has been as close to silent as they can be about her.

If we are going to rally around Edward Snowden and start a campaign dedicated to getting him a presidential pardon, it is only right that the same be extended to Chelsea Manning. Free her today, unconditionally!

Feature Articles
General Equivalences and the Freed Market

The capitalist market system is defined by the strictures of wage labour relations and the regulatory mechanisms, which are the used for the valorisation of capital and the commodity production which maintains, expands and homogenises this valorisation. These are the inevitable products of capitalist exchange relations and the creation of a general equivalence in which generic commodities, produced by capital through the wage labour relation, are circulated. For the purpose of these exchanges (some of which maintain the manufacturing and production bases of the classes of capital, and others which engender the final movement of commodities into their form as consumables) markets are used as mechanisms of distribution and sale. The extent of capitalist relations becomes universalisable in such an homogenised, controlled system. States, through their capacity to regulate market transactions and mediate the class relations of wage labourers and the owners of the means of production, create regulatory apparatuses which engender the recreation and revaluation of capital through a series of metamorphoses where relations are changed, markets are restructured and the fundamental germ of capitalism, that of the dominance of capital and its control of the means of production, are maintained and even boosted.

Out of these processes there forms a system of general equivalence, where the plethora of subjective values that work in variable economic systems are subjected to the increasing stringencies of capitalist valuations. Historical processes of accumulation pull alternative production systems into the wider capitalist structure, stripping down subjective valuation and pushing it into peripheral concerns. General equivalence becomes the major way through which commodities in production and for consumption become valued and homogenised, with alternative cost structures becoming either subsidised, externalised or minimised.

Capitalism is therefore the creation of equivalence within commodity production and the use of labour-power, with a basic hierarchy of control of the wage-earning classes maintained via systematised state intervention and control. The intermixing of the classes of capital and the bureaucratic classes of government becomes an inevitability which pushes for more control through capitalist means, and for the uprooting and destruction of various forms of traditional modes of life and alternative forms of socio-economic relations. There develops “the separation of labour-power from all its conditions of existence. The mode of life of the wage-earning class then suffers a deep degradation”[1]. Such exigencies shape the historical character of capitalism and the development of private property as a reality rather than an intellectual abstraction. Whether it be the enclosures throughout much of Europe from the late Middle Ages to the creation of huge infrastructure in America which expanded capitalist economies of scale, processes of accumulation have sucked huge areas of socio-economic relations into the homogenous field of value and the field of general equivalence.

Freed markets in the anarchist sense have a distinct relation to the processes of general equivalence. While capitalist markets have the need to constantly expand to re-engender the valorisation of capital through generating movements away from the tendency of the rate of profit to fall, the dynamics of freed markets generate the natural decentralisation of economic activity and the value it creates. Profit is the not the guaranteed means of economic activity, nor even its most desired faculty, while capital as an economic reality is varied, truly heterogeneous and almost impossible to concentrate outside the mechanisms of state regulation. Monopolised capital in its monetary form or in its concentration amongst the wage-earning class becomes untenable when the general equivalence of capitalist relations is ended by the ability for individuals (removed from their class structures) to act on their innate desires and subjective preferences. “Freed from the oppressive tensions of capitalism we would surely prefer to turn such focus on say crafting baskets or writing poems rather than neurotically calculating and re-calculating the week’s remaining expenses or the quickest trip across town”[2].

Through this essay I intend to contrast the existence of the dynamics of general equivalence within capitalism with the theoretical and interstitial potentials of freed markets. Freed markets encompass so much more than the conceptions of capitalism. They can be seen as the totality of voluntary socio-economic relations which require reciprocal exchange and the movement of subjective values. Further from this, freed markets can act as a dynamic variable in opposition to both the objectivities of the state and the coercive power of existing capitalism. “It is precisely through not simplifying our desires into a form parsable by CEOs, politicians, and general assemblies, but instead embracing their infinite diversity and potency that we can begin to make traction against the forces that need visibility and human interchangeability to control us”[3]. Humanity’s needs and preferences are extremely variable and complex, open to a multitude of value judgments that aren’t codified into simple concepts like profit or capital. But it is precisely capitalism and its socio-economic energies, through the homogeneous field of value and the systems of general equivalences, that produces these simplistic tendencies. Instead of a variable, dynamic economic system that provides complex relations of abundance and scarcity and produces individualistic and collective productive arrangements, there is a Weberian “struggle for economic existence, whereby the formation of prices is a struggle for dominance, with money as the main weapon for such a struggle”[4].

Particular advocates of capitalist markets will declare that the idea of a general equivalence pervading the exchanges and transactions of capitalism is an impossibility due to the fact that human desires and beliefs are subjective in their capacities. Yet such a view is tending to the position that in unfree markets the actual subjective desires of individuals in all their multiplicity is in any way possible. In the unfree markets that exist in the capitalist framework, the Weberian axioms of action (which defined some of the basic concepts of purposive human action) become defined by one of their parameters, that of the economistic view. Weber identified four particular types of action within an economic society. “Value-rational actions, whereby action is taken because it leads to a valued goal, and ignores other consequences of attaining this goal; affectual action, which is an action driven by emotion; traditional action, where something is done because it is what is usually done”[5] and instrumentally rational action, which is the “exercise of an actor’s control over resources which is in its main impulse oriented towards economic ends”[6]. Under capitalism, instrumentally rational action, defined by “the conception of the profit motive and the idea that goods are bought based on a rational, cost-benefit analysis”[7], becomes the dominant mode of economic thinking and acting. Resources come to mean the genericism of capital, both as constant capital (resources, raw materials, etc.) and as variable capital (wage labour), which come together to form the basis of the wider socio-economy.

Within this wider field of value defined by the economistic view of action as seen under the capitalist conceptions of capital, the homogeneous field of value and the idea of the general equivalence are developed as mainstays of capitalist social relations. “In order for the commensurability of commodities to be completely defined, it is necessary to know the unit by which value is measured”[8]. Such a measure of value comes from the capacity for commodities to fuel continued economic growth and with it the valorisation of capital, and for other commodities to be consumed by the wage labourers whose value is extracted in the production process.

The wage is generally conceived as the marker of said value as it is the ability through which final-end products are able to be consumed, thus validating the capitalist production process. However, in the fluid economic relations which have developed between the wage-earning classes and the classes of capital, debt has developed as another force of value equivalence through mechanisms of privatised Keynesianism. In modern capitalism, with wages having stagnated relative to both productivity increases and the inflationary increases in living costs, there has been an amplifying need to maintain the valorisation of capital through the consumption of final-end products. New forms of monetary capital have been created which rely on the presence of debt instruments to continue to uphold current levels of consumption, pushing wage-earners into using mortgages, credit cards and other debt-and-interest instruments which, as well as maintaining consumption ratios, provide a new regulatory force that recreates the wage labour relation and provides new avenues of profit which capital can exploit. These new relations of production will be fleshed out later in the essay.

The homogeneous field of value is thus defined by the dynamics of wage-earning and profit-making, with the production of commodities being one capacity through which such antagonistic relations are regulated and maintained. The heterogeneity of values which inform freed markets in their production and distribution decisions are quashed under the regulative auspices of capitalist production and control. Further, this homogeneous field of value leads to particular nuances which favour the preservation of capital over that of wage labour.

Capital perceives value not in the destruction of the end-product through consumption, but through a “metamorphoses of value”. “For the capitalist the pattern of metamorphosis is inverted. It is transformed from C-M-C into M-C-M”[9], with the social relations of capital needing constant regulatory intervention to maintain this procedure. For the owners of the means of production to maintain their dominance, there is a consistent need to valorise capital, as well as allow for processes of devalorisation and revaluation which allows for the reconstruction of the dynamics of capital. Without the market being able to act competitively by destroying profit and equalising relations of capital and labour, the capitalist classes use the state as a tool of accumulation and valorisation. Through the state, the wage labour relation and all its contradictions are maintained. A huge set of regulatory apparatuses are constructed, aptly defined by Tucker and Carson in the five monopolies which maintain the power of capitalist firms and capital-owners. The monopolies of money, land, intellectual property, protectionism and communications and transport infrastructures serve to maintain the dominance of capital. Such monopolies construct these fields of general equivalence by continuously expanding the means of capital accumulation and removing alternative forms of productive capacity from the realms of reality. Entry barriers are erected which limit the actual processes of capital from reaching the wage-earning classes, with distribution of income being a relation of capitalism which furthers its valorisation instead of being a true market distribution which opens competitive avenues and rewards innovation instead of monopolisation.

Wage labour becomes a cog in the valorisation of capital, itself affected by the homogenisation of value. The wage-earning classes are treated as another commodity, adding to the value of production. This division between capital and labour “arises from a qualitative difference in the positions of the two social classes vis-a-vis the conditions of production”[10], with labour as the subordinate element which has no access to either the true regulative powers of the state or the transformational capacities of markets and capital movement. However certain regulations do trickle down to the working classes, as in some of the legislation that developed out the New Deal. Yet the effect of this is not the transformation of the positions of the working classes but rather the maintenance of capitalist social relations. “Capital is not a thing because it is a definite social relationship and the standpoint of capital and wage labour is the same because both are perverted forms of social reproduction”[11].

The processes of general equivalence then comes out of these relations. General equivalence is defined by capitalist production processes and the ability for wage labourers to access commodities through consumption. “The law of value, or the general law of equivalence, is the formal representation of the process of homogenization of economic objects. Its field is the general circulation of commodities as the homogeneous social space”[12] of wage labour and its concomitant social relations. Commodities are the result of productive capacities where the economistic value (as defined through instrumentally rational action) is the most prized part of any production process or the consumables it produces. The spaces of capitalist value that are defined around this specific conception of action produces an economic reality from which social relations and the collectivisation of labour by capital are produced. The state acts as the arbiter of these social relations, allowing for their maintenance and recreation through multiple cycles of accumulation. General equivalence is fundamentally the capability for alternative socio-economic relations to be crushed under the dominance of economistic conceptions of action which are defined by profit and the wage labour relation. Commodities are stripped of any value judgment, and homogenously defined in relation to their capacity to be consumed or to valorise capital. The productive relations which Colin Ward saw developing in a self-employed society of worker ownership are unable to be realised as wage labour is codified into the regulatory mechanisms which maintain capitalism. General equivalence is the means through which subjective value is simplified, codified and destroyed, as productive relations are made evermore strict and immovable. Even during crises, capital acts to allow for the recreation of production systems and wage labour relations so as to recreate surplus value extraction and the maintained field of homogeneous value.

But how does such value, and the productive systems which come from it and create commodities in a system of general equivalence, develop. As already mentioned, productive systems have a fluid character which allows for their recreation. Capitalism is defined as a morphological system, “in other words a space structured by relationships subject to the principles of qualitative difference and unequal influence”[13]. Ruptures and reconstructions are a necessary part of this system as without them the antagonistic character of labour and capital becomes too much. Ruptures are needed as a pressure valve. Through these ruptures there is also the requirement of regulatory systems which maintain the basic wage labour system and the field of general equivalence in commodity production. The state, as an arbiter of relations, is a major factor in the creation of these regulatory systems and the forms of accumulation they allow for. Whether it be from early primitive accumulation, through to the extensive regime of accumulation and its productive systems, and onto periods of intensive accumulation which specifically relied on a significant paradigm of consumption, the state has played a massive role in concentrating the interests of capital and creating new productive capacities which soak up excess product and maintain the variables of varied wage labour relations.

The most obvious and earliest form that this state-capitalist intervention took was in the relations and actions of primitive accumulation. “Primitive accumulation is a constantly reproduced accumulation, be it in terms of the renewed separation of new populations from the means of production and subsistence, or in terms of the reproduction of the wage relation in the ‘established’ relations of capital”[14]. Historically speaking this was the process of disenfranchisement, where agricultural labourers and those with access to common lands were subsequently made into urban labourers for the developing factory systems of the Industrial Revolution. It can be seen as the early development of both extensive and intensive forms of accumulation in the processes of capital valorisation. The extensive land monopolies of states which led to massive transport and communications infrastructures, skewing economic relations away from petty commodity production and decentralised, variable market activity and pushing these relations into the realm of national and international economies of scale, can be seen as a more modern form of primitive accumulation, as it soaks up existing capital and allows for its transformation and metamorphoses into new forms of economic activity.

The early English enclosures, being the most prescient form of historical primitive accumulation, expropriated huge amounts of land, in particular common land, into the hands of established landowners who had preferential access to both parliamentary representation and the English court system. What developed was a huge class of landless labourers who were dispossessed of common rights to land. “A Parliament of landowners was naturally tender of landed property…. The landed class, taken as a whole, and Parliament as its legislative body, failed to ensure that the essential modernization of a large part of English agriculture did not leave in its wake a trail of dispossessed”[15]. The parliamentary actions which helped engender the early enclosures were almost entirely on the side of established large landowners, many of whom were created out of the effective expropriation and nationalisation of monastic lands during the Tudorian era. Cottagers, farm labourers and those who relied to a huge extent on the existing common lands became “a trail of dispossessed”, removed from their natural rights to subsistence and survival. “The old communal system kept many small men in being, but with the prop of the common removed, numbers must have found it very difficult, and in some instances impossible, to survive”[16].

During the early period of the Industrial Revolution, such enclosures were extremely profitable for the developing factory system. With 2 million acres of land becoming enclosed under the Enclosure acts of 1850, the privatisation of land and open fields by and through the state led to an early landless proletariat. Poverty increased substantially, with poor relief expenditure swelling, and access to survival which the commons represented was cut-off. “The laboring people” became “crowded together in new places of desolation, the so-called industrial towns of England; the country people had been dehumanized into slum dwellers; the family was on the road to perdition; and large parts of the country were rapidly disappearing under the slack and scrap heaps vomited forth from the ‘satanic mills'”[17]. According to Ashton, “there was, especially in London and the South, a large supply of unskilled, unemployed people who were a charge on the parishes”[18] whom became the backbone of factory labour, particular in the cotton mills of the North of England. As Albert Jay Nock noted, the state was the primary conduit for such land expropriations and enclosures. Populations of individuals were removed from common land, and made cheap and available as labourers to be regulated and strictly controlled by the relations of capitalism. Thus not only is there the early use of state power for the development of capitalist economic expansion, but also the early use of said power for the regulation of wage labour relations. Wage labourers were placed under the control of the poor laws and an internal passport system, which regulated a labourers’ movements and their ability to choose work. The choice now became either the factory mills or the workhouses. ““The traditional unity of a Christian society,” writes Polanyi even from his secular Jewish perspective, “was giving place to a denial of responsibility on the part of the well-to-do for the condition of their fellows.” Or, as the Hammonds had put it: “the spirit of fellowship was dead””[19]. The traditional mores that defined the socio-economic relations of agricultural labour and the commons was utterly destroyed through the mechanisms of the state to benefit established landowners and the burgeoning capitalist systems of factories and intensive labour.

Much of later capitalist accumulation developed on the back of this system of land monopolisation and early wage labour regulation. European states also went through periods of enclosure and land accumulation, and in America there was the use of the state to develop massive transportation infrastructure which provided new outlets of economic growth, ending alternative relations of production and entrenching the wage labour relation in a country that didn’t have a European history of aristocracy and common land use. Instead, as Aglietta notes, America has a deep history of individualist political and economic thought, where the role of political economy is assigned this ideological baggage. Aglietta further goes on to theorise that the rapid rise of capitalist social relations in America is due to this individualist tendency. “All social activities were conceived as exchange relationships formed and unformed by the will of the contracting parties”[20]. Aglietta may well be right in his description, but I don’t believe he is in his theory. Rather, individualist doctrine was used and in many cases abused by centralised US court systems and political machines which relied on the legitimation of Jeffersonian rhetoric, much as Aglietta later points out. But such individualist tendencies do not explain the meteoric rise of the centralisation of capitalist relations into the wider political economy. Rather, it was the Hamiltonian mercantilist realities constructed by US governments and the industrial interests of the North, much of which were originally codified in the Constitution. State structures were always close-by and even integral in the development of American capitalism, whether in its legitimation through particular discourses or its destruction of alternative praxes of economic functioning. The Jeffersonian principles of independent agricultural labourers situated within local market structures and decentralised economies was fundamentally lost with the ratification of the Constitution, and the development of Hamiltonian economic constructions in the form of a central bank and widespread tariff system.

During the latter half of the 19th century, American capitalist relations gained a massive expansionary force in the form of mass infrastructure projects, in particular the construction of railways throughout much of the Midwest and South, dragging in economies previously defined by petty commodity production. Small-scale distribution systems were crushed by monopolistic distribution companies who could piggyback on the land monopolies granted to rail companies by the US government. Large industrial capacities and the ability to further regulate wage labourers for the interests of developing manufacturing and factory systems meant a move away from pure primitive accumulation to a system of extensive accumulation. Previous modes of production, such as a local foodstuffs system and small factories using independent labourers were transformed into an extensive expansion of infrastructure, factories and the mobility of labour. “The division of society (is) effected by classificatory and identificatory logic (which) operates on working time in production”[21]. Thus there is a move from classic conceptions of time, where labour-time is defined by natural characteristics of agricultural seasons and the needs of commoners and wage-earners, toward a systematised concept of time where things are done in relation to the demands of commodity production. In such a system industry is able to expand massively, usually on the back of huge state robbery through enclosures of land and transport monopolisation. Kropotkin noted such occurrences when large monolithic factory systems and manufacturing industries began to dominate smaller production outfits in the many industrialised economies of Europe and America. Primitive accumulation was overtaken by extensive accumulation.

Under general accumulation and previous primitive accumulation, the system of general equivalence begins to define both the production of commodities as homogeneous goods whose value is economistically determined through early mass production and the development of ever-expanding market economies, and the system of wage labour where labourers are treated as a collective whole, to be classified, hierarchalised and moved based on the demands of particular industries and capitals. However such a system meets natural limits due to the pre-existing social relations of wage labourers, which, while being transformed, have not wholly been removed as a construction of reality. Primitive accumulation had produced massive structural transformations but had only created and germinated an industrial system. Workers still held the knowledge of things like the commons and petty commodity production which provided more dignity and control. Such pre-existing relations limit the effectiveness of a consumer economy while there still remains the germ of resistance in the form of different socio-economic praxes.

A system of intensive accumulation is thus constructed which builds on the systems of industrial infrastructure developed under extensive accumulation. “The predominantly intensive regime of accumulation creates a new mode of life for the wage-earning class by establishing a logic that operates on the totality of time and space occupied or traversed by its individuals in daily life”[22]. A fundamental transformation of the wage-earning classes is enacted, with their productive relation to commodities fitting into the consumption relation which valorises capital. The field of general equivalence is fully enacted as the relations of capitalism, that of wage labour and capital, become emplaced within the generalities of capitalism and its production systems. The limits of extensive accumulation are overcome as wage labour is placed under the full regulative power of capital and entrenched in mass production systems which require constant inputs of capital and consumption, as witnessed in the production systems which developed around the time of the move toward intensive capital accumulation. These are Taylorism, Fordism and their successors.

Such forms of productive organisation enforce a new regulatory system on workers, building on past forms of accumulation and re-enforcing the system of general equivalence in the wider capitalist system. Wage labourers are fully subjected to the relations of capital and the needs of industry for constant consumption. Under Taylorism, there was the early development of the technical division of labour as wage labourers were increasingly individualised in their task roles and collectivised within workgroups under the supervision of bolstered management networks and team leaders. This form of organisation reached new heights under the systems of Fordism, as mechanisation was introduced leading to a further division of labour and an increase in the use of departmentalisation and management power. Worker autonomy, and collective working, were turned on their heads as the technical division produces a dialectical relation of increasing worker individualisation on the one hand and a collective realisation of wage labour on the other. Under these systems, productivity gains realised by labour are used for the purposes of capital valorisation and an increase in the extraction of surplus value. Wage labourers themselves are further homogenised as tools of capital accumulation, subject to the vagaries of capitalist discipline with no alternative modes of existence even provisionally available.

Later developments in production systems further such a dialectical relation of workers, with individualisation within the wage-earning classes and collectivisation under the auspices of capital both increasing. Productivity gains are increasingly divorced from wages and the collective means of labour organisation are destroyed by state intervention, limiting their influence and capabilities. Such was witnessed under Thatcher and Reagan during periods of deindustrialisation in Western countries. Under deindustrialisation, productivity has been completely divorced from wages, and the methods of production divorced from their consumption. Workers in developed countries are fully subjected to the consumption paradigm, and through new mechanisms the huge levels of internationalised overproduction are soaked up by forms of financialisation and state intervention. The forces of wage labour now inhabit an economy of services and minimal industry, with their wages determined by the output of international industry and the ability of workers to continue consumption patterns. Now with financialisation this also means the introduction of new methods of wage labour regulation in the form of a debt relation between banks, employers and labourers. Employers can afford to pay minimal wages completely divorced from productivity and even from living costs, with banks and other financial firms making the shortfall through forms of privatised Keynesianism. Mortgages, credit cards and other debt instruments maintain the consumption paradigm (and with it the valorisation of capital) and introduce another method of regulatory control as debt relations overtake industrial relations. “For the working and middle classes, they (mortgages) represent increased indebtedness due to a belief in homeownership. For global elites, they represent an opportunity for the continuation of the extraction of surplus value through financial markets”[23]. These classes of indebted individuals are now a widespread precariat, of part-time and low-wage workers and a class of unemployed surplus labour.

From the early interventions of primitive accumulation, through the expansion of capitalist relations under extensive accumulation, and onto the systems of intensive accumulation which reshaped wage labour relations and created huge regulatory machinery, there was constant recreation of the capitalist socio-economic order. Throughout out these systemic transformations, which invariably relied on the use of state power for their creation, there was the continual renewal of the field of general equivalence and the wage labour relation. The wage-earning class are increasingly homogenised as a tool of capital valorisation and regulated into dialectical relations of production. Any form of independence from the consumption paradigm and the wage labour relation are eliminated by the increasing stringency of regulative action by the classes of capital and the conduit of the state. Conceptions of time are homogenised around the concept of the wage. Time wages become the norm as agricultural work and the guilds are outmanoeuvred by large factory owners and the general classes of capital. When the factory system enlarges and internationalises, the division of labour is increased and entrenched and the autonomy of the wage labourer is quashed. During the periods of deindustrialisation, wage labour was implanted with new regulative relations in the form of debt and privatised Keynesianism, removing agency and ending the relation of wages to productivity. In these modern dynamics, the state intervenes both on behalf of capital, through subsidies which maintain monopoly and soak-up excess product, and on behalf of wage labour through things like the minimum wage and workplace regulation which limit the desire for radical change and maintain the antagonistic relations of capital and labour.

These are the fundamental relations of capitalism and its continual recreation and metamorphoses. The state plays a huge role in regulating, coordinating and systematising the mechanisms which reproduce capitalism. However such a conception does not define the theoretical definitions and interstitial realities of free, or freed, markets. Rather a distinction must be made between the regulative methods of existing capitalism in all its forms, and the definitions and realities of freed markets, which encompass a much higher level of social and economic interactions and relations.

The most obvious difference is the role and mechanisms of regulation within the freed market. Freed markets rely on a huge level of operationalised, nested forms of regulation which interact in polycentric ways with market actors and socio-economic relations. This can be as simple as attempting to maximise value through good relations with customers and other firms, giving a particular firm or entrepreneur the ability to maximise their subjective value preferences. Further from this, there is the ability for collective organisations (such as trade unions, consumer groups, etc.) to create levels of regulation which fit conceptions of particular rights, demands and necessities in their economies. Already, international social movements have created forms of social regulation through labelling movements and Fairtrade contracts[24].

Such regulatory mechanisms act as an alternative praxis to state regulation, which effectively subsidise externalities and favour largesse. As well as this, in the capital-labour dialectic the state fundamentally favours and acts on behalf of the classes of capital. As Manuel DeLanda would put it, under modern capitalism there exist anti-markets which emphasise monopoly power and extreme regulative control of all modes of production under the firm’s command via state bureaucracies. However, freed markets are the opposite, acting interstitially and relying on the bottlenecks of disaggregated information and imperfect market conditions. Under capitalist anti-markets, entrepreneurial spirits are nowhere near as important as the maintenance of regulated class relations between capital and labour. Things like competition, falling profits and an autonomy in work are a veneer on the general capitalist system. If such things were able to dynamically exist, capitalist social relations would be untenable. The antagonistic relations of capital and labour, regulated via the state, would be outcompeted by new forms of capital creation and access and the ability for wage labourers to operate in different socio-economic systems of action. In a truly freed market, rather than a system of general equivalence where all commodities’ value are measured relative to the wage labour relations’ ability to reproduce consumption patterns and capital valorisation, there would exist a plethora of value maximisation systems and subjective value preferences. A praxeological system where values and desires are met by heterogeneous forms of both capital and market systems. A freed market is not simply determined by economistic rationalism. Instead it is “only one denotation of praxeological understanding. It is based around seeing the market as a particular institution of economic praxis. But of course there exist other systems that may well sprout up in conditions of freedom and the unlocking of human desires and actions from the coercive state. This could include production for direct use, collective decentralised planning systems for public goods, primitivist economies, recommoning (as seen in Zomia and some of the right to repair movements) and economies of abundance, as are developing in filesharing and 3D printing. The market need not be “turned into an idol”, but rather understood and codified as a major area of human activity and value creation and maximisation. Markets and capital are heterogeneous due to their subjective valuation by individuals. In the same way one chooses between different products or services in a market, and leads oneself to different bargaining strategies and forms of price discovery, in a freed market one could and should have the ability to subjectively value and choose different economic governance structures and different forms of market and capital”[25].

And these are simply the theoretical possibilities. Where such freed market structures exist interstitially, there are decentralised systems of micro-firms and direct economy production, with high levels of competition and cooperation depending upon the socially-developed regulatory mechanisms. In the Shanzhai economy, black market production in micro-technologies and handheld-computer goods are produced through micro-manufacturers, with high levels of innovation in things like smartphones and tablets. In the Third Italy system, there are cooperative firms producing by order rather than relying on subsidised mass production. The Greek people, since the destruction wrought by the financial crisis, have begun to construct their own alternative economy through city-based cooperatives, local currencies and collective forms of consumption[26]. Finally, the Piqueteros of Argentina have constructed a gift-market hybrid economy where there is production for petty commodity exchange as well as production for direct use. Variable and intensive economies of scale, with significant independence from wage labour and autonomy for worker-entrepreneurs, are developed and honed in[27]. Something akin to Konkin’s entrepreneuriat is being developed in all of these examples. Nothing akin to a field of general equivalence is witnessed in these systems as value maximisation is not simply boiled down to an economistic relation of production and consumption.

Without the state, there is the ability to return to the relations developed from petty commodity production and common ownership of land and foodstuffs, as well as new advantages brought by the capitalist collectivisation of wage labour. Modern variants, like tool exchanges, capital formation alternatives and different conceptions of time which effect the dynamics of work and end the homogenisation of wage labour, can become existential realities. A distributist system of independent property holders, or a reinvigorated commons of unused capital are also possible. The realities of capitalism, those of regulated, enforced capital-labour relations, a huge imbalance between exchange and use value and a system of entry barriers and statist monopolies are simply the construction of one praxis among many alternatives, with the capitalist praxis being extremely fragile and far too homogeneous. The anti-markets of capital rely on state intervention, and the construction of complex regulatory apparatuses which need constant expansion and growth. Enforced scarcities and monopolies are the inevitability of such a system, with wage labour being the outlet for valorisation and consumption. In a world of declining resources, increasing abundance of information and technology, and new alternative praxes sprouting up, this system is neither viable nor desirable.

“Some opportune remedy must be found quickly for the misery and wretchedness pressing so unjustly on the majority of the working class: for the ancient workingmen’s guilds were abolished in the last [the eighteenth] century, and no other protective organization took their place. Public institutions and the laws set aside the ancient religion. Hence, by degrees it has come to pass that working men have been surrendered, isolated and helpless, to the hardheartedness of employers and the greed of unchecked competition”[28]. Freed markets encompass such a range of opportunities for the freeing of the wage-earning classes from the tyranny of capitalism and the state. An independence in property holding, a range of spontaneously-ordered regulatory systems and an end to the antagonistic and fragile relations of capital and labour are entirely possible under a pluralistic system of socio-economic relations. A field of general equivalence cannot be constructed when the subjective, multitudinous desires of independent people and voluntary collectives are fully met in heterogeneous economic systems which meet demand, not through state subsidy and mass overproduction, but through variably scaled economies and principles of freedom, subsidiarity and pluralism.

[1] Aglietta, M. A Theory of Capitalist Regulation: The US Experience, 2015, 81

[2] Gillis, W. Debt: The Possibilities Ignored, 2014

[3] Gillis, W. Debt: The Possibilities Ignored, 2014

[4] Shaw, C. Money’s Perimeters of Freedom, 2016

[5] https://thelibertarianideal.wordpress.com/2015/02/06/the-limits-of-economic-action/

[6] Weber, M. Economy and Society, 1978, 63

[7] https://thelibertarianideal.wordpress.com/2015/02/06/the-limits-of-economic-action/

[8] Aglietta, M. A Theory of Capitalist Regulation: The US Experience, 2015, 40

[9] Aglietta, M. A Theory of Capitalist Regulation: The US Experience, 2015, 48

[10] Aglietta, M. A Theory of Capitalist Regulation: The US Experience, 2015, 49

[11] Bonefeld, W. The Permanence of Primitive Accumulation: Commodity Fetishism and Social Constitution, 2001, 3

[12] Aglietta, M. A Theory of Capitalist Regulation: The US Experience, 2015, 41

[13] Aglietta, M. A Theory of Capitalist Regulation: The US Experience, 2015, 19

[14] Bonefeld, W. The Permanence of Primitive Accumulation: Commodity Fetishism and Social Constitution, 2001, 11

[15] Ferrara, C. The Austrian Version of the English Enclosures Part II, 2011

[16] Ferrara, C. The Austrian Version of the English Enclosures Part II, 2011

[17] Ferrara, C. The Austrian Version of the English Enclosures III, 2011

[18] Ferrara, C. The Austrian Version of the English Enclosures III, 2011

[19] Ferrara, C. The Austrian Version of the English Enclosures III, 2011

[20] Aglietta, M. A Theory of Capitalist Regulation: The US Experience, 2015, 73

[21] Aglietta, M. A Theory of Capitalist Regulation: The US Experience, 2015, 71

[22] Aglietta, M. A Theory of Capitalist Regulation: The US Experience, 2015, 71

[23] Shaw, C. Redefining Money: The Praxis of Local Currencies, 2016

[24] Shaw, C. Creating the Seeds of Capitalism’s Death, 2016

[25] Shaw, C. Praxeology: The Importance of First Principles

[26] Shaw, C. Redefining Money: The Praxis of Local Currencies, 2016

[27] Shaw, C. Rethinking Markets: Anarchism, Capitalism and the State, 2016, 27-29

[28] Ferrara, C. The Austrian Version of the English Enclosures III, 2011

Italian, Stateless Embassies
Combattete l’Odio, Ridipingetelo!

[Di Logan Glitterbomb. Originale pubblicato su Center for a Stateless Society il 12 settembre 2016 con il titolo Fight Hate, Paint Back! Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.]

Ogni proibizionismo, per quanto ragionevole, ha il suo mercato nero, e ogni stato, per quanto autoritario, è incapace di vietare completamente alcunché. Così, quando un genitore berlinese ha visto delle svastiche, vietate dalle leggi tedesche, in un campo di gioco per bambini, ha capito che era meglio agire da sé.

Mettendo due bombolette di vernice spray sulla cassa di un vicino negozio di bricolage, questo genitore ha rivelato le sue intenzioni al cassiere. Quest’ultimo, pur ammirando la determinazione dell’uomo, ha capito che non si trattava di un artista e gli ha offerto una mano. È stato così che il cassiere, assieme alla NGO The Cultural Inheritance, hanno lanciato #PaintBack, un progetto che mira a trasformare le svastiche in qualcosa di artistico e avulso da sentimenti di odio.

Come dicevo, le leggi tedesche vietano tassativamente tutto ciò che ha a che fare con il Nazionalsocialismo: partiti, propaganda, slogan, saluti, simbologie. Ma nonostante i tentativi di denazificare la Germania dopo la seconda guerra mondiale, da quando sono in vigore queste leggi le attività neonaziste esistono ancora, e sono anche riuscite a conquistare una rappresentanza politica. Come tutti i proibizionismi, queste leggi falliscono perché considerare fuorilegge certe attività serve solo a costringere certe persone a cambiare tattica, mentre la legge viene usata contro persone che non fanno nulla di male. È già successo che degli antifascisti siano finiti nel mirino della legge per aver usato la svastica a fini antinazisti. Per questo la legge è stata modificata così che “non si applica se il mezzo propagandistico serve al progresso civile, punta a prevenire fini incostituzionali, promuovere l’arte, la scienza, la ricerca o l’insegnamento, riportare eventi storici attuali o altro simile.”

Quanto ai graffiti fascisti, la legge ha la stessa efficacia che ha contro i graffiti in generale. La maggior parte dei graffitari sta bene attenta ad evitare la polizia, e rintracciarli a fatto compiuto è impossibile in assenza di testimoni. Cosa fare, allora, per far capire che la comunità non vuole queste espressioni di odio? Bè, escludendo l’ovvietà del confronto diretto con queste persone, si può evitare che diffondano la loro propaganda.

Trasformando questi simboli bigotti in fiori, bestiole, finestre e altre belle immagini, si dimostra che si possono affrontare i simboli dell’odio senza ricorrere allo stato e la sua gang personale conosciuta come polizia. Con questa reazione pacifica i cittadini possono combattere l’odio con la creatività, abbellendo la città e coinvolgendo quei giovani del quartiere che hanno realizzato molta dell’arte di PaintBack.

“I ragazzi immaginano le cose diversamente. Per loro, la svastica è solo un simbolo,” dice Ibo Omari, il cassiere da cui è nata l’idea. “Non l’associano al razzismo o al nazismo. Tendono a camuffarla molto meglio di un adulto ed è per questo che la maggior parte delle opere vengono dai ragazzi.”

Chi poteva immaginare che la lotta contro l’odio potesse diventare un progetto artistico che coinvolgesse i ragazzi del posto? Questa è solo una delle tante idee creative che possono venire quando si sceglie di risolvere i problemi senza invocare lo stato.

Anarchy and Democracy
Fighting Fascism
Markets Not Capitalism
The Anatomy of Escape
Organization Theory