Italian, Stateless Embassies
Che Minchia ci Facciamo in Yemen?

Il governo degli Stati Uniti parte alla carica contro un’altra guerra civile in Medio Oriente. Quando continui a chiederti “Impareranno mai?”, la risposta più probabile è che chi prende le decisioni non ha alcun incentivo a fare altrimenti. Quello che sembra un fallimento potrebbe essere invece il risultato voluto. I pantani hanno i loro lati positivi (per le élite di governo) se le vittime americane sono poche.

L’amministrazione Obama sta aiutando l’Arabia Saudita a bombardare lo Yemen. Questo, unito all’embargo imposto dai sauditi, crea una catastrofe umanitaria nel paese più povero del Vicino Oriente. Muoiono i civili, e quel poco di infrastrutture che il paese aveva viene distrutto.

Perché? Il segretario di stato John Kerry dice che gli Stati Uniti non “staranno a guardare mentre la regione viene destabilizzata.” Kerry è un veterano, e forse anche uno studioso, della guerra d’Indocina. Dovrebbe sapere che il bombardamento è un modo terribile per evitare le destabilizzazioni. Kerry non è uno stupido. Il che significa che è un bugiardo e un demagogo.

Da notare le parole “la regione”, non “lo Yemen”. Perché mai una guerra civile nello Yemen dovrebbe avere ripercussioni sulla regione? Secondo le spiegazioni ufficiali, diffuse fedelmente da gran parte dei media, perché lo Yemen è sotto assedio da parte di agenti che operano per conto dell’Iran, gli Huthi.

L’Iran oggi ricopre lo stesso ruolo ricoperto dall’Unione Sovietica, o dalla Cospirazione Comunista Internazionale, dalla fine della seconda guerra mondiale fino al 1989-91, quando l’impero sovietico crollò. L’Iran è il nemico tuttofare che può essere accusato praticamente di ogni nefandezza. Ogni giorno il partito della guerra e i suoi alleati sauditi e israeliani avvertono che l’Iran è in marcia, che controlla le capitali di tutto il Medio Oriente: Bagdad, Damasco, Beirut, e ora anche Sana’a.

Ma questo è assurdo. L’Iran non è in marcia. Fu George W. Bush nel 2003 a consegnare volutamente Bagdad agli sciiti amici dell’Iran. Il regime siriano di Assad è un alleato dell’Iran da molto tempo, contro cui Obama e il suo primo segretario di stato Hillary Clinton hanno aperto la caccia rinforzando al Qaeda e la sua mutazione più virulenta, l’Isis. Il partito libanese Hezbollah, amico dell’Iran, è nato in risposta all’invasione israeliana del 1982 e alla lunga occupazione militare. Nessuno di questi casi dimostra l’esistenza di un Iran aggressivo. Detto meglio, queste alleanze aiutano l’Iran a fronteggiare l’accerchiamento americano. Ricordate che nel 1953 la Cia rovesciò il governo democratico iraniano, e negli anni ottanta fu complice nell’offensiva militare irachena contro l’Iran, una guerra in cui Saddam Hussein fece uso di armi chimiche ottenute grazie all’aiuto degli Stati Uniti. È da allora che i vari presidenti americani e i governi israeliani attaccano l’Iran in ogni modo: economicamente, con atti di ciberterrorismo, di terrorismo mediato e sotto copertura.

E lo Yemen, allora? Qui gli Huthi, dopo aver mandato via il presidente autocratico appoggiato dagli Stati Uniti, combattono ora contro i nemici giurati dell’America, come la sunnita al Qaeda nella Penisola Arabica e gli affiliati yemeniti di Isis. Certo, quello degli Huthi è un islam di tipo sciita, lo Zaidi, ma con importanti differenze rispetto alla versione iraniana. In realtà, gli Huthi non sono altro che l’ultima manifestazione di una minoranza religiosa yemenita oppressa da lungo tempo, che ora cerca la propria autonomia dal governo centrale. Dopo anni di frustrazioni, menzogne e tradimenti, finalmente ora attaccano quel governo. Si può dire quello che si vuole di questo gruppo, ma non che è un agente dell’Iran.

L’Arabia Saudita considera l’Iran una minaccia, ma il regno non è credibile, e probabilmente l’amministrazione Obama riuscirà a placare la famiglia reale ora che un accordo sul nucleare con l’Iran è a portata di mano. Come fa notare il ricercatore indipendente Jonathan Marshall, “Decenni prima che l’Iran diventasse suo nemico, l’Arabia Saudita cominciò ad intervenire presso il suo vicino meridionale [lo Yemen]. Dopo la conquista di territori, i sauditi cominciarono a mandare soldi per promuovere il suo marchio di Sunnismo noto come Wahhabismo. Nel 2009 invasero lo Yemen del nord con il proposito di attaccare gli Huthi, ma senza successo.”

Aggiunge Marshall: “Sono decenni che anche Washington è impelagata in questi conflitti civili yemeniti.”

Di sicuro Washington uccide yemeniti (a molti dei quali non viene dato neanche il titolo di “sospetti terroristi”) fin dal 2001, quando il governo corrotto e oppressivo di Sana’a è diventato un alleato nella “guerra al terrore”.

“Il governo dello Yemen si è servito più volte di aiuti militari americani in supporto ad un attacco in grande stile contro gli Huthi (la cosiddetta ‘Operazione Terra Bruciata’),” scrive Marshall, “facendo numerosissime vittime civili.”

A questo punto, si può ben dire che l’intervento americano non è affatto un errore innocente.

Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.

Portuguese, Stateless Embassies
Benjamin Tucker, anarquista de Boston

O movimento libertário americano não se recuperaria por décadas da cisão causada pela Guerra Civil dos Estados Unidos. Conflitos internos entre abolicionistas que eram favoráveis à guerra e à invasão do Sul, que enxergavam a guerra como inevitável e necessária para pôr um fim à escravidão, e aqueles que pensavam que a guerra era moralmente inaceitável e desnecessária para acabar com a escravidão fizeram com que o movimento libertário se dividisse em vários movimentos sociais radicais menores. Entre eles estavam o livre pensamento, o amor livre e o movimento trabalhista. Depois de 1865, a tradição individualista sobreviveu como parte dessas causas mais amplas, embora não como um movimento coeso. Dado o crescimento astronômico do estado devido à guerra e o declínio do pensamento radical individualista, parecia que a chama da liberdade havia se apagado.

Nascido em 17 de abril de 1854 em Massachusetts, Benjamin Tucker cresceu em uma família quaker e unitarista radical. Tucker se matriculou no MIT, mas após conhecer três importantes anarquistas individualistas (Ezra Heywood, William B. Greene e Josiah Warren) em uma convenção da New England Labor Reform League em Boston em 1872, Tucker se tornaria um ativista, jornalista e ensaísta anarquista. Se aliaria fortemente ao movimento trabalhista e teria algumas conexões com os movimentos do livre pensamento e do amor livre (assim como seus colegas). O núcleo comum em todo o seu pensamento, porém, era o individualismo.

Tucker construiu sua teoria do anarquismo individualista (que chamava de “anarquismo de Boston” para distingui-lo dos “anarquistas de Chicago”, que eram geralmente menos favoráveis às ideias de mercado e mais favoráveis à violência como meio para a mudança social) sobre os princípios da soberania individual e da teoria do valor-trabalho (que era aceita por muitos importantes economistas desde Adam Smith, mas que foi suplantada mais tarde dentro da profissão econômica pela revolução marginalista, encabeçada por Carl Menger, William S. Jevons e Leon Walras). Para os anarquistas do século 19, a teoria do valor-trabalho — de acordo com a qual o “custo é o limite do preço” — era a extensão natural da soberania do indivíduo sobre si mesmo. O trabalho era visto como a fonte de toda a riqueza e o trabalhador naturalmente tem propriedade sobre os frutos de seu trabalho como extensão de sua propriedade sobre si. A teoria do valor de Tucker estava intimamente ligada às suas visões éticas, segundo as quais cada indivíduo é o único legítimo soberano sobre seu corpo e sua propriedade justa, que requeria a mistura de seu trabalho.

Tucker e seus colegas anarquistas individualistas eram anticapitalistas, mas favoráveis ao livre mercado (PDF). Enxergavam o capitalismo como uma economia estatista que beneficiava artificialmente os capitalistas às custas dos trabalhadores através da extração do valor excedente do trabalho por rents artificiais. Tucker pensava que os frutos das classes trabalhadoras são sistematicamente e coercitivamente tomados pelas elites sob o estatismo. Ele via o estado como patrocinador da classe dominante. Identificava quatro grandes monopólios: o da moeda, da terra, das patentes e das tarifas (Charles Johnson já identificou ainda mais deles). O papel desses monopólios era concentrar capital nas mãos de poucos e criar um sistema de trabalho assalariado. A origem desses monopólios, porém, não está no livre mercado, mas no estado.

Ao invés de adotar uma retórica pró-capitalista e uma vez que os anarquistas americanos viam os capitalistas como braços do estado, eles eram bastante simpáticos ao termo “socialismo” (alguns anarquistas individualistas contemporâneos pretendem retomar o termo “socialismo” do jugo dos socialistas estatistas). Tucker acreditava que havia uma visão única que juntava todos os socialistas, de Warren e Proudhon a Marx, que era:

[Que] o custo é o limite do preço — esses três homens fizeram as seguintes deduções: que a remuneração natural do trabalho é o seu produto; que essa remuneração, ou produto, é a única fonte justa de rendimentos (ignorando, é claro, presentes, heranças etc.); que todos aqueles que derivam suas riquezas de qualquer outra fonte as extraem direta ou indiretamente da remuneração justa e natural do trabalho; que esse processo de extração geralmente toma três formas — juro, renda e lucro; que esses três constituem a trindade da usura e são simplesmente diferentes métodos de arrecadar tributos pelo uso do capital; que o capital, sendo apenas trabalho armazenado que já foi remunerado em sua totalidade, deve ser de uso gratuito, sob o princípio de que o trabalho é a única base do preço; que o credor de capital tem direito ao seu retorno intacto e nada mais; que a única razão pela qual o banqueiro, o acionista, o senhorio, o manufatureiro e o mercador são capazes de extrair usura do trabalho se deve ao fato de que são sustentados por privilégios legais — ou monopólios; e que a única forma de garantir que o trabalho usufrua de seu produto total, ou de sua remuneração natural, é acabar com o monopólio.

Tucker fazia uma distinção entre o socialismo de estado e o socialismo de mercado. Seu programa socialista individualista consistia “na destruição desses monopólios e na substituição deles pela livre concorrência” e se baseava “num princípio fundamental: a liberdade do indivíduo, seu direito soberano sobre si mesmo, sobre seus produtos e suas relações, e seu direito de rebelião contra as ordens de uma autoridade externa”. A abolição dos monopólios (isto é, a reforma econômica) se tornou o objetivo principal de Benjamin Tucker e sua missão era ser “um defensor da justiça para o trabalho”. Sobre suas duas maiores influências, Tucker escreveu:

Quando Warren e Proudhon, em sua luta pela justiça para os trabalhadores, se depararam com o obstáculo dos monopólios de classe, eles observaram que esses monopólios eram sustentados pela autoridade e concluíram que a coisa a ser feita não era fortalecer essa autoridade e assim tornar o monopólio universal, mas extirpá-lo totalmente e assim brandir o princípio oposto — a liberdade —, tornando a competição, a antítese do monopólio, universal.

Tucker rejeitava a visão de Marx e dos socialistas de estado, caracterizando-a como a “doutrina de que todas as relações humanas devem ser gerenciadas pelo governo, sem levar em consideração a escolha individual”, seguindo os ensinamentos dos individualistas (principalmente Warren e Proudhon):

Assim como a ideia de tirar o capital dos indivíduos e dá-los para o governo levou Marx a um caminho que termina ao transformar o governo em tudo e o indivíduo em nada, a ideia de tirar o capital dos monopólios protegidos pelo governo e colocá-los ao alcance de todos os indivíduos colocou Warren e Proudhon no caminho que termina na transformação do indivíduo em tudo e do governo nada. Se o indivíduo tem o direito de governar a si mesmo, toda autoridade externa é tirânica. Daí a necessidade de se abolir o estado.

São precisamente as barreiras à entrada e as regulamentações econômicas criadas pelo estado que impedem a competição e, portanto, concentram o poder econômico e os recursos nas mãos de algumas poucas elites políticas. De acordo com Tucker, a exploração capitalista, à qual Marx legitimamente se opunha, se baseia na autoridade do estado. A rejeição da autoridade significa a adoção do “anarquismo, que pode ser descrito como a doutrina de que todas as relações humanas devem ser gerenciadas pelos indivíduos ou por associações voluntárias e de que o estado deve ser abolido”.

Tucker, em seu “jeffersonianismo sem medo” deu origem a um novo movimento libertário em 1881 quando fundou o jornal Liberty, um canal de divulgação daquilo que Tucker chamava de anarquismo filosófico, especificamente de sua própria variedade, que incorporava o pensamento pró-trabalho, pró-mercado e egoísta, influenciado fortemente por Josiah Warren, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon (o autor do slogan do jornal, “A mãe, não a filha da liberdade”), Herbert Spencer e Max Stirner. O periódico servia como divulgação de suas visões na cena política radical americana e também como plataforma para um discurso que moldaria a tradição individualista e o movimento libertário para sempre.

Os individualistas, juntamente com os livre-pensadores, o amor livre e o movimento trabalhista foram unidos pelo jornal Liberty, que publicava os trabalhos de radicais influentes como Lysander Spooner, Auberon Herbert, Joshua K. Ingalls, John Henry Mackay, Victor Yarros e Wordsworth Donisthorpe. Suas páginas traçaram e criaram vários debates internos e controvérsias dentro da tradição radical individualista por três décadas e, de acordo com Wendy McElroy, “forneceram um núcleo em torno do qual um movimento revitalizado poderia surgir e crescer”. Ao reunir as tradições individualistas remanescentes da cisão da Guerra Civil, Tucker e Liberty foram instrumentais no renascimento do movimento libertário americano e vitais para seu sucesso no século 20.

O jornal do livre pensamento Boston Investigator deu boas-vindas à primeira edição de Liberty em 1881 dizendo: “O Sr. Tucker tem a capacidade, a indústria, o radicalismo e a independência para fazer um jornal interessante e sugestivo”. O jornal claramente ultrapassou as expectavias.

Em 1908, no entanto, Liberty chegava ao fim da linha e em 1930 meu radical de Boston preferido também já pensava que a própria liberdade tinha acabado:

[O] obstáculo insuperável à realização da Anarquia não é mais o poder dos trustes, mas o fato incontestável de que nossa civilização está à beira do colapso. Talvez duremos ainda alguns séculos; por outro lado, uma década pode precipitar nosso fim. (…) Uma idade das trevas é certa. O Monstro, o Mecanismo, está devorando a humanidade.

Nove anos mais tarde, Benjamin Tucker morria acreditando que a chama da liberdade havia se apagado permanentemente. Eu espero que, quase cem anos depois, o movimento libertário que deve seu renascimento e sua existência à chama de Tucker em 1881 não deixe que sua chama radical e independente jamais se apague.

Traduzido por Erick Vasconcelos.

Feature Articles, The Benjamin R. Tucker Collection
Benjamin Tucker, Boston Anarchist

The Civil War caused a huge schism in the American libertarian movement from which it wouldn’t recover for decades. Inner conflicts between abolitionists who favored the war and the invasion of the South, ones who saw the war as inevitable and required to end slavery, and those who thought the war was an egregious moral wrong in and of itself and unnecessary to end slavery caused the libertarian movement to faction off into other radical social movements, such as freethought, free love, and the labor movement. After 1865, the individualist tradition lived on, not in a distinct libertarian movement, but as a radical faction within these broader social causes. Considering the astronomical growth in the state due to the war and the growing decline of radical individualist thought, it seemed the flame of liberty had burned out.

Born on April 17, 1854 in Massachusetts, Benjamin Tucker grew up in a Quaker and Radical Unitarian family. Tucker enrolled in MIT, but after a fateful encounter with three prominent individualist anarchists (Ezra Heywood, William Greene, and Josiah Warren), at a New England Labor Reform League convention in Boston in 1872, Tucker would go on to become an anarchist activist, journalist, and essayist. He would align strongly with the labor movement and had some connections to the freethought and free love movements (as did his fellow radicals). The common strain in all his thought, however, was individualism.

Tucker built his theory of individualist anarchism (or what he called “Boston Anarchism” to distinguish him from “Chicago Anarchists” who were generally less favorable to markets and more favorable to violence as a means for social change) out of the principles of individual sovereignty and the labor theory of value (which was commonly accepted by mainstream economists dating back to Adam Smith, but was later thrown out by the profession after the marginal revolution led by early Austrians, such as Carl Menger and Eugene Böhm von Bawerk). For 19th century anarchists, the labor theory of value, or “cost limit of price,” was the natural extension of the individual’s absolute sovereignty over themselves. Labor was seen as the source for all wealth, and the laborer naturally owns the fruits of their labor as an extension of their self-ownership. Tucker’s theory of value was intimately related to his ethical views based on each individual having sole dominion over their body and their justly acquired property, which required labor mixing.

Tucker and his fellow individualist anarchists were anti-capitalist, but pro-free market [PDF]. They viewed capitalism as representative of a statist economy that artificially benefited capitalists at the expense of laborers by extracting surplus value through artificial rents. Tucker thought the fruits of the laboring classes are systematically and coercively taken by the elites under statism. He viewed the State as propagator of the ruling class. Tucker identified the four big monopolies: money, land, patent, and tariff (Charles Johnson has identified even more). The role of these monopolies are to concentrate capital in the hands of a few and create a wage system. But the origin of these monopolies lies, not in the free market, but in the State.

Instead of adopting pro-capitalist rhetoric, since the American anarchists saw capitalists as largely arms of the State, they were very friendly to “Socialism” (Some modern individualist anarchists want to reclaim the term “socialism” from the monopoly statists now have on the term). Tucker saw the strain of thought that tied all socialists together, from Warren to Proudhon to Marx, as the view,

…that cost is the proper limit of price – these three men made the following deductions: that the natural wage of labor is its product; that this wage, or product, is the only just source of income (leaving out, of course, gift, inheritance, etc.); that all who derive income from any other source abstract it directly or indirectly from the natural and just wage of labor; that this abstracting process generally takes one of three forms, — interest, rent, and profit; that these three constitute the trinity of usury, and are simply different methods of levying tribute for the use of capital; that, capital being simply stored-up labor which has already received its pay in full, its use ought to be gratuitous, on the principle that labor is the only basis of price; that the lender of capital is entitled to its return intact, and nothing more; that the only reason why the banker, the stockholder, the landlord, the manufacturer, and the merchant are able to exact usury from labor lies in the fact that they are backed by legal privilege, or monopoly; and that the only way to secure labor the enjoyment of its entire product, or natural wage, is to strike down monopoly.

Tucker distinguished between state socialism and market socialism. His individualistic socialist program consisted, “in the destruction of these monopolies and the substitution for them of the freest competition… [which] rested upon a very fundamental principle, the freedom of the individual, his right of sovereignty over himself, his products, and his affairs, and of the rebellion against the dictation of external authority.” Abolishing the monopolies (i.e, economic reform) became the central goal for Benjamin Tucker and his mission to be an, “advocate for the justice of labor.” Of his two biggest influences, Warren and Proudhon, Tucker wrote,

…in prosecuting their search for justice to labor, came face to face with the obstacle of class monopolies, the saw that these monopolies rested upon Authority, and concluded the thing to be done was, not to strength this Authority, and thus make monopoly universal, but to utterly uproot Authority and give full sway to the opposite principle, Liberty, by making competition, the antithesis of monopoly, universal.

Tucker rejected the view of Marx and the state socialists as “the doctrine that all affairs of men should be managed by the government regardless of individual choice,” and instead followed the individualists (primarily Warren and Proudhon):

Just as the idea of taking capital away from individuals and giving it to the government started Marx in a path which ends in making the government everything and the individual nothing, so the idea of taking capital away from government-protected monopolies and putting it within easy reach of all individuals started Warren and Proudhon in a path which ends in making the individual everything and the government nothing. If the individual has a right to govern himself, all external government is tyranny. Hence the necessity of abolishing the State.

It is precisely the state-created barriers to entry and economic regulations that prevent competition and therefore concentrate economic power and resources into the hands of a few, politically entrenched elites. It is the Authority of the State that Tucker objected to that capitalist exploitation, which Marx rightfully objected to, rests upon. Rejecting that authority means embracing, “Anarchism, which may be described as the doctrine that all affairs of men should be managed by individuals and voluntary associations, and that the State should be abolished.”

Tucker and his “Unterrified Jeffersonianism” gave rise to a new libertarian movement in 1881 when he founded Liberty: Not the Daughter but the Mother of Order, a periodical that served as a conduit for what Tucker called philosophical anarchism, specifically his own flavor, which incorporated pro-labor, pro-market, egoist thought and drew heavily on Josiah Warren, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon (the author of Liberty’s sub-heading), Herbert Spencer, and Max Stirner, in the American radical political scene as well as a platform for discourse that would shape the individualist tradition and libertarian movement forever.

The individualists among freethought, free love, and the labor movement were brought together with Tucker’s Liberty, which published such influential radicals as Lysander Spooner, Auberon Herbert, Joshua K. Ingalls, John Henry Mackay, Victor Yarros, and Wordsworth Donisthorpe. The magazine chronicled and created all the in debates and controversies of the radical individualist tradition for over three decades and, according to Wendy McElroy, “provided a core around which a revitalized movement could sprout and grow.” By bringing together the remaining individualist factions left over from the Civil War schism, Tucker and Liberty were instrumental in the revival of the American libertarian movement and vital for it’s success and growth in the 20th century.

The Freethinking Boston Investigator welcomed the first issue of Liberty in 1881 by saying, “Mr. Tucker has ability and industry, radicalism and independence, he will make an interesting and suggestive paper.” The periodical clearly surpassed expectations.

By 1908, though, Liberty had run its course and by 1930, my favorite Boston Radical thought liberty itself had as well:

…the insurmountable obstacle to the realization of Anarchy is no longer the power of the trusts, but the indisputable fact that our civilization is in its death throes. We may last a couple of centuries yet; on the other hand, a decade may precipitate our finish. … The dark ages sure enough. The Monster, Mechanism, is devouring mankind.

Nine years later, Benjamin Tucker passed away believing the flame of liberty was permanently burned out. I hope almost a hundred years later, the libertarian movement that owes its revival and existence to Tucker’s inner spark in 1881 doesn’t let its radical and independent flame ever burn out.

Stateless Embassies, Turkish
Devletin Suça Ihtiyaci Var

Saturday Night Live ’ın Citizen Kane parodisinde Charles Foster Kane yavaş bir haber gününde diyorki, “Haber yoksa, biz yaparız”, ve insanları rastgele gazete ofislerinin camlarından atmaya başlıyor. Okuduğum zaman ilk aklıma gelen California’daki iki sivil polis –yağmacılığı başlatmaya çalışınca! — Oakland ve Berkeley’deki jurinin silahsız siyah erkekleri öldüren polisleri suçsuz bulma kararına karşı gelen yürüyüşteki protestocular tarafından kendilerini ele geçirttiklerinin raporu.

Evet, doğru, yağmayı başlatmak için teşebbüs — yanlış okumadınız. Gösteriden rapor veren birincil tanıklara göre, iki polis memurları — gösterici pozlarla — “yağmacılığın elebaşılarıydı” (“Courtney Harrop, “Undercover Cops Outed and Pulled Guns on Crowd”, Storify, 11 Aralık 2013). Sızılan gruptaki protestocular polis memurlarını sahte olarak gördüler ve öbür göstericilere belirttiler. Paniklenen memurların bir tanesi, hemen ünlenen fotoğrafta bulunan, silahını çekti ve çevrede olan yürüyüşcüleri tehdit etti.

Polis provokatörlerinin suç elebaşıları oldukları eski bir öykü. Earth First! organizatör Judi Bari dediki, “Dinamiti getirmeyi teklif eden insan herzaman bir FBI ajanıdır”. Aralık’daki 1999 Seattle protestolarından beri, anti-küreselleşme hareketleri gizli polislerin camları kırmayı önerdiği söylentileriyle doludurlar. Eylül 11’den beri FBI yüzünden kapatılan, yaklaşık her “terör hücresi” federal ajanlar tarafından organize edildiler. Aslında, “teröristler” genellikle çok beceriksizlerdiki, FBI’nın yardımıyla bile işlev yapamadılar.

Charles Foster Kane’in haber olmayınca haber üretmesi gibi, devlet suç olmayınca suç üretiyor.

Başlangıçta, devletin eleştirmenlerini — küreselleşmeye karşı gelen protestocular, Occupy Wall Street hareketindeki yürüyüşçüler, ve ırksal adaletsizliğinden sinirlenen göstericiler– sömürmeye bahane bulmak için bunu yapıyor. Devlet “Başka Bir Dünya Mümkün” mesaji veren veya mevcut güç sisteminin meşruluğunu sorgulayan hareketleri karartmaya çalışıyor. Devlet hareketcileri “kırmızı”, “anarşist”, ve “yabancı tahrikçi” — Haymarket Baskısı ve Dünya Savaş I’deki yaptığı gibi– olarak reddediyor ve gerekliyse, suçu kolayca üretiyor.

Temelde, devlet bizi korkuda tutması gerekliki ona güç vermeye gönüllü olalım. Korkmak yerine, birbirlerine güvenen, komşularla huzurlu işbirliği yaparak kendilerini sağlıkta tutan, kapasitelerine güven veren toplumlar devlet gücünün gelişmesi için üretken yerler değiller. Devletin suça ihtiyaci var — üretmesi gerekse bile.

Batu Caliskan bu çeviriden sorumludur.

Left-Libertarian - Classics, Stigmergy - C4SS Blog
The Iron Fist Behind the Invisible Hand

Support C4SS with Kevin Carson’s “The Iron Fist Behind the Invisible Hand”

Audio version, read by Mike Gogulski

Introduction to the Portuguese Version of Iron Fist

Versione in italiano

Версия на русском

<< Back to the Market Anarchism FAQ page

Introduction

Manorialism, commonly, is recognized to have been founded by robbery and usurpation; a ruling class established itself by force, and then compelled the peasantry to work for the profit of their lords. But no system of exploitation, including capitalism, has ever been created by the action of a free market. Capitalism was founded on an act of robbery as massive as feudalism. It has been sustained to the present by continual state intervention to protect its system of privilege, without which its survival is unimaginable.

The current structure of capital ownership and organization of production in our so-called “market” economy, reflects coercive state intervention prior to and extraneous to the market. From the outset of the industrial revolution, what is nostalgically called “laissez-faire” was in fact a system of continuing state intervention to subsidize accumulation, guarantee privilege, and maintain work discipline.

Most such intervention is tacitly assumed by mainstream right-libertarians as part of a “market” system. Although a few intellectually honest ones like Rothbard and Hess were willing to look into the role of coercion in creating capitalism, the Chicago school and Randroids take existing property relations and class power as a given. Their ideal “free market” is merely the current system minus the progressive regulatory and welfare state — i.e., nineteenth century robber baron capitalism.

But genuine markets have a value for the libertarian left, and we shouldn’t concede the term to our enemies. In fact, capitalism — a system of power in which ownership and control are divorced from labor — could not survive in a free market. As a mutualist anarchist, I believe that expropriation of surplus value — i.e., capitalism — cannot occur without state coercion to maintain the privilege of usurer, landlord, and capitalist. It was for this reason that the free market anarchist Benjamin Tucker — from whom right-libertarians selectively borrow — regarded himself as a libertarian socialist.

It is beyond my ability or purpose here to describe a world where a true market system could have developed without such state intervention. A world in which peasants had held onto their land and property was widely distributed, capital was freely available to laborers through mutual banks, productive technology was freely available in every country without patents, and every people was free to develop locally without colonial robbery, is beyond our imagination. But it would have been a world of decentralized, small-scale production for local use, owned and controlled by those who did the work — as different from our world as day from night, or freedom from slavery.

The Subsidy of History

Accordingly, the single biggest subsidy to modern corporate capitalism is the subsidy of history, by which capital was originally accumulated in a few hands, and labor was deprived of access to the means of production and forced to sell itself on the buyer’s terms. The current system of concentrated capital ownership and large-scale corporate organization is the direct beneficiary of that original structure of power and property ownership, which has perpetuated itself over the centuries.

For capitalism as we know it to come about, it was essential first of all for labor to be separated from property. Marxians and other radical economists commonly refer to the process as “primitive accumulation.” “What the capitalist system demanded was… a degraded and almost servile condition of the mass of the people, the transformation of them into mercenaries, and of their means of labor into capital.” That meant expropriating the land, “to which the [peasantry] has the same feudal rights as the lord himself.” [Marx, “Chapter 27: The Expropriation,” Capital vol. 1]

To grasp the enormity of the process, we must understand that the nobility’s rights in land under the manorial economy were entirely a feudal legal fiction deriving from conquest. The peasants who cultivated the land of England in 1650 were descendants of those who had occupied it since time immemorial. By any standard of morality, it was their property in every sense of the word. The armies of William the Conqueror, by no right other than force, had compelled these peasant proprietors to pay rent on their own land.

J. L. and Barbara Hammond treated the sixteenth century village and open field system as a survival of the free peasant society of Anglo-Saxon times, with landlordism superimposed on it. The gentry saw surviving peasant rights as a hindrance to progress and efficient farming; a revolution in their own power was a way of breaking peasant resistance. Hence the agricultural community was “taken to pieces … and reconstructed in the manner in which a dictator reconstructs a free government.” [The Village Labourer 27-28, 35-36].

When the Tudors gave expropriated monastic lands to the nobility, the latter “drove out, en masse, the hereditary sub tenants and threw their holdings into one.” [Marx, “The Expropriation“]. This stolen land, about a fifth of the arable land of England, was the first large-scale expropriation of the peasantry.

Another major theft of peasant land was the “reform” of land law by the seventeenth century Restoration Parliament. The aristocracy abolished feudal tenures and converted their own estate in the land, until then “only a feudal title,” into “rights of modern private property.” In the process, they abolished the tenure rights of copyholders. Copyholders were de jure tenants under feudal law, but once they paid a negligible quit-rent fixed by custom, the land was theirs to sell or bequeath. In substance copyhold tenure was a manorial equivalent of freehold; but since it derived from custom it was enforceable only in the manor courts. Under the “reform,” tenants in copyhold became tenants at-will, who could be evicted or charged whatever rent their lord saw fit [Marx, “The Expropriation…”].

Another form of expropriation, which began in late medieval times and increased drastically in the eighteenth century, was the enclosure of commons–in which, again, the peasants communally had as absolute a right of property as any defended by today’s “property rights” advocates. Not counting enclosures before 1700, the Hammonds estimated total enclosures in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries at a sixth or a fifth of the arable land in England [Village Labourer 42]. E. J. Hobsbawm and George Rude estimated enclosures between 1750 and 1850 alone as transforming “something like one quarter of the cultivated acreage from open field, common land, meadow or waste into private fields….” [Captain Swing 27].

The ruling classes saw the peasants’ right in commons as a source of economic independence from capitalist and landlord, and thus a threat to be destroyed. Enclosure eliminated “a dangerous centre of indiscipline” and compelled workers to sell their labor on the masters’ terms. Arthur Young, a Lincolnshire gentleman, described the commons as “a breeding-ground for ‘barbarians,’ ‘nursing up a mischievous race of people’.” “[E]very one but an idiot knows,” he wrote, “that the lower classes must be kept poor, or they will never be industrious.” The Commercial and Agricultural Magazine warned in 1800 that leaving the laborer “possessed of more land than his family can cultivate in the evenings” meant that “the farmer can no longer depend on him for constant work.” [Thompson, The Making of the English Working Class, 219-220, 358]. Sir Richard Price commented on the conversion of self-sufficient proprietors into “a body of men who earn their subsistence by working for others.” There would, “perhaps, be more labour, because there will be more compulsion to it.” [Marx, “The Expropriation….”].

Marx cited parliamentary “acts of enclosure” as evidence that the commons, far from being the “private property of the great landlords who have taken the place of the feudal lords,” actually required “a parliamentary coup detat… for its transformation into private property.” [“The Expropriation….”]. The process of primitive accumulation, in all its brutality, was summed up by the same author:

These new freedmen [i.e. former serfs] became sellers of themselves only after they had been robbed of all their own means of production, and of all the guarantees of existence afforded by the old feudal arrangements. And the history of this, their expropriation, is written in the annals of mankind in letters of blood and fire [“Chapter 26: The Secret of Primitive Accumulation,” Capital Vol. 1].

Even then, the working class was not sufficiently powerless. The state had to regulate the movement of labor, serve as a labor exchange on behalf of capitalists, and maintain order. The system of parish regulation of the movement of people, under the poor laws and vagrancy laws, resembled the internal passport system of South Africa, or the reconstruction era Black Codes. It “had the same effect on the English agricultural labourer,” Marx wrote, “as the edict of the Tartar Boris Godunov on the Russian peasantry.” [“The Expropriation…”] Adam Smith ventured that there was “scarce a poor man in England of forty years of age… who has not in some part of his life felt himself most cruelly oppressed by this ill-contrived law of settlements.” [Wealth of Nations 61].

The state maintained work discipline by keeping laborers from voting with their feet. It was hard to persuade parish authorities to grant a man a certificate entitling him to move to another parish to seek work. Workers were forced to stay put and bargain for work in a buyer’s market [Smith 60-61].

At first glance this would seem to be inconvenient for parishes with a labor shortage [Smith 60]. Factories were built at sources of water power, generally removed from centers of population. Thousands of workers were needed to be imported from far away. But the state saved the day by setting itself up as a middleman in providing labor-poor parishes with cheap surplus labor from elsewhere, depriving workers of the ability to bargain for better terms. A considerable trade arose in child laborers who were in no position to bargain in any case [the Hammonds, The Town Labourer 1:146].

Relief “was seldom bestowed without the parish claiming the exclusive right of disposing, at their pleasure, of all the children of the person receiving relief,” in the words of the Committee on Parish Apprentices, 1815 [the Hammonds, Town Labourer 1:44, 147]. Even when Poor Law commissioners encouraged migration to labor-poor parishes, they discouraged adult men and “Preference was given to ‘widows with large families of children or handi-craftsmen… with large families.'” In addition, the availability of cheap labor from the poor-law commissioners was deliberately used to drive down wages; farmers would discharge their own day-laborers and instead apply to the overseer for help [Thompson 223-224].

Although the Combination Laws theoretically applied to masters as well as workmen, in practice they were not enforced against the latter [Smith 61; the Hammonds, Town Labourer 1:74]. “A Journeyman Cotton Spinner” — a pamphleteer quoted by E. P. Thompson [pp. 199-202] — described “an abominable combination existing amongst the masters,” in which workers who had left their masters because of disagreement over wages were effectively black-listed. The Combination Laws required suspects to answer interrogations on oath, empowered magistrates to give summary judgment, and allowed summary forfeiture of funds accumulated to aid the families of strikers [Town Labourer 123-127]. And the laws setting maximum rates of pay amounted to a state enforced system of combination for the masters. As Adam Smith put it, “[w]henever the legislature attempts to regulate the differences between the masters and their workmen, its counsellors are always the masters.” [p. 61].

The working class lifestyle under the factory system, with its new forms of social control, was a radical break with the past. It involved drastic loss of control over their own work. The seventeenth century work calendar was still heavily influenced by medieval custom. Although there were long days in spurts between planting and harvest, intermittent periods of light work and the proliferation of saints days combined to reduce average work-time well below our own. And the pace of work was generally determined by the sun or the biological rhythms of the laborer, who got up after a decent night’s sleep, and sat down to rest when he felt like it. The cottager who had access to common land, even when he wanted extra income from wage labor, could take work on a casual basis and then return to working for himself. This was an unacceptable degree of independence from a capitalist standpoint.

In the modern world most people have to adapt themselves to some kind of discipline, and to observe other’ people’s timetables, …or work under other people’s orders, but we have to remember that the population that was flung into the brutal rhythm of the factory had earned its living in relative freedom, and that the discipline of the early factory was particularly savage…. No economist of the day, in estimating the gains or losses of factory employment, ever allowed for the strain and violence that a man suffered in his feelings when he passed from a life in which he could smoke or eat, or dig or sleep as he pleased, to one in which somebody turned the key on him, and for fourteen hours he had not even the right to whistle. It was like entering the airless and laughterless life of a prison [the Hammonds, Town Labourer 1:33-34].

The factory system could not have been imposed on workers without first depriving them of alternatives, and forcibly denying access to any source of economic independence. No unbroken human being, with a sense of freedom or dignity, would have submitted to factory discipline. Stephen Marglin compared the nineteenth century textile factory, staffed by pauper children bought at the workhouse slave market, to Roman brick and pottery factories which were manned by slaves. In Rome, factory production was exceptional in manufactures dominated by freemen. The factory system, throughout history, has been possible only with a work force deprived of any viable alternative.

The surviving facts… strongly suggest that whether work was organized along factory lines was in Roman times determined, not by technological considerations, but by the relative power of the two producing classes. Freedmen and citizens had sufficient power to maintain a guild organization. Slaves had no power — and ended up in factories [“What Do Bosses Do?“].

The problem with the old “putting out” system, in which cottage workers produced textiles on a contractual basis, was that it only eliminated worker control of the product. The factory system, by eliminating worker control of the production process, had the advantage of discipline and supervision, with workers organized under an overseer.

The origin and success of the factory lay not in technological superiority, but in the substitution of the capitalist’s for the worker’s control of the work process and the quantity of output, in the change in the workman’s choice from one of how much to work and produce, based on his preferences for leisure and goods, to one of whether or not to work at all, which of course is hardly much of a choice.

Marglin took Adam Smith’s classic example of the division of labor in pin-making, and stood it on its head. The increased efficiency resulted, not from the division of labor as such, but from dividing and sequencing the process into separate tasks in order to reduce set-up time. This could have been accomplished by a single cottage workman separating the various tasks and then performing them sequentially (i.e., drawing out the wire for an entire run of production, then straightening it, then cutting it, etc.).

Without specialization, the capitalist had no essential role to play in the production process. If each producer could himself integrate the component tasks of pin manufacture into a marketable product, he would soon discover that he had no need to deal with the market for pins through the intermediation of the putter-outer. He could sell directly and appropriate to himself the profit that the capitalist derived from mediating between the producer and the market.

This principle is at the center of the history of industrial technology for the last two hundred years. Even given the necessity of factories for some forms of large-scale, capital-intensive manufacturing, there is usually a choice between alternate productive technologies within the factory. Industry has consistently chosen technologies which de-skill workers and shift decision-making upward into the managerial hierarchy. As long ago as 1835, Dr. Andrew Ure (the ideological grandfather of Taylorism and Fordism), argued that the more skilled the workman, “the more self-willed and… the less fit a component of a mechanical system” he became. The solution was to eliminate processes which required “peculiar dexterity and steadiness of hand… from the cunning workman” and replace them by a “mechanism, so self-regulating, that a child may superintend it.” [Philosophy of Manufactures, in Thompson 360]. And the principle has been followed throughout the twentieth century. William Lazonick, David Montgomery, David Noble, and Katherine Stone have produced an excellent body of work on this theme. Even though corporate experiments in worker self-management increase morale and productivity, and reduce injuries and absenteeism, beyond the hopes of management, they are usually abandoned out of fear of loss of control.

Christopher Lasch, in his foreword to Noble’s America by Design, characterized the process of de-skilling in this way:

The capitalist, having expropriated the worker’s property, gradually expropriated his technical knowledge as well, asserting his own mastery over production….

The expropriation of the worker’s technical knowledge had as a logical consequence the growth of modern management, in which technical knowledge came to be concentrated. As the scientific management movement split up production into its component procedures, reducing the worker to an appendage of the machine, a great expansion of technical and supervisory personnel took place in order to oversee the productive process as a whole [pp. xi-xii].

The expropriation of the peasantry and imposition of the factory labor system was not accomplished without resistance; the workers knew exactly what was being done to them and what they had lost. During the 1790s, when rhetoric from the Jacobins and Tom Paine were widespread among the radicalized working class, the rulers of “the cradle of liberty” lived in terror that the country would be swept by revolution. The system of police state controls over the population resembled an alien occupation regime. The Hammonds referred to correspondence between north-country magistrates and the Home Office, in which the law was frankly treated “as an instrument not of justice but of repression,” and the working classes “appear[ed]… conspicuously as a helot population.” [Town Labourer 72]

… in the light of the Home Office papers, …none of the personal rights attaching to Englishmen possessed any reality for the working classes. The magistrates and their clerks recognized no limit to their powers over the freedom and the movements of working men. The Vagrancy Laws seemed to supercede the entire charter of an Englishman’s liberties. They were used to put into prison any man or woman of the working class who seemed to the magistrate an inconvenient or disturbing character. They offered the easiest and most expeditious way of proceeding against any one who tried to collect money for the families of locked-out workmen, or to disseminate literature that the magistrates thought undesirable [Ibid. 80].

Peel’s “bobbies” — professional law enforcement — replaced the posse comitatus system because the latter was inadequate to control a population of increasingly disaffected workmen. In the time of the Luddite and other disturbances, crown officials warned that “to apply the Watch and Ward Act would be to put arms into the hands of the most powerfully disaffected.” At the outset of the wars with France, Pitt ended the practice of quartering the army in alehouses, mixed with the general population. Instead, the manufacturing districts were covered with barracks, as “purely a matter of police.” The manufacturing areas “came to resemble a country under military occupation.” [Ibid. 91-92].

Pitt’s police state was supplemented by quasi-private vigilantism, in the time-honored tradition of blackshirts and death squads ever since. For example the “Association for the Protection of Property against Republicans and Levellers” — an anti-Jacobin association of gentry and mill-owners — conducted house-to-house searches and organized Guy Fawkes-style effigy burnings against Paine; “Church and King” mobs terrorised suspected radicals [Chapter Five, “Planting the Liberty Tree,” in Thompson].

Thompson characterized this system of control as “political and social apartheid,” and argued that “the revolution which did not happen in England was fully as devastating” as the one that did happen in France [pp. 197-198].

Finally, the state aided the growth of manufactures through mercantilism. Modern exponents of the “free market” generally treat mercantilism as a “misguided” attempt to promote some unified national interest, adopted out of sincere ignorance of economic principles. In fact, the architects of mercantilism knew exactly what they were doing. Mercantilism was extremely efficient for its real purpose: making wealthy manufacturing interests rich at the expense of everyone else. Adam Smith consistently attacked mercantilism, not as a product of economic error, but as a quite intelligent attempt by powerful interests to enrich themselves through the coercive power of the state.

British manufacturing was created by state intervention to shut out foreign goods, give British shipping a monopoly of foreign commerce, and stamp out foreign competition by force. As an example of the latter, British authorities in India destroyed the Bengalese textile industry, makers of the highest quality fabric in the world. Although they had not adopted steam-driven methods of production, there is a real possibility that they would have done so, had India remained politically and economically independent. The once prosperous territory of Bengal is today occupied by Bangladesh and the Calcutta area [Chomsky, World Orders Old and New].

The American, German and Japanese industrial systems were created by the same mercantilist policies, with massive tariffs on industrial goods. “Free trade” was adopted by safely established industrial powers, who used “laissez-faire” as an ideological weapon to prevent potential rivals from following the same path of industrialization. Capitalism has never been established by means of the free market, or even by the primary action of the bourgeoisie. It has always been established by a revolution from above, imposed by a pre-capitalist ruling class. In England, it was the landed aristocracy; in France, Napoleon II’s bureaucracy; in Germany, the Junkers; in Japan, the Meiji. In America, the closest approach to a “natural” bourgeois evolution, industrialization was carried out by a mercantilist aristocracy of Federalist shipping magnates and landlords [Harrington, Twilight of Capitalism].

Romantic medievalists like Chesterton and Belloc described the process in the high middle ages by which serfdom had gradually withered away, and the peasants had transformed themselves into de facto freeholders who paid a nominal quit-rent. The feudal class system was disintegrating and being replaced by a much more libertarian and less exploitative one. Immanuel Wallerstein argued that the likely outcome would have been “a system of relatively equal small-scale producers, further flattening out the aristocracies and decentralizing the political structures.” By 1650 the trend had been reversed, and there was “a reasonably high level of continuity between the families that had been high strata” in 1450 and 1650. Capitalism, far from being “the overthrow of a backward aristocracy by a progressive bourgeoisie,” “was brought into existence by a landed aristocracy which transformed itself into a bourgeoisie because the old system was disintegrating.” [Historical Capitalism 41-42, 105-106]. This is echoed in part by Arno Mayer [The Persistence of the Old Regime], who argued for continuity between the landed aristocracy and the capitalist ruling class.

The process by which the high medieval civilization of peasant proprietors, craft guilds and free cities was overthrown, was vividly described by Kropotkin [Mutual Aid 225]. Before the invention of gunpowder, the free cities repelled royal armies more often than not, and won their independence from feudal dues. And these cities often made common cause with peasants in their struggles to control the land. The absolutist state and the capitalist revolution it imposed became possible only when artillery could reduce fortified cities with a high degree of efficiency, and the king could make war on his own people. And in the aftermath of this conquest, the Europe of William Morris was left devastated, depopulated, and miserable.

Peter Tosh had a song called “Four Hundred Years.” Although the white working class has suffered nothing like the brutality of black slavery, there has nevertheless been a “four hundred years” of oppression for all of us under the system of state capitalism established in the seventeenth century. Ever since the birth of the first states six thousand years ago, political coercion has allowed one ruling class or another to live off other people’s labor. But since the seventeenth century the system of power has become increasingly conscious, unified, and global in scale. The current system of transnational state capitalism, without rival since the collapse of the soviet bureaucratic class system, is a direct outgrowth of the seizure of power “four hundred years” ago. Orwell had it backwards. The past is a “boot smashing a human face.” Whether the future is more of the same depends on what we do now.

Ideological Hegemony

Ideological hegemony is the process by which the exploited come to view the world through a conceptual framework provided to them by their exploiters. It acts first of all to conceal class conflict and exploitation behind a smokescreen of “national unity” or “general welfare.” Those who point to the role of the state as guarantor of class privilege are denounced, in theatrical tones of moral outrage, for “class warfare.” If anyone is so unpardonably “extremist” as to describe the massive foundation of state intervention and subsidy upon which corporate capitalism rests, he is sure to be rebuked for “Marxist class war rhetoric” (Bob Novak), or “robber baron rhetoric” (Treasury Secretary O’Neill).

The ideological framework of “national unity” is taken to the point that “this country,” “society,” or “our system of government” is set up as an object of gratitude for “the freedoms we enjoy.” Only the most unpatriotic notice that our liberties, far from being granted to us by a generous and benevolent government, were won by past resistance against the state. Charters and bills of rights were not grants from the state, but were forced on the state from below.

If our liberties belong to us by right of birth, as a moral fact of nature, it follows that we owe the state no debt of gratitude for not violating them, any more than we owe our thanks to another individual for refraining from robbing or killing us. Simple logic implies that, rather than being grateful to “the freest country on earth,” we should raise hell every time it infringes on our liberty. After all, that’s how we got our liberty in the first place. When another individual puts his hand in our pocket to enrich himself at our expense, our natural instinct is to resist. But thanks to patriotism, the ruling class is able to transform their hand in our pocket into “society” or “our country.”

The religion of national unity is most pathological in regard to “defense” and foreign policy. The manufacture of foreign crisis and war hysteria has been used since the beginning of history to suppress threats to class rule. The crooked politicians may work for the “special interests” domestically, but when those same politicians engineer a war it is a matter of loyalty to “our country.”

The Chairman of the JCS, in discussing the “defense” posture, will refer with a straight face to “national security threats” faced by the U. S., and describe the armed forces of some official enemy like China as far beyond “legitimate defensive requirements.” The quickest way to put oneself beyond the pale is to point out that all these “threats” involve what some country on the other side of the world is doing within a hundred miles of its own border. Another offense against fatherland worship is to judge the actions of the United States, in its global operations to keep the Third World safe for ITT and United Fruit Company, by the same standard of “legitimate defensive requirements” applied to China.

In the official ideology, America’s wars by definition are always fought “for our liberties,” to “defend our country,” or in the smarmy world of Maudlin Albright, a selfless desire to promote “peace and freedom” in the world. To suggest that the real defenders of our liberties took up arms against the government, or that the national security state is a greater threat to our liberties than any foreign enemy we have ever faced, is unforgivable. Above all, good Americans don’t notice all those military advisers teaching death squads how to hack off the faces of union organizers and leave them in ditches, or to properly use pliers on a dissident’s testicles. War crimes are only committed by defeated powers. (But as the Nazis learned in 1945, unemployed war criminals can usually find work with the new hegemonic power.)

After a century and a half of patriotic indoctrination by the statist education system, Americans have thoroughly internalized the “little red schoolhouse” version of American history. This authoritarian piety is so diametrically opposed to the beliefs of those who took up arms in the Revolution that the citizenry has largely forgotten what it means to be American. In fact, the authentic principles of Americanism have been stood on their head. Two hundred years ago, standing armies were feared as a threat to liberty and a breeding ground for authoritarian personalities; conscription was associated with the tyranny of Cromwell; wage labor was thought to be inconsistent with the independent spirit of a free citizen. Today, two hundred years later, Americans have been so Prussianized by sixty years of a garrison state and “wars” against one internal enemy or another, that they are conditioned to genuflect at the sight of a uniform. Draft dodgers are equivalent to child molesters. Most people work for some centralized corporate or state bureaucracy, where as a matter of course they are expected to obey orders from superiors, work under constant surveillance, and even piss in a cup on command.

During wartime, it becomes unpatriotic to criticize or question the government and dissent is identified with disloyalty. Absolute faith and obedience to authority is a litmus test of “Americanism.” Foreign war is a very useful tool for manipulating the popular mind and keeping the domestic population under control. War is the easiest way to shift vast, unaccountable new powers to the State. People are most uncritically obedient at the very time they need to be most vigilant.

The greatest irony is that, in a country founded by revolution, “Americanism” is defined as respecting authority and resisting “subversion.” The Revolution was a revolution indeed, in which the domestic political institutions of the colonies were forcibly overthrown. It was, in many times and places, a civil war between classes. But as Voltairine de Cleyre wrote a century ago in “Anarchism and American Traditions,” the version in the history books is a patriotic conflict between our “Founding Fathers” and a foreign enemy. Those who can still quote Jefferson on the right of revolution are relegated to the “extremist” fringe, to be rounded up in the next war hysteria or red scare.

This ideological construct of a unified “national interest” includes the fiction of a “neutral” set of laws, which conceals the exploitative nature of the system of power we live under. Under corporate capitalism the relationships of exploitation are mediated by the political system to an extent unknown under previous class systems. Under chattel slavery and feudalism, exploitation was concrete and personalized in the producer’s relationship with his master. The slave and peasant knew exactly who was screwing them. The modern worker, on the other hand, feels a painful pounding sensation, but has only a vague idea where it is coming from.

Besides its function of masking the ruling class interests behind a facade of “general welfare,” ideological hegemony also manufactures divisions between the ruled. Through campaigns against “welfare cheats” and “deadbeats,” and demands to “get tough on crime,” the ruling class is able to channel the hostility of the middle and working classes against the underclass.

Especially nauseating is the phenomenon of “billionaire populism.” Calls for bankruptcy and welfare “reform,” and for wars on crime, are dressed up in pseudo-populist rhetoric, identifying the underclass as the chief parasites who feed off the producers’ labor. In their “aw, shucks” symbolic universe, you’d think America was a Readers Digest/Norman Rockwell world with nothing but hard-working small businessmen and family farmers, on the one hand, and welfare cheats, deadbeats, union bosses and bureaucrats on the other. From listening to them, you’d never suspect that multi-billionaires or global corporations even exist, let alone that they might stand to benefit from such “populism.”

In the real world, corporations are the biggest clients of the welfare state, the biggest bankruptcies are corporate chapter eleven filings, and the worst crimes are committed in corporate suites rather than on the streets. The real robbery of the average producer consists of profit and usury, extorted only with the help of the state — the real “big government” on our backs. But as long as the working class and the underclass are busy fighting each other, they won’t notice who is really robbing them.

As Stephen Biko said, “The oppressors most powerful weapon is the mind of the oppressed.”

The Money Monopoly

In every system of class exploitation, a ruling class controls access to the means of production in order to extract tribute from labor. Under capitalism, access to capital is restricted by the money monopoly, by which the state or banking system is given a monopoly on the medium of exchange, and alternative media of exchange are prohibited. The money monopoly also includes entry barriers against cooperative banks and prohibitions against private issuance of banknotes, by which access to finance capital is restricted and interest rates are kept artificially high.

Just in passing, we might mention the monumental hypocrisy of the regulation of credit unions in the United States, which require that their membership must share some common bond, like working for the same employer. Imagine the outrage if IGA and Safeway lobbied for a national law to prohibit grocery co-ops unless the members all worked for the same company! One of the most notable supporters of these laws is Phil Gramm, that renowned “free marketeer” and economics professor — and foremost among the banking industry’s whores in Congress.

Individualist and mutualist anarchists like William Greene [Mutual Banking], Benjamin Tucker [Instead of a Book], and J. B. Robertson [The Economics of Liberty] viewed the money monopoly as central to the capitalist system of privilege. In a genuinely free banking market, any group of individuals could form a mutual bank and issue monetized credit in the form of bank notes against any form of collateral they chose, with acceptance of these notes as tender being a condition of membership. Greene speculated that a mutual bank might choose to honor not only marketable property as collateral, but the “pledging … [of] future production.” [p. 73]. The result would be a reduction in interest rates, through competition, to the cost of administrative overhead — less than one percent.

Abundant cheap credit would drastically alter the balance of power between capital and labor, and returns on labor would replace returns on capital as the dominant form of economic activity. According to Robinson,

Upon the monopoly rate of interest for money that is… forced upon us by law, is based the whole system of interest upon capital, that permeates all modern business.

With free banking, interest upon bonds of all kinds and dividends upon stock would fall to the minimum bank interest charge. The so-called rent of houses… would fall to the cost of maintenance and replacement.

All that part of the product which is now taken by interest would belong to the producer. Capital, however… defined, would practically cease to exist as an income producing fund, for the simple reason that if money, wherewith to buy capital, could be obtained for one-half of one per cent, capital itself could command no higher price [pp. 80-81].

And the result would be a drastically improved bargaining position for tenants and workers against the owners of land and capital. According to Gary Elkin, Tucker’s free market anarchism carried certain inherent libertarian socialist implications:

It’s important to note that because of Tucker’s proposal to increase the bargaining power of workers through access to mutual credit, his so-called Individualist anarchism is not only compatible with workers’ control but would in fact promote it. For if access to mutual credit were to increase the bargaining power of workers to the extent that Tucker claimed it would, they would then be able to (1) demand and get workplace democracy, and (2) pool their credit buy and own companies collectively.

The banking monopoly was not only the “lynchpin of capitalism,” but also the seed from which the landlord’s monopoly grew. Without a money monopoly, the price of land would be much lower, and promote “the process of reducing rents toward zero.” [Gary Elkin, “Benjamin Tucker — Anarchist or Capitalist“].

Given the worker’s improved bargaining position, “capitalists’ ability to extract surplus value from the labor of employees would be eliminated or at least greatly reduced.” [Gary Elkin, Mutual Banking]. As compensation for labor approached value-added, returns on capital were driven down by market competition, and the value of corporate stock consequently plummeted, the worker would become a de facto co-owner of his workplace, even if the company remained nominally stockholder-owned.

Near-zero interest rates would increase the independence of labor in all sorts of interesting ways. For one thing, anyone with a twenty-year mortgage at 8% now could, in the absence of usury, pay it off in ten years. Most people in their 30S would have their houses paid off. Between this and the nonexistence of high-interest credit card debt, two of the greatest sources of anxiety to keep one’s job at any cost would disappear. In addition, many workers would have large savings (“go to hell money”). Significant numbers would retire in their forties or fifties, cut back to part-time, or start businesses; with jobs competing for workers, the effect on bargaining power would be revolutionary.

Our hypothetical world of free credit in many ways resembles the situation in colonial societies. E. G. Wakefield, in View of the Art of Colonization, wrote of the unacceptably weak position of the employing class when self-employment with one’s own property was readily available. In colonies, there was a tight labor market and poor labor discipline because of the abundance of cheap land. “Not only does the degree of exploitation of the wage-labourer remain indecently low. The wage-labourer loses into the bargain, along with the relation of dependence, also the sentiment of dependence on the abstemious capitalist.”

Where land is cheap and all men are free, where every one who so pleases can obtain a piece of land for himself, not only is labour very dear, as respects the labourers’ share of the product, but the difficulty is to obtain combined labour at any price.

This environment also prevented the concentration of wealth, as Wakefield commented: “Few, even of those whose lives are unusually long, can accumulate great masses of wealth”. As a result, colonial elites petitioned the mother country for imported labor and for restrictions on land for settlement. According to Wakefield’s disciple Herman Merivale, there was an “urgent desire for cheaper and more subservient labourers — for a class to whom the capitalist might dictate terms, instead of being dictated to by them.” [Maurice Dobb, Studies in the Development of Capitalism; Marx, Chapter 33: “The New Theory of Colonialism,” in Capital Vol. 1].

In addition to all this, central banking systems perform additional service to the interests of capital. First of all, the chief requirement of finance capitalists is to avoid inflation, in order to allow predictable returns on investment. This is ostensibly the primary purpose of the Federal Reserve and other central banks. But at least as important is the role of the central banks in promoting what they consider a “natural” level of unemployment — until the 1990s around six per cent. The reason is that when unemployment goes much below this figure, labor becomes increasingly uppity and presses for better pay and working conditions and more autonomy. Workers are willing to take a lot less crap off the boss when they know they can find a job at least as good the next day. On the other hand, nothing is so effective in “getting your mind right” as the knowledge that people are lined up to take your job.

The Clinton “prosperity” is a seeming exception to this principle. As unemployment threatened to drop below the four per cent mark, some members of the Federal Reserve agitated to raise interest rates and take off the “inflationary” pressure by throwing a few million workers on the street. But as Greenspan [Testimony of Chairman Alan Greenspan] testified before the Senate Banking Committee, the situation was unique. Given the degree of job insecurity in the high-tech economy, there was “[a]typical restraint on compensation increases.” In 1996, even with a tight labor market, 46% of workers at large firms were fearful of layoffs — compared to only 25% in 1991, when unemployment was much higher.

The reluctance of workers to leave their jobs to seek other employment as the labor market tightened has provided further evidence of such concern, as has the tendency toward longer labor union contracts. For many decades, contracts rarely exceeded three years. Today, one can point to five- and six-year contracts — contracts that are commonly characterized by an emphasis on job security and that involve only modest wage increases. The low level of work stoppages of recent years also attests to concern about job security.

Thus the willingness of workers in recent years to trade off smaller increases in wages for greater job security seems to be reasonably well documented. For the bosses, the high-tech economy is the next best thing to high unemployment for keeping our minds right. “Fighting inflation” translates operationally to increasing job insecurity and making workers less likely to strike or to look for new jobs.

Patents

The patent privilege has been used on a massive scale to promote concentration of capital, erect entry barriers, and maintain a monopoly of advanced technology in the hands of western corporations. It is hard even to imagine how much more decentralized the economy would be without it. Right-libertarian Murray Rothbard considered patents a fundamental violation of free market principles.

The man who has not bought a machine and who arrives at the same invention independently, will, on the free market, be perfectly able to use and sell his invention. Patents prevent a man from using his invention even though all the property is his and he has not stolen the invention, either explicitly or implicitly, from the first inventor. Patents, therefore, are grants of exclusive monopoly privilege by the State and are invasions of property rights on the market. [Man, Economy, and State vol. 2 p. 655]

Patents make an astronomical price difference. Until the early 1970s, for example, Italy did not recognize drug patents. As a result, Roche Products charged the British national health a price over 40 times greater for patented components of Librium and Valium than charged by competitors in Italy [Raghavan, Recolonization p. 124].

Patents suppress innovation as much as they encourage it. Chakravarthi Raghavan pointed out that research scientists who actually do the work of inventing are required to sign over patent rights as a condition of employment, while patents and industrial security programs prevent sharing of information, and suppress competition in further improvement of patented inventions. [op. cit. p. 118] Rothbard likewise argued that patents eliminate “the competitive spur for further research” because incremental innovation based on others’ patents is prohibited, and because the holder can “rest on his laurels for the entire period of the patent,” with no fear of a competitor improving his invention. And they hamper technical progress because “mechanical inventions are discoveries of natural law rather than individual creations, and hence similar independent inventions occur all the time. The simultaneity of inventions is a familiar historical fact.” [op. cit. pp. 655, 658-659].

The intellectual property regime under the Uruguay Round of GATT goes far beyond traditional patent law in suppressing innovation. One benefit of traditional patent law, at least, was that it required an invention under patent to be published. Under U.S. pressure, however, “trade secrets” were included in GATT. As a result, governments will be required to help suppress information not formally protected by patents [Raghavan, op. cit. p. 122].

And patents are not necessary as an incentive to innovate. According to Rothbard, invention is rewarded by the competitive advantage accruing to the first developer of an idea. This is borne out by F. M. Scherer’s testimony before the FTC in 1995 [Hearings on Global and Innovation-Based Competition]. Scherer spoke of a survey of 91 companies in which only seven “accorded high significance to patent protection as a factor in their R & D investments.” Most of them described patents as “the least important of considerations.” Most companies considered their chief motivation in R & D decisions to be “the necessity of remaining competitive, the desire for efficient production, and the desire to expand and diversify their sales.” In another study, Scherer found no negative effect on R & D spending as a result of compulsory licensing of patents. A survey of U.S. firms found that 86% of inventions would have been developed without patents. In the case of automobiles, office equipment, rubber products, and textiles, the figure was 100%.

The one exception was drugs, in which 60% supposedly would not have been invented. I suspect disingenuousness on the part of the respondents, however. For one thing, drug companies get an unusually high portion of their R & D funding from the government, and many of their most lucrative products were developed entirely at government expense. And Scherer himself cited evidence to the contrary. The reputation advantage for being the first into a market is considerable. For example in the late 1970s, the structure of the industry and pricing behavior was found to be very similar between drugs with and those without patents. Being the first mover with a non-patented drug allowed a company to maintain a 30% market share and to charge premium prices.

The injustice of patent monopolies is exacerbated by government funding of research and innovation, with private industry reaping monopoly profits from technology it didn’t spend a penny to develop. In 1999, extending the research and experimentation tax credit was, along with extensions of a number of other corporate tax preferences, considered the most urgent business of the Congressional leadership. Hastert, when asked if any elements of the tax bill were essential, said: “I think the [tax preference] extenders are something we’re going to have to work on.” Ways and Means Chair Bill Archer added, “before the year is out… we will do the extenders in a very stripped down bill that doesn’t include anything else.” A five-year extension of the research and experimentation credit (retroactive to 1 July 1999) was expected to cost $13.1 billion. (That credit makes the effective tax rate on R & D spending less than zero.) [Citizens for Tax Justice, GOP Leaders Distill Essence of Tax Plan].

The Government Patent Policy Act of 1980, with 1984 and 1986 amendments, allowed private industry to keep patents on products developed with government R & D money — and then to charge ten, twenty, or forty times the cost of production. For example, AZT was developed with government money and in the public domain since 1964. The patent was given away to Burroughs Wellcome Corp. [Chris Lewis, “Public Assets, Private Profits“].

As if the deck were not sufficiently stacked already, the pharmaceutical companies in 1999 actually lobbied Congress to extend certain patents by two years by a special act of private law [Benjamin Grove, “Gibbons backs drug-monopoly bill“].

Patents have been used throughout the twentieth century “to circumvent antitrutst laws,” according to David Noble. They were “bought up in large numbers to suppress competition,” which also resulted in “the suppression of invention itself.” [America by Design, pp. 84-109]. Edwin Prindle, a corporate patent lawyer, wrote in 1906:

Patents are the best and most effective means of controlling competition. They occasionally give absolute command of the market, enabling their owner to name the price without regard to the cost of production…. Patents are the only legal form of absolute monopoly [America by Design p. 90].

Patents played a key role in the formation of the electrical appliance, communications, and chemical industries. G. E. and Westinghouse expanded to dominate the electrical manufacturing market at the turn of the century largely through patent control. In 1906 they curtailed the patent litigation between them by pooling their patents. AT&T also expanded “primarily through strategies of patent monopoly.” The American chemical industry was marginal until 1917, when Attorney-General Mitchell Palmer seized German patents and distributed them among the major American chemical companies. DuPont got licenses on 300 of the 735 patents [America by Design pp. 10, 16].

Patents are also being used on a global scale to lock the transnational corporations into a permanent monopoly of productive technology. The single most totalitarian provision of the Uruguay Round is probably its “intellectual property” provisions. GATT has extended both the scope and duration of patents far beyond anything ever envisioned in original patent law. In England, patents were originally for fourteen years — the time needed to train two journeymen in succession (and by analogy, the time necessary to go into production and reap the initial profit for originality). By that standard, given the shorter training times required today, and the shorter lifespan of technology, the period of monopoly should be shorter. Instead, the U.S. seeks to extend them to fifty years [Raghavan, Recolonization pp. 119-120]. According to Martin Khor Kok Peng, the U.S. is by far the most absolutist of the participants in the Uruguay Round. Unlike the European Community, and for biological processes for animal and plant protection [The Uruguay Round and Third World Sovereigntyp. 28].

The provisions for biotech are really a way of increasing trade barriers, and forcing consumers to subsidize the TNCs engaged in agribusiness. The U.S. seeks to apply patents to genetically-modified organisms, effectively pirating the work of generations of Third World breeders by isolating beneficial genes in traditional varieties and incorporating them in new GMOs — and maybe even enforcing patent rights against the traditional variety which was the source of the genetic material. For example Monsanto has attempted to use the presence of their DNA in a crop as prima facie evidence of pirating — when it is much more likely that their variety cross-pollinated and contaminated the farmer’s crop against his will. The Pinkerton agency, by the way, plays a leading role in investigating such charges — that’s right, the same folks who have been breaking strikes and kicking organizers down stairs for the past century. Even jack-booted thugs have to diversify to make it in the global economy.

The developed world has pushed particularly hard to protect industries relying on or producing “generic technologies,” and to restrict diffusion of “dual use” technologies. The U. S.-Japanese trade agreement on semi-conductors, for example, is a “cartel-like, ‘managed trade’ agreement.” So much for “free trade.” [Dieter Ernst, “Technology, Economic Security and Latecomer Idustrialization,” in Raghavan Pp. 39-40].

Patent law traditionally required a holder to work the invention in a country in order to receive patent protection. U.K. law allowed compulsory licensing after three years if an invention was not being worked, or being worked fully, and demand was being met “to a substantial extent” by importation; or where the export market was not being supplied because of the patentee’s refusal to grant licenses on reasonable terms [Raghavan pp. 120, 138].

The central motivation in the GATT intellectual property regime, however, is to permanently lock in the collective monopoly of advanced technology by TNCs, and prevent independent competition from ever arising in the Third World. It would, as Martin Khor Kok Peng writes, “effectively prevent the diffusion of technology to the Third World, and would tremendously increase monopoly royalties of the TNCs whilst curbing the potential devel- opment of Third World technology.” Only one percent of patents worldwide are owned in the Third World. Of patents granted in the 1970s by Third World countries, 84% were foreign-owned. But fewer than 5% of foreign-owned patents were actually used in production. As we saw before, the purpose of owning a patent is not necessarily to use it, but to prevent anyone else from using it [op. cit. pp. 29-30].

Raghavan summed up nicely the effect on the Third World:

Given the vast outlays in R and D and investments, as well as the short life cycle of some of these products, the leading Industrial Nations are trying to prevent emergence of competition by controlling… the flows of technology to others. The Uruguay round is being sought to be used to create export monopolies for the products of Industrial Nations, and block or slow down the rise of competitive rivals, particularly in the newly industrializing Third World countries. At the same time the technologies of senescent industries of the north are sought to be exported to the South under conditions of assured rentier income [op. cit. p. 96].

Corporate propagandists piously denounce anti-globalists as enemies of the Third World, seeking to use trade barriers to maintain an affluent Western lifestyle at the expense of the poor nations. The above measures — trade barriers — to permanently suppress Third World technology and keep the South as a big sweatshop, give the lie to this “humanitarian” concern. This is not a case of differing opinions, or of sincerely mistaken understanding of the facts. Setting aside false subtleties, what we see here is pure evil at work — Orwell’s “boot stamping on a human face forever.” If any architects of this policy believe it to be for general human well-being, it only shows the capacity of ideology to justify the oppressor to himself and enable him to sleep at night.

Infrastructure

Spending on transportation and communications networks from general revenues, rather than from taxes and user fees, allows big business to “externalize its costs” on the public, and conceal its true operating expenses. Chomsky described this state capitalist underwriting of shipping costs quite accurately:

One well-known fact about trade is that it’s highly subsidized with huge market-distorting factors…. The most obvious is that every form of transport is highly subsidized…. Since trade naturally requires transport, the costs of transport enter into the calculation of the efficiency of trade. But there are huge subsidies to reduce the costs of transport, through manipulation of energy costs and all sorts of market-distorting functions [“How Free is the Free Market?”].

Every wave of concentration of capital has followed a publicly subsidized infrastructure system of some sort. The national railroad system, built largely on free or below-cost land donated by the government, was followed by concentration in heavy industry, petrochemicals, and finance. The next major infrastructure projects were the national highway system, starting with the system of designated national highways in the 1920s and culminating with Eisenhower’s interstate system; and the civil aviation system, built almost entirely with federal money. The result was massive concentration in retail, agriculture, and food processing.

The third such project was the infrastructure of the worldwide web, originally built by the Pentagon. It permits, for the first time, direction of global operations in real time from a single corporate headquarters, and is accelerating the concentration of capital on a global scale. To quote Chomsky again,

The telecommunications revolution… is… another state component of the international economy that didn’t develop through private capital, but through the public paying to destroy themselves… [Class Warfare p. 40].

The centralized corporate economy depends for its existence on a shipping price system which is artificially distorted by government intervention. To fully grasp how dependent the corporate economy is on socializing transportation and communications costs, imagine what would happen if truck and aircraft fuel were taxed enough to pay the full cost of maintenance and new building costs on highways and airports; and if fossil fuels depletion allowances were removed. The result would be a massive increase in shipping costs. Does anyone seriously believe that Wal-Mart could continue to undersell local retailers, or corporate agribusiness could destroy the family farm?

Intellectually honest right-libertarians freely admit as much. For example, Tiber Machan wrote in The Freeman that

Some people will say that stringent protection of rights [against eminent domain] would lead to small airports, at best, and many constraints on construction. Of course — but what’s so wrong with that?

Perhaps the worst thing about modern industrial life has been the power of political authorities to grant special privileges to some enterprises to violate the rights of third parties whose permission would be too expensive to obtain. The need to obtain that permission would indeed seriously impede what most environmentalists see as rampant — indeed reckless — industrialization.

The system of private property rights — in which… all… kinds of… human activity must be conducted within one’s own realm except where cooperation from others has been gained voluntarily — is the greatest moderator of human aspirations…. In short, people may reach goals they aren’t able to reach with their own resources only by convincing others, through arguments and fair exchanges, to cooperate [“On Airports and Individual Rights“].

The logjams and bottlenecks in the transportation system are an inevitable result of subsidies. Those who debate the reason for planes stacked up at O’Hare airport, or decry the fact that highways and bridges are deteriorating several times faster than repairs are being budgeted, need only read an economics 101 text. Market prices are signals that relate supply to demand. When subsidies distort these signals, the consumer does not perceive the real cost of producing the goods he consumes. The “feedback loop” is broken, and demands on the system overwhelm it beyond its ability to respond. When people don’t have to pay the real cost of something they consume, they aren’t very careful about only using what they need.

It is interesting that every major antitrust action in this century has involved either some basic energy resource, or some form of infrastructure, on which the overall economy depends. Standard Oil, AT&T, and Microsoft were all cases in which monopoly price gouging was a danger to the economy as a whole. This brings to mind Engels’ observation that advanced capitalism would reach a stage where the state — “the official representative of capitalist society” — would have to convert “the great institutions for intercourse and communication” into state property. Engels did not foresee the use of antitrust actions to achieve the same end [Anti-Duhring].

“Military Keynesianism”

The leading sectors of the economy, including cybernetics, communications, and military industry, have their sales and profits virtually guaranteed by the state. The entire manufacturing sector, as a whole, was permanently expanded beyond recognition by an infusion of federal money during World War II. In 1939 the entire manufacturing plant of the U.S. was valued at $40 billion. By 1945, another $26 billion worth of plant and equipment had been built, “two thirds of it paid for directly from government funds.” The top 250 corporations in 1939 owned 65% of plant and equipment, but during the war operated 79% of all new facilities built with government funds [Mills,The Power Elite p. 101].

Machine tools were vastly expanded by the war. In 1940, 23% of machine tools in use were less than 10 years old. By 1945, the figure had grown to 62%. The industry contracted rapidly after 1945, and would probably have gone into a depression, had it not returned to wartime levels of output during Korea and remained that way throughout the Cold War. The R & D complex, likewise, was a creation of the war. Between 1939 and 1945, the share of AT&T research expenditures made up of government contracts expanded from 1% to 83%. Over 90% of the patents resulting from government-funded wartime research were given away to industry. The modern electronics industry was largely a product of World War II and Cold War spending (e.g., miniaturization of circuits for bomb proximity fuses, high capacity computers for command and control, etc.) [Noble,Forces of Production pp. 8-16].

The jumbo jet industry would never have come about without continuous Cold War levels of military spending. The machine tools needed for producing large aircraft were so complex and expensive that no “small peacetime orders” would have provided a sufficient production run to pay for them. Without large military orders, they would simply not have existed. The aircraft industry quickly spiraled into red ink after 1945, and was near bankruptcy at the beginning of the 1948 war scare, after which Truman restored it to life with massive spending. By 1964, 90% of aerospace R & D was funded by the government, with massive spillover into the electronics, machine tool, and other industries [Noble, Forces of Production pp. 6-7; Kofsky, Harry S. Truman and the War Scare of 1948].

Other Subsidies

Infrastructure and military spending are not the only examples of the process by which cost and risk are socialized, and profit is privatized — or, as Rothbard put it, by which “our corporate state uses the coercive taxing power either to accumulate corporate capital or to lower corporate costs.” [“Confessions of a Right-Wing Liberal“]. Some of these government assumptions of risk and cost are ad hoc and targeted toward specific industries.

Among the greatest beneficiaries of such underwriting are electrical utilities. Close to 100% of all research and development for nuclear power is either performed by the government itself, in its military reactor program, or by lump-sum R & D grants; the government waives use-charges for nuclear fuels, subsidizes uranium production, provides access to government land below market price (and builds hundreds of miles of access roads at taxpayer expense), enriches uranium, and disposes of waste at sweetheart prices. The Price-Anderson Act of 1957 limited the liability of the nuclear power industry, and assumed government liability above that level [Adams and Brock pp. 279-281]. A Westinghouse official admitted in 1953,

If you were to inquire whether Westinghouse might consider putting up its own money.., we would have to say “No.” The cost of the plant would be a question mark until after we built it and, by that sole means, found out the answer. We would not be sure of successful plant operation until after we had done all the work and operated successfully…. This is still a situation of pyramiding uncertainties…. There is a distinction between risk-taking and recklessness [Ibid. pp. 278-279].

So much for profit as a reward for the entrepreneur’s risk. These “entrepreneurs” make their profits in the same way as a seventeenth-century courtier, by obtaining the favor of the king. To quote Chomsky,

The sectors of the economy that remain competitive are those that feed from the public trough…. The glories of Free Enterprise provide a useful weapon against government policies that might benefit the general population…. But the rich and powerful… have long appreciated the need to protect themselves from the destructive forces of free-market capitalism, which may provide suitable themes for rousing oratory, but only so long as the public handout and the regulatory and protectionist apparatus are secure, and state power is on call when needed (Chomsky, Deterring Democracy p. 144].

Dwayne Andreas, the CEO of Archer Daniels Midland, admitted that “[t]here is not one grain of anything in the world that is sold in the free market. Not one. The only place you see a free market is in the speeches of politicians.” [Don Carney, “Dwayne’s World“].

Big business also enjoys financial support through the tax code. It is likely that most of the Fortune 500 would go bankrupt without corporate welfare. Direct federal tax breaks to business in 1996 were close to $350 billion [Based on my crunching on numbers in Zepezauer and Naiman, Take the Rich Off- Welfare]. This figure, for federal corporate welfare alone, is over two-thirds of annual corporate profits for 1996 ($460 billion) [Statistical Abstract of the United States 1996].

Estimates of state and local tax breaks is fairly impressionistic, since they vary not only with each critic’s subjective definition of “corporate welfare,” but involve the tax codes of fifty states and the public records of thousands of municipalities. Besides money pimps in the state and local governments are embarrassed by the sweet deals they give their corporate johns. In my own state of Arkansas, the incorruptible Baptist preacher who serves as governor opposed a bill to require quarterly public reports from the Department of Economic Development on its special tax breaks to businesses. “[K]eeping incentive records from public scrutiny is important in attracting business,” and releasing “proprietary information” could have a “chilling effect.” [Arkansas Democrat-Gazette 3 Feb. 2001]. But state and local corporate welfare could easily amount to a figure comparable to federal.

Taken as a whole, direct tax breaks to business at all levels of government are probably on the same order of magnitude as corporate profits. And this understates the effect of corporate welfare, since it disproportionately goes to a handful of giant firms in each industry. For example, accelerated depreciation favors expansion by existing firms. New firms find it of little benefit, since they are likely to lose money their first few years. An established firm, however, can run a loss in a new venture and charge the accelerated depreciation against its profits on old facilities [Baratz, “Corporate Giants and the Power Structure“].

The most outrageous of these tax expenditures is the subsidy to the actual financial transactions by which capital is concentrated. The interest deduction on corporate debt, most of which was run up on leveraged buyouts and acquisitions, costs the treasury over $200 billion a year [Zepezauer p. 122-123]. Without this deduction, the wave of mergers in the 1980s, or the megamergers of the 1990s, could never have taken place. On top of everything else, this acts as a massive direct subsidy to banking, increasing the power of finance capital in the corporate economy to a level greater than it has been since the Age of Morgan.

A closely related subsidy is the exemption from capital gains of securities transactions involved in corporate mergers (i.e. “stock swaps”) — even though premiums are usually paid well over the market value of the stock [Green p. 11]. The 1986 tax reform included a provision which prevented corporations from deducting fees for investment ‘banks and advisers involved in leveraged buyouts. The 1996 minimum wage increase repealed this provision, with one exception: interest deductions were removed for employee buyouts [Judis, “Bare Minimum“].

Right-libertarians like Rothbard object to classifying tax expenditures as subsidies. It presumes that tax money rightfully belongs to the government, when in fact the government is only letting them keep what is rightfully theirs. The tax code is indeed unfair, but the solution is to eliminate the taxes for everyone, not to level the code up [Rothbard, Power and Market p. 104]. This is a very shaky argument. Supporters of tax code reform in the 1980s insisted that the sole legitimate purpose of taxation was to raise revenue, not to provide carrots and sticks for social engineering purposes. And, semantic quibbling aside, the current tax system would be exactly the same if we started out with zero tax rates and then imposed a punitive tax only on those not engaged in favored activities. Either way, the uneven tax policy gives a competitive advantage to privileged industries.

Political Repression

In times of unusual popular consciousness and mobilization, when the capitalist system faces grave political threats, the state resorts to repression until the danger is past. The major such waves in this country — the Haymarket reaction, and the red scares after the world wars — are recounted by Goldstein [Political Repression in Modern America]. But the wave of repression which began in the 1970s, though less intense, has been permanently institutionalized to a unique extent.

Until the late 1960s, elite perspective was governed by the New Deal social contract. The corporate state would buy stability and popular acquiescence in imperialist exploitation abroad by guaranteeing a level of prosperity and security to the middle class. In return for higher wages, unions would enforce management control of the workplace. But starting during the Vietnam era, the elite’s thinking underwent a profound change.

They concluded from the 1960s experience that the social contract had failed. In response to the antiwar protests and race riots, LBJ and Nixon began to create an institutional framework for martial law, to make sure that any such disorder in the future could be dealt with differently. Johnson’s operation GARDEN PLOT involved domestic surveillance by the military, contingency plans for military cooperation with local police in suppressing disorder in all fifty states, plans for mass preventive detention, and joint exercises of police and the regular military [Morales, U.S. Military Civil Disturbance Planning]. Governor Reagan and his National Guard chief Louis Giuffrida were enthusiastic supporters of GARDEN PLOT exercises in California. Reagan was also a pioneer in creating quasi-military SWAT teams, which now exist in every major town.

The wave of wildcat strikes in the early 1970s showed that organized labor could no longer keep its part of the bargain, and that the social contract should be reassessed. At the same time, the business press was flooded with articles on the impending “capital shortage,” and calls for shifting resources from consumption to capital accumulation. They predicted frankly that a cap on real wages would be hard to force on the public in the existing political environment [Boyte, Backyard Revolution pp. 13-16]. This sentiment was expressed by Huntington et al. in The Crisis of Democracy (a paper for the Trilateral Institution — a good proxy for elite thinking); they argued that the system was collapsing from demand overload, because of an excess of democracy.

Corporations embraced the full range of union-busting possibilities in Taft-Hartley, risking only token fines from the NLRB. They drastically increased management resources devoted to workplace surveillance and control, a necessity because of discontent from stagnant wages and mounting workloads [Fat and Mean]. Wages as a percentage of value added have declined drastically since the 1970s; all increases in labor productivity have been channeled into profit and investment, rather than wages. A new Cold War military buildup further transferred public resources to industry.

A series of events like the fall of Saigon, the nonaligned movement, and the New International Economic Order were taken as signs that the transnational corporate empire was losing control. Reagan’s escalating intervention in Central America was a partial response to this perception. But more importantly the Uruguay Round of GATT snatched total victory from the jaws of defeat; it ended all barriers to TNCs buying up entire economies, locked the west into monopoly control of modern technology, and created a world government on behalf of global corporations.

In the meantime the U.S. was, in the words of Richard K. Moore, importing techniques of social control from the imperial periphery to the core area. With the help of the Drug War and the National Security State, the apparatus of repression continued to grow. The Drug War has turned the Fourth Amendment into toilet paper; civil forfeiture, with the aid of jailhouse snitches, gives police the power to steal property without ever filing charges — a lucrative source of funds for helicopters and kevlar vests. SWAT teams have led to the militarization of local police forces, and cross-training with the military has led many urban police departments to view the local population as an occupied enemy [Weber, Warrior Cops].

Reagan’s crony Giuffrida resurfaced as head of FEMA, where he worked with Oliver North to fine-tune GARDEN PLOT. North, as the NSC liaison with FEMA from 1982-84, developed a plan “to suspend the constitution in the event of a national crisis, such as nuclear war, violent and widespread internal dissent or national opposition to a U.S. military invasion abroad.” [Chardy, “Reagan Aides and the ‘Secret’ Government“]. GARDEN PLOT, interestingly, was implemented during the Rodney King Riots and in recent anti-globalization protests. Delta Force provided intelligence and advice in those places and at Waco [Rosenberg, The Empire Strikes Back; Cockburn, The Jackboot State].

Another innovation is to turn everyone we deal with into a police agent. Banks routinely report “suspicious” movements of cash; under “know your customer” programs, retailers report purchases of items which can conceivably be used in combination to manufacture drugs; libraries come under pressure to report on readers of “subversive” material; DARE programs turn kids into police informers.

Computer technology has increased the potential for surveillance to Orwellian levels. Pentium III processors were revealed to embed identity codes in every document written on them. Police forces are experimenting with combinations of public cameras, digital face-recognition technology, and databases of digital photos. Image Data LLC, a company in the process of buying digital drivers licence photos from all fifty states, was exposed as a front for the Secret Service.

Conclusion

It is almost too easy to bring back Bob Novak and Secretary O’Neill for another kick — but I can’t resist. “Marxist class warfare?” “Robber baron rhetoric?” Well, the pages above recount the “class warfare” waged by the robber barons themselves. If their kind tend to squeal like pigs when we talk about class, it’s because they’ve been stuck. But all the squealing in the world won’t change the facts.

But what are the implications of the above facts for our movement? It is commonly acknowledged that the manorial economy was founded on force. Although you will never see the issue addressed by Milton Friedman, intellectually honest right libertarians like Rothbard acknowledge the role of the state in creating European feudalism and American slavery. Rothbard, drawing the obvious conclusion from this fact, acknowledged the right of peasants or freed slaves to take over their “forty acres and a mule” without compensation to the landlord.

But we have seen that industrial capitalism, to the same extent as manorialism or slavery, was founded on force. Like its predecessors, capitalism could not have survived at any point in its history without state intervention. Coercive state measures at every step have denied workers access to capital, forced them to sell their labor in a buyer’s market, and protected the centers of economic power from the dangers of the free market. To quote Benjamin Tucker again, landlords and capitalists cannot extract surplus value from labor without the help of the state. The modern worker, like the slave or the serf, is the victim of ongoing robbery; he works in an enterprise built from past stolen labor. By the same principles that Rothbard recognized in the agrarian realm, the modern worker is justified in taking direct control of production, and keeping the entire product of his labor.

In a very real sense, every subsidy and privilege described above is a form of slavery. Slavery, simply put, is the use of coercion to live off of someone else’s labor. For example, consider the worker who pays $300 a month for a drug under patent, that would cost $30 in a free market. If he is paid $15 an hour, the eighteen hours he works every month to pay the difference are slavery. Every hour worked to pay usury on a credit card or mortgage is slavery. The hours worked to pay unnecessary distribution and marketing costs (comprising half of retail prices), because of subsidies to economic centralization, is slavery. Every additional hour someone works to meet his basic needs, because the state tilts the field in favor of the bosses and forces him to sell his labor for less than it is worth, is slavery.

All these forms of slavery together probably amount to half our working hours. If we kept the full value of our labor, we could probably maintain current levels of consumption with a work week of twenty hours. As Bill Haywood said, “for every man who gets a dollar he didn’t sweat for, someone else sweated to produce a dollar he never received.”

Our survey also casts doubt on the position of “anarchist” social democrat Noam Chomsky, who is notorious for his distinction between “visions” and “goals.” His long-term vision is a decentralized society of self-governing communities and workplaces, loosely federated together — the traditional anarchist vision. His immediate goal, however, is to strengthen the regulatory state in order to break up “private concentrations of power,” before anarchism can be achieved. But if , as we have seen, capitalism is dependent on the state to guarantee it survival, it follows that it is sufficient to eliminate the statist props to capitalism. In a letter of 4 September 1867, Engels aptly summed up the difference between anarchists and state socialists: “They say ‘abolish the state and capital will go to the devil.’ We propose the reverse.” Exactly.

Sources

Morton S. Baratz. “Corporate Giants and the Power Structure,” in Richard Gillam, ed., Power in Postwar America (Boston: Little, Brown, and Co., 1971).

Harry C. Boyte. The Backyard Revolution: Understanding the New Citizen Movement (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1980).

Don Carney. “Dwayne’s World,” at http://www.motherjones.com/mother_jones/JA95/carney.html

Alfonso Chardy. “Reagan Aides and the ‘Secret’ Government” Miami Herald 5 July 1987, at http://www.totse.com/en/conspiracy/the_new_world_order/scrtgovt.html

Noam Chomsky. Class Warfare: Interviews with David Barsamian (Monroe, Maine: Common Courage Press, 1996)

Chomsky. How Free is the Free Market? Resurgence no. 173. http://www.oneworld.org/second_opinion/chomsky.html

Chomsky. World Orders Old and New (New York: Columbia University Press, 1998).

Citizens for Tax Justice. “GOP Leaders Distill Essence of Tax Plan: Surprise! It’s Corporate Welfare” 14 September 1999, at http://www.ctj.org/pdf/corp0999.pdf

Alexander Cockburn. “The Jackboot State: The War Came Home and We’re Losing It” Counterpunch 10 May 2000, at http://www.counterpunch.org/jackboot.html

Maurice Dobbs. Studies in the Development of Capitalism (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, Ltd, 1963).

Gary Elkin. Benjamin Tucker–Anarchist or Capitalist? at http://flag.blackened.net/davo/anarchism/tucker/an_or_cap.html

Elkin. Mutual Banking. available through http://www.subsitu.com

Friedrich Engels. Anti-Duhring. Marx and Engels, Collected Works v. 25 (New York: International Publishers, 1987).

Edgar Friedenberg. The Disposal of Liberty and Other Industrial Wastes (Garden City, N.Y.: Anchor, 1976).

Robert Goldstein. Political Repression in America: 1870 to the Present (Cambridge, New York: Schenkman Publishing Co’, 1978).

David M. Gordon. Fat and Mean: The Corporate Squeeze of Working Americans and the Myth of Management Downsizing (New York: The Free Press, 1996).

William B. Greene. Mutual Banking (New York: Gordon Press, 1849, 1974).

Benjamin Grove. “Gibbons Backs Drug Monopoly Bill,” Las Vegas Sun 18 February 2000, at http://www.ahc.umn.edu/NewsAlert/Feb00/022100NewsAlert/44500.htm

J.L. and Barbara Hammond. The Town Labourer (1760-1832) 2 vols. (London: Longmans, Green & Co., 1917)

Hammonds. The Village Labourer (1760-1832) (London: Longmans, Green & Co., 1913).

Michael Harrington. Socialism (New York: Bantam, 1970, 1972).

Harrington. The Twilight of Capitalism (Simon and Schuster, 1976).

Hearings on Global and Innovation-Based Competition. FTC, 29 November 1995, at http://www.ftc.gov/opp/gc112195.pdf

John Judis. “Bare Minimum: Goodies for the Rich Hidden in Wage Bill,” The New Republic 28 October 1996, in Project Censored Yearbook 1997 (New York: Seven Stories Press, 1997).

Frank Kofsky. Harry S. Truman and the War Scare of 1948 (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1993).

Peter Kropotkin. Mutual Aid: A Factor of Evolution (New York: Doubleday, Page & Co., 1909).

William Lazonick. Business Organization and the Myth of the Market Economy (Cambridge University Press, 1991).

Lazonick. Competitive Advantage on the Shop Floor (Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press, 1990).

Chris Lewis. “Public Assets, Private Profits,” Multinational Monitor, in Project Censored Yearbook 1994 (New York: Seven Stories Press, 1994).

Tiber Machan. “On Airports and Individual Rights,” The Freeman: Ideas on Liberty. February 1999.

Steven A. Marglin. “What Do Bosses Do? The Origins and Functions of Hierarchy in Capitalist Production–Part I” Review of Radical Political Economics 6:2 (Summer 1974).

Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels. Capital vol. 1, Collected Works v. 35 (New York: International Publishers, 1996).

Seymour Melman. Profits Without Production. (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1983).

C. Wright Mills. The Power Elite (Oxford University Press, 1956, 2000).

David Montgomery. The Fall of the House of Labor (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1979).

Montgomery. Workers Control in America (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1979).

Richard K. Moore. “Escaping the Matrix” Whole Earth (Summer 2000).

Frank Morales. “U.S. Military Civil Disturbance Planning: The War at Home” Covert Action Quarterly 69, Spring-Summer 2000, at http://infowar.net/warathome/warathome.html

David F. Noble. America By Design: Science, Technology, and the Rise of Corporate Capitalism (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1977).

Noble. Forces of Production: A Social History of Industrial Automation (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1984).

Martin Khor Kok Peng. The Uruguay Round and Third World Sovereignty (Penang, Malaysia: Third World Network, 1990).

Chakravarthi Raghavan. Recolonization: GATT, the Uruguay Round & the Third World (Penang, Malaysia: Third World Network, 1990).

J. B. Robertson. The Economics of Liberty. (Mineapolis: Herman Kuehn, 1916).

Paul Rosenberg. “The Empire Strikes Back: Police Repression of Protest From Seattle to L.A.” L.A. Independent Media Center 13 August 2000, at http://www.r2kphilly.org/pdf/empire-strikes.pdf

Murray Rothbard. “Confessions of a Right-Wing Liberal,” in Henry J. Silverman, ed., American Radical Thought (Lexington, Mass.: D.C. Heath and Co., 1970).

Rothbard. Man, Economy, and State: A Treatise on Economic Principles (Los Angeles: Nash Publishing, 1952, 1970).

Rothbard. Power and Market (New York: New York University Press, 1977).

Adam Smith. The Wealth of Nations. Great Books edition (Encyclopedia Brittanica, Inc., 1952).

Testimony of Chairman Alan Greenspan. U. S. Senate Committee on Banking, Housing, and Urban Affairs. 26 February 1997, at http://www.federalreserve.gov//boarddocs/hh/1997/february/testimony/htm

E. P. Thompson. The Making of the English Working Class (New York: Vintage, 1963, 1966).

Benjamin Tucker. Instead of a Book, by a Man Too Busy to Write One (New York: Haskell House Publishers, 1897 1969).

Immanuel Wallerstein. Historical Capitalism (London, New York: Verso, 1983).

Diane Cecilia Weber. “Warrior Cops: The Ominous Growth of Paramilitarism in American Police Departments” Cato Briefing Paper No. 50, 26 August 1999, at http://www.cato.org/pubs/briefs/bp-050es.html

Mark Zepezauer and Arthur Naiman. Take the Rich Off Welfare (Odonian Press/Common Courage Press, 1996).

Commentary
Debt Forgiveness: End the Student Loan Industrial Complex

On April 15th, the Department of Education stated it is “working on a process to help federal student loan borrowers submit a defense to repayment of their federal student loans.” The statement came with a press release announcing that the federal government will fine Corinthian Colleges $29.6 million for lying to students about its jobs placement numbers. The DOE cites nearly 1,000 cases of outright lying to students, including one incident where an accounting students previous position at Taco Bell was listed as a successful job placement.

“Defense to repayment” refers to an obscure provision that forgives federal student loans when “schools have done something wrong” according to state law. Over 250 Corinthian College Students have requested their loans be forgiven on these grounds. The DOE is now working towards a formal process for addressing such requests, as none has existed before. Activists from the National Consumer Law Center and New America Foundation express concern that the new process will impose arbitrary requirements on those seeking debt relief or become a “horrible web of red tape.” For profit-colleges are notorious for their dishonest recruitment and surprise expenses. They are known to prey upon those with few options, who are looking to get out of tough situations. Their outright fraud is completely incompatible with a free society.

Worse, a major source of funding for the for-profit college industry is Federal Student Loans. It is debatable whether the student loans program will cost or earn billions of dollars for the government over the next decade, depending on what accounting system is used, but it is a clear conflict of interest for the state to be earning interest off dishonest education schemes.

The student debt crisis is not limited to students in for-profit schools, but state institutions as well. Federal Student loans have the problem of being one size fits all. In a market setting, lenders would be able to assess student’s future prospects before lending. By making student loans so widely available the state contributes to making higher education a “must have” for even entry level jobs. Corporations are now able to abandon in-house education, shifting costs to tax payers and students. Degrees themselves have become commodities rather than the skills acquired. In such an environment, Universities are able to charge students for four years of irrelevant courses rather than simply granting the degree or certification for a specific trade or skill. Furthermore, it allows corporations to justify shifting greater percentages of their pay to overly credentialed upper management. The same happens at universities themselves as administration costs and tuition sky-rocket, while cuts are made everywhere else.

The end result is students forced to choose between overpriced state colleges or predatory for-profit schools. The banking interests who benefit from this situation also benefit from a series of laws making it near impossible to absolve student debt through bankruptcy (unlike other types of debt). The state also makes it difficult to create alternatives to this system, as anyone seeking to start their own college or trade school will have costly red tape to work through. It funds predatory for-profit institutions and over-priced public institutions, while artificially raising the credentials needed for entry level work. The state is at the heart of the debt crisis. Let’s forgive the debt it creates and kill the student loan industrial complex.

Italian, Stateless Embassies
La “Proprietà Intellettuale” Uccide

Il sette aprile, il New York Times (Bernice Dahn, “Yes, We Were Warned About Ebola”) ha fatto questa rivelazione: l’epidemia di Ebola in Liberia era stata adeguatamente annunciata, ma nessuno era giunto alla giusta conclusione e nessuno aveva agito di conseguenza perché le informazioni necessarie erano nascoste in un articolo a pagamento pubblicato da una rivista accademica. L’articolo, pubblicato su Annals of Virology, avvertiva nel 1982 che, già dalla sua scoperta alla metà degli anni settanta, il virus era ormai endemico nella Liberia nordoccidentale. Purtroppo, nessuno in Liberia ci fece caso perché scaricare l’articolo costava 45 dollari, circa mezza paga settimanale di un medico liberiano.

Aaron Swartz combatté coraggiosamente per liberare la ricerca accademica da questi recinti corporativi, e a causa dei suoi sforzi fu spinto al suicidio da un pubblico ministero bigotto ossessionato dal desiderio di aggiungere un’altra condanna di alto profilo al suo curriculum. Si può dire che questo fu un altro esempio di come la “proprietà intellettuale” uccide.

Come se non bastasse il contributo dato dal fatto di aver nascosto un articolo dietro un accesso a pagamento, l’epidemia di Ebola, che ha ucciso diecimila persone, è aggravata dal fatto che la distribuzione dei vaccini è impedita da una disputa sul brevetto. Anche se a possedere il brevetto è lo stato canadese, la società a cui è stato concessa la licenza ha impedito la distribuzione del vaccino per paura di perdere il controllo sul suo sviluppo.

Questo è solo l’ultimo esempio di una lotta in corso. Da anni la distribuzione di medicinali gratis, come quelli per l’aids, ha costituito materia di contenzioso tra i governi di paesi del terzo mondo e le compagnie farmaceutiche americane.

L’amministrazione Obama sta cercando, ostinatamente, di far passare regole globali sulla “proprietà intellettuale” che non farebbero altro che peggiorare il problema. L’Accordo Trans-Pacifico, è un accordo che ha come principale forza propulsiva le aziende americane, proprietarie di copyright e brevetti, che agiscono tramite i loro tirapiedi noti come Rappresentanti per il Commercio per gli Stati Uniti. Questo accordo rafforzerebbero le leggi internazionali sui farmaci brevettati, portandole al livello degli standard americani. Questo significa estendere la possibilità di rinnovo perpetuo dei brevetti, così che questi non scadrebbero mai. E molti farmaci generici salvavita, attualmente disponibili in molti paesi in via di sviluppo grazie a leggi locali, diventerebbero fuorilegge.

Al centro di questi cosiddetti “accordi di libero mercato” è l’imposizione, per conto dei colossi industriali che dipendono dalla “proprietà intellettuale” per i loro profitti, di una forma di protezionismo molto più costrittiva e dannosa dei dazi. La “proprietà intellettuale” ha la stessa funzione che avevano i dazi doganali un secolo fa, solo che oggi le aziende hanno dimensioni globali più che nazionali, e le barriere protezionistiche vengono erette attorno alle aziende più che attorno agli stati. In entrambi i casi, però, protezionismo significa il diritto di vendere certi beni in certi mercati in regime di monopolio.

I brevetti sui farmaci uccidono milioni di persone, e se i porci dell’Accordo Trans-Pacifico riusciranno nel loro intento, molti altri milioni saranno uccisi. Il recinto in cui è stata rinchiusa la conoscenza, con il suo sistema di pedaggi all’ingresso, impedisce la condivisione del sapere e la possibilità di ampliare la conoscenza. Tutto ciò distrugge l’ethos da pari a pari che è alla base della scienza, e che è simboleggiato dall’espressione “stare sulle spalle di un gigante”.

È necessario continuare la battaglia di Aaron Swartz a favore della libertà d’informazione. Bisognerebbe piratare gli articoli delle riviste accademiche per pubblicarli liberamente sui siti di condivisione. Dovremmo cogliere l’opportunità offerta dalla stampa tridimensionale di medicinali e dalla farmacologia open-source per produrre versioni piratate, a basso costo, di farmaci brevettati, il tutto agendo tramite piccole organizzazioni che siano così diffuse che le compagnie e lo stato non possano fare nulla per fermarle.

La “proprietà intellettuale”, assieme agli stati che la impongono, è nemica della conoscenza, del progresso e della stessa vita. La cosa migliore è far fuori entrambi.

Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.

Portuguese, Stateless Embassies
O estado regulatório caseiro em destaque

De acordo com sua versão mais conhecida, o “pluralismo de grupos de interesse” mencionado no livro Capitalismo americano de John Kenneth Galbraith, existe, em tese, um sistema de pesos e contrapesos (Galbraith os chamava de “pesos compensatórios”) entre as grandes empresas, as agências regulatórias do governo e os trabalhadores organizados. Porém, o que acontece no mundo real normalmente, quando há tão poucos centros de poder “opostos”, é que eles se unem em vez de limitar os poderes uns dos outros. Os grandes sindicatos que conhecemos (as uniões sob tutela estatal) são principalmente aliados das classes gerenciais cujo papel é forçar os trabalhadores subordinados a aceitarem seus contratos e evitar greves espontâneas e outras formas de ação direta. O relacionamento entre o governo e as empresas é notoriamente cooperativo, em que os dois formam “complexos” como o militar-industrial ou se unem em capturas regulatórias (o que ocorre, por exemplo, no caso do Departamento de Agricultura dos Estados Unidos, que emprega normalmente ex-executivos de grandes corporações do agronegócio). Contudo, como uma notícia da NBC mostra (Javier E. David, “Cyberbullying’s Got a New Target: Big Business“, NBCNews, 28 de março), há uma agência regulatória que os grandes negócios não podem capturar: nós!

Dado que o sistema econômico e político esteja organizado em torno de alguns poucos centros de poder concentrados, não é possível evitar essa tendência de formação de alianças. Mas há uma maneira de fazer com que o “estado regulatório” não seja capturável: tornando-o coextensivo às nossas ações, sem lideranças ou gerentes que afirmem agir em nosso nome. É exatamente isso que formas de organização horizontais em rede, possibilitadas pela internet, têm feito.

Anos atrás, Tom Coates observou que a combinação de comunicação em rede e plataformas caseiras livres e abertas permitiam que as pessoas executassem trabalhos informacionais (programação, publicação, gravação de vídeos e áudio, etc.) de qualidade superior ao que faziam em escritórios, com todas as suas reuniões, interrupções e programas proprietários que eram forçados a utilizar. John Robb criou a expressão “indivíduo superempoderado” para descrever a maneira pela qual essa comunicação e essas plataformas amplamente disponíveis agiam como multiplicadores de força e permitiam que indivíduos e pequenas células desafiassem instituições enormes e burocráticas (por exemplo, a al-Qaeda contra os Estados Unidos) em guerras assimétricas. O mesmo fenômeno é ilustrado pelo que os “piratas” que compartilham arquivos fizeram com as indústrias do cinema e da música, pelo que Chelsea Manning e Edward Snowden fizeram com o estado de segurança americano, e pela forma como a Primavera Árabe e o Syntagma derrubaram governos inteiros.

No caso da limitação dos poderes corporativos, os princípios básicos já existem há muito tempo. Os wobblies, trabalhadores associados ao sindicato radical Industrial Workers of the World, criaram a expressão “sabotar abrindo a boca” para quando empregados insatisfeitos vazam documentos e informam o público sobre todas as falcatruas de dentro das companhias que os empregadores prefeririam manter em segredo.

Com a ascensão da internet, das mídias sociais e de veículos de apoio como o Wikileaks e outros sites de vazamento de informações, o potencial para esse tipo de sabotagem cresceu em várias ordens de magnitude. Vimos os primeiros esboços dessa nova abordagem no julgamento de McLibel e nas campanhas de “culture jamming” (de subversão das mensagens corporativas) de Frank Kernaghan contra as más condições de trabalho em fábricas nos anos 1990. Ao mesmo tempo, as táticas tradicionais do trabalho de campanhas comunitárias e corporativas em conjunção com boicotes e decisões dissidentes de acionistas ganharam muito em poder — como evidenciado por campanhas como a da Coalizão dos Trabalhadores de Immolakee de informação e boicote a várias cadeias de fast food. Quando todas essas facetas do ativismo em rede se unem contra uma corporação gigante, é como um cardume de piranhas que engole um tiranossauro.

Neste último surto de atenção midiática ao fenômeno, Javier David examina as experiências infelizes em relações públicas das corporações neste admirável mundo novo de ativismo social de mídia e os péssimos acontecimentos de quando campanhas felizes e sorridentes encontram pessoas no Twitter e no Facebook que não vão cooperar com elas. Seus exemplos são duas campanhas recentes de relações públicas — a hashtag do Starbucks #RaceTogether (que pretendia fazer com que os trabalhadores e consumidores “conversassem” a respeito de questões raciais) e uma capa sexista da revista em quadrinhos Batgirl — que se tornaram desastres humilhantes nas mídias sociais. Em ambos os casos, as campanhas foram suspensas após uma violenta reação.

David também menciona uma campanha de 2013 no Twitter contra a empresa Sallie Mae por perseguir os pais de um estudante morto para que pagassem seu empréstimo estudantil, o que fez com que a empresa tivesse que se recolher com o rabo entre as pernas por conta do ultraje público.

Embora David não mencione, a nova arquitetura democrática da mídia também se faz sentir na política internacional. Se os levantes do EZLN em Chiapas ou o uso de esquadrões mercenários na Nigéria tivesse ocorrido antes dos anos 1990, as notícias nunca teriam passado da página 7 do New York Times. No entanto, graças a ativistas do mundo todo presentes na internet, a Shell teve que responder à repercussão pública e os zapatistas, que uma década antes teriam sido suprimidos permanentemente em poucos dias, têm mantido o autogoverno em Chiapas há vinte anos.

Todos concordam que a causa dessas mudanças na estrutura comunicativa é a mudança da estrutura anterior, que era baseada num canal unidirecional em que alguns poucos gatekeepers controlam o que vemos, para uma arquitetura “de muitos para muitos” em que todos podem falar uns com os outros — e responder — livremente. Se isso é bom, os opinadores oficiais ainda estão divididos.

O próprio David envolve a questão no esquema “por um lado, mas por outro” de forma estranha. A internet é “vista por muitos como uma forma de limitar o poder das empresas e dar aos consumidores alguma alavancagem”. Aparentemente, esse é o lado Dr. Jekyll da equação. “Contudo, ela também [ênfase minha] significa que as empresas não mais controlam suas próprias narrativas e podem rapidamente se tornar incapazes de interferir em suas histórias”. Veja bem, essas duas afirmações parecem ser apenas formas diferentes de dizer a mesma coisa. Os consumidores são capazes de limitar o poder das corporações porque estas não mais controlam a mensagem. Ninguém além das corporações deve ter qualquer problema com isso e é seguro dizer que qualquer coisa que deixe os gerentes corporativos insatisfeitos é um bom motivo para as outras pessoas comemorarem. Então, o uso do “contudo” no texto de David parece ser o mesmo que escrever um texto sobre antibióticos que dá igual espaço à opinião das bactérias pneumococos.

David cita a professora do MIT Renée Richardson Gosline: “Antigamente, na época dos ‘Mad Men’, as empresas tinham completo controle sobre as mensagens e sobre aquilo que os consumidores podiam ver”. Agora, por outro lado, “o consumidor também tem uma voz”.

Jules Polonetsky do Future of Privacy Forum vê esse fenômeno por uma perspectiva mais negativa. “As visões de um certo nicho estão sendo extrapoladas (…) e moldam o que parece ser a opinião pública. As mídias sociais estão começando a ditar a primeira camada da opinião pública. Elas podem provocar reações mais extremas do que aquilo que de fato representa o público.”

Vamos rebobinar rapidamente e colocar a reclamação de Polonetsky em perspectiva. Desde a ascensão do nexo corporativo-estatal americano no final do século 19 até, talvez, 20 anos atrás, nós vivíamos mergulhados em uma “opinião pública mainstream” criada quase inteiramente pelas elites gerenciais-centristas das grandes empresas, agências regulatórias, grandes universidades, grandes fundações sem fins lucrativos e dos veículos de mídia corporativos. Não apenas a estrutura do estado corporativo foi erguida por esses interesses institucionais interconectados, sem levar em conta as opiniões reais do público, mas essas oligarquias burocráticas levaram o país a uma guerra atrás da outra sob falsos pretextos como se fossem fatos consumados. Em todas as instâncias, o sistema dependia de um canal unidirecional de informações para “fabricar o consentimento” (nas palavras de Edward Bernays, que ajudou Woodrow Wilson a legitimar a entrada dos Estados Unidos na Primeira guerra Mundial e que acabou mais tarde por criar toda a indústria de relações públicas). E, em todas as instâncias, uma vez que a única ideia de “opinião pública” que o público possuía era o produto final excretado pelo braço midiático dessas elites corporativas-estatais, a “opinião pública” sempre foi moldada pelo establishment como algumas poucas alternativas que modificassem muito pouco a estrutura do sistema e que fossem executadas por aqueles que já detinham o poder. Qualquer alternativa política fora desse espectro centrista que alterasse fundamentalmente a estrutura do sistema a ponto de reduzir seriamente o poder das elites corporativas-estatais era descartada como “extremista” e fora do “consenso mainstream” da opinião pública. E o público não tinha qualquer forma de conhecer essas alternativas, porque, além de discutir com seus círculos de amigos imediatos, não havia qualquer maneira de saber qual era a “opinião pública”, que, para todos os efeitos, era aquilo que o sistema centralizado de informações dizia ser.

Não há qualquer preocupação por parte de Polonetsky de que o velho e fabricado “consenso centrista”, montado para legitimar o domínio contínuo pelas elites corporativas-estatais, possa ter representado algo menos autêntico que a “opinião pública”. Porém, agora que um século e meio de fabricação de “opinião pública” — que é impossível saber se de fato refletia a opinião pública — chega ao fim e nós de fato podemos conversar uns com os outros sem o intermédio das grandes redes de TV e da Associated Press, ele está repentinamente preocupado que os extremistas estejam criando uma impressão errônea do que caracteriza a opinião pública.

Não. Durante toda a história humana, a chamada “opinião pública” foi moldada por “extremistas” — a elite de gerentes da opinião que C. Wright Mills chamava de “crackpot realists” (“realistas excêntricos”) e que irônicos comentaristas de mídia chamam de “pessoas sérias”. Todas as sociedades ao longo da história, desde a ascensão dos primeiros estados e dos primeiros sistemas de exploração de classe, possuíam um aparato de reprodução cultural cujo objetivo era garantir que cada geração estivesse inserida numa visão de mundo que enxergasse o sistema de poder sob o qual viviam como natural e inevitável, o único modo viável de se fazer as coisas, e que qualquer alternativa que envolvesse perdas significativas de poder pelas elites só poderia ser “extremista”.

Por muito tempo vivemos sob um sistema de informações desenhado para evitar a comunicação horizontal entre as pessoas, para que nossas comunicações pudessem apenas ser mediadas pelas elites de gatekeepers que cuidassem das arquiteturas de informação. Nossa única impressão do que caracteriza a opinião pública é agregada por essas estruturas. Agora, porém, como afirmou James Scott em A dominação e a arte da resistência, as pessoas comuns são capazes de se comunicar diretamente umas com as outras e reconhecer que suas reivindicações, seus sonhos e suas angústias são compartilhadas por outros subordinados com os quais não estão em contato direto.

Pela primeira vez, podemos driblar o consenso fabricado, conversar uns com os outros e reagir àqueles que controlam o sistema. Quando conversamos uns com os outros, dizemos — e fazemos — coisas que eles não aprovam. Onde quer que vão, o que quer que façam, nós os vigiaremos e agiremos.

Repetindo algo que eu já disse várias vezes, o século 20 foi a era das organizações gigantes. No final do 21, não faltará enterrar nenhuma delas.

Traduzido por Erick Vasconcelos.

Stigmergy - C4SS Blog, Weekly Libertarian Leftist Review
The Weekly Libertarian Leftist Review 78

Stephen Kinzer discusses how safe the U.S. is.

Nick Turse discusses the battlefield of tomorrow.

Laurence M. Vance discusses how the state needs servants to do its dirty work.

Ivan Eland discusses how Obama’s nuclear agreement is a good one but issues remain.

Justin Raimondo discusses why we can’t limit government without limiting foreign intervention.

Rami G. Khouri discusses respect as the death knell of colonialism.

Lucy Steigerwald discusses changing why wars happen.

Sheldon Richman discuses U.S. and Saudi intervention in Yemen.

Sharon Presley discusses the existence of rape culture in America.

Anthony F. Shaker discusses the history of Saudi funded fundamentalism and sectarian war on the Shia.

Jacob G. Hornberger discusses draft registration and America’s serf society.

Charles Pierson discusses the lack of accountability for U.S. drone kills.

Sheldon Richman discusses empathy and patience in presenting libertarianism.

Brian Cloughley discusses US-NATO antics in the nuclear playground.

Matt Welch discusses Marco Rubio’s 7 lousy foreign policy judgments.

Kelley Vlahos discusses our bad friends; the Saudis.

Steven Horowitz discusses whether the ninth amendment can save us.

Uri Avnery discusses Avnery vs the State of Israel.

Lawrence Davidson discusses Islamophobia on wheels.

Ron Jacobs discusses outlaws in the eyes of Amerika.

Ramzy Baroud discusses naming and shaming in Yarmouk.

Tariq Ali discusses the new world disorder.

Michael Uhl discusses the Vietnam Veterans Memorial wall.

Robert Fantina discusses Hilary as a disaster in the making.

Matt Welch discusses why debating with words rather than government force is better.

Nick Gillespie discusses why libertarians are like Kale to everyone but Paul Krugman.

Damon Root discusses the smearing of Herbert Spencer and past progressive support for eugenics.

Baylen Linnekin discusses cracking down on feeding the homeless.

Jesse Walker discusses Mike Huckabee’s run for president.

Justin Logan discusses the real reason hawks oppose the Iranian deal.

Feature Articles
Anarchy is a Scale-Independent Proposition

There’s a particular narrative–surprisingly common in certain corners of the anarchist scene–that no one has really bothered to call out and so has grown rather fat and comfortable over the last few decades. It goes something like this:

Thinking or acting from a big-picture perspective is–if not The Problem–then at least a major root cause of everything miserable about our world. Any claims, theories, ideals, or motivations that extend our frame of reference beyond our immediate lives are predicated in the same mistaken arrogance, a mistake responsible for the seemingly intractable poison within the left and activist struggles, as well as so much more. In response we must ward ourselves from the ideologies, the grand constructs, the stories that dwarf the particulars of our immediate perceptions, our social circles, our daily struggles. Most of all we must reject the search for universals and focus only on the “human sized”.

Often this narrative quickly segues to pattern-matching this “big-thinking” tendency in terms of some unified Judeo-Christian tradition (under the assumption that there’s only a tiny chance of running across anyone with a strong claim to be part of a different tradition). At this point the narrative really picks up steam: There was once polytheism/animism/spiritualism but then all the little gods and little tribes got ground up by the big universal monster and now there’s just universal stuff, and we should just break things apart again until they’re back on a “human scale”–ala Dunbar’s Number–where we can better keep track of everything. And, supposedly, therefor stop our thought from growing “out of control.”

All you should be concerned about are your immediate relationships with other people in your social/drama circles, how you relate to them and the kind of psychological states you’re able to briefly create together.

For a lot of people this perspective somehow resonates very deeply as a kind of clean break. There’s this big boogeyman representation of supposedly all existing paradigms, and then there’s them, breaking away, abruptly free to explore an array of new possibilities. You get this with a lot of cults too, once you just see The Problemeverything is so clear and filled with newness and possibility. Our brains love the feeling of a new perspective or a new context, especially when we’re dealing with continually grinding problems. We get to let go of all our frustrating calculations and considerations constantly hanging around, persisting in the back of our minds, and start anew! People get so overwhelmed by that rush that they refuse to pay attention when this new One Simple Trick fails to actually address anything, when the exact same sort of problems creep back, and the limits of the new paradigm start to feel like a prison walls again. And so you see people, enraptured by the feeling of the original break, with the impression of it, refusing to feel out for these walls, repeating the same kind of sad content-devoid mantras in response to any input. “If you’d only see that it’s all Moralism maann.

Granted, this can be an important step in flexing your brain, I guess, if you come from a certain background, with certain priorities. But I don’t. This shit and the context it comes out of are just so incredibly alien to me. And so the magical salve of returning to the small-scale is just a wad of spit and leaves to me. It doesn’t begin to address the things that worry me.

Like a lot of people I didn’t originally become an anarchist over concerns about black helicopters or mushroom clouds or any showy large-scale horror. I first became an anarchist because at a very young age I saw people–individual people–exercising control over other people. I saw dynamics of abuse, coercion and manipulation and I recoiled from them. I thought about the way these dynamics worked and then I critiqued and rejected them. Simple as that. Crucially these behaviors were often completely divorced from epic narratives, big ideologies or global forces. They were, in fact, often intensely localized, personal, and situational. Sometimes they gave rise to grand ambitions and sweeping frameworks. But they arose separately, and indeed, were often joined closely with an anti-narrative and anti-globalist bent. “This situation is unique and can’t or shouldn’t be compared with any other, much less any commonality identified.” “Ethics is a delusion for weak people.” “There are no constants so why not give into whatever impulses strike me.” Indeed the most powerful tools in perpetuating these power dynamics were those that denied universals or constants and those that exploited limited knowledge, information or communication. Gaslighting. Triangulation. Isolation.

You actually believed me?!” and then cackling laughter.

Such sociopathy is not a fringe dynamic, but a near constant tendency that is deeply deeply riven in just about every society or culture on this planet. It survives in no small part by keeping its ever present machinations hidden or at least unspoken. It perpetuates itself through narratives that reduce the world to an unmappable formless mess, devoid of constants or directions. It portrays the world and our experiences as a substanceless game of immediate impulses and chance particulars. Everything is arbitrary, so why not? An impulse towards friends and family after all is just a historically contingent trapping that one could easily emerge without or shed off. Love and compassion just a fleeting affliction of sentiment, with no deep reason to prompt valuing its perpetuation. I may bask in parental love for you today and tomorrow delight myself by your screams as I break your fingers. There are no constants, no universal attractors, no way to argue or persuade that isn’t just manipulation, positioning, delusion. Being kind or resisting power might happen to give you some sense of pleasure or happiness but any sufficiently intelligent person can change their brain. Why not take the easier route and just just find ways to hack how you get pleasure? To distract yourself from recognizing oppression and suffering, or to take delight in them?

Cinematic buckets of blood dumped on Carrie or the hordes beating Piggy are not a departure from the norm but are implicit in everything we do. Our society’s illusion of normalcy is a detente riven with the fluctuations of our continuing and almost-all-present manipulations, cruelties, and selfish acts. These small violences form a constant fabric whose wrinkles form the scaffolding of larger emergent structures until we arrive at governments, religions and corporations.

Leftists declare such interpersonal power dynamics–insofar as they are ever forced to recognize them–only the consequence of macroscopic patterns like Capitalism. What a laugh! The small is ultimately not so much the result of the big as the other way around. Feudalism, state communism, city states, federated tribes… no matter how you push the wrinkles in the fabric around the psychology of abuse, control and deception that ties it together remains unaddressed. Hunter gatherers like any other iteration of humanity often did horrible things to one another, held each other in abusive bondage, faith and ritual. The bonds that oppress us are no less bonds if they are small-scale and responsive. The might of emperors has oft been but a puff of air compared to aggregate coercive power and suffering caused by every abusive partner or parent or friend in the world. It does not take the existence of sweeping patriarchal norms and socializations for partners to abuse each other, for parents to be cruel or domineering to children, these behaviors emerge in almost every culture or circle. The rates of abuse and physical violence among lesbians are the same as among heteros. This is not some magically adaptable macroscopic force or conspiracy that absorbs every punch we through at it and reorganizes itself, it is not some huge spectre out there beyond our immediate lives, it is a persistent tendency, a creeping low-level infection riven throughout our immediate lives, our collective and one-on-one relations.

And everywhere it smirks to itself. Every Pope has been an atheist. Every successful president or czar a passionate egoist. They wrap their thoughts in robes, just as most of us wrap our thoughts in what we term ‘useful‘ delusions in our most clearheaded moments. Temporary allegiances and affectations. Sure the power that binds others often binds the wielder. But not always. And certainly not always in a meaningful one-to-one relation against the subjective desires of the wielder.

This kind of person, this kind of thinking, has no need for universal or big-perspective thinking; they will scramble for power in any context. The problem they represent is irrespective of the scale of pageantry. These sociopathic currents run deep in almost every cluster of individuals and often crawl into our own heads.

The damage we do each other at the small-scale, at the “human level”, is usually far more profound in suffering than the damage done by big tangled contexts and social organisms above and beyond our families, lovers, and friends. They intersect, they feedback off each other in interesting ways, and with bigger scale comes bigger risk, to be sure, but at the end of the day the narrative of small-scale against big-scale is utterly toothless against the roots of the horrors we face.

I and many others were originally attracted to anarchism not because we were looking to satiate some hunger for the participatory delusion / commodity known as “community”, but as a ray of absolute resistance against the fundamentally sociopathic and nihilistic social norms of our world. Against an omnipresent foul fog that burns our lungs and seeks to settle deep into our skin.

For us Anarchism has always first, foremost, and at root, presented itself as a sharp critique of this rampantly common and pedestrian perspective, this staunch belief in immediatism and the irrelevance or nonexistence of universals or solids of any form of truly persuasive arguments that might be found–this assumption of the uniform arbitrariness and futility of vigilant investigation beyond one’s momentary or happenstance motivations–that infests every abuser, every conman, every social capitalist, every creep, every rapist.

Our anarchism represents a break with this, it is the cry that an-archy is possible, even considerable, that we need not reassign the term like so much litter to denote merely diffuse, local and personal archies. That we need not embrace the orwellian framework in which anarchy is the same shit, only more locally responsive. It is the declaration that there is a substantive differentiation to be found between the ideologies or psychologies of constraint and those of richer, wider engagement, of more expansive identity and compassion. And that the latter is ultimately more attractive than the former. That we need not shy away from reality or lower our gaze in furtive dejection to our immediate trappings, to mere fleeting impressions of love and resistance, to aesthetics rather than anything of consequence.

Such an anarchism is an unraveling of the very fabric of power relations that bind almost every society on earth. And critically: there is no scale at which it does not apply.

That big showy tangles of power must also be dissolved is but a trivial ramification, it is no more representative of the anarchist break than any other shift or twist in the fabric of power relations. Nor can our break be characterized by a brief or local loosening of the weave. The break anarchism signifies is not with the particularities of the west, or of civilization, it goes far far deeper than that.

Why do we throw ourselves on bombs or strap bombs on ourselves to save others? These are not superficial feelings, they are not socialized happenstance or quirk of birth. These are conclusions those who are radical in their investigations, their vigilant explorations, find themselves drawn to. As radicals we never allow ourselves to be satisfied with hazy mystical simplified abstractions and spooks like “friendship” rather than concrete realities and dynamics of thought and action. Or wander in circles, adding contextual complications but not even attempting to weigh, reorganize or sort through them. Relishing the self-created maze of notes upon notes and so never attempting to isolate the deeper patterns or consistencies.

The narrative of opposition to “big-thinking” is at its core just a kind of smug pride in timidity, of ritualized fear and comfortable despair. “We have not won in a few scant iterations of history and this is proof that we will lose.” “Some people tried thinking and look at where that inevitably led.” It’s the instinctive recoil of the traumatized animal. A sense that “when the stakes go up we dare not rise to compete.” And at its core it swallows and preserves every nihilistic assumption at the core of our sociopathic society. One might be able to relate to the mewling slave repeating “might makes right” like a prayer of absolution, having internalized the masters’ intellectual laziness, but one should never join them.

Let us never forget that coffins are made “human sized”; our lives should be bigger than them.

Italian, Stateless Embassies
È Ora di Mettere Fine all’Orribile Embargo Contro Cuba

Il dodici aprile, al Vertice delle Americhe, il presidente americano Barack Obama ha parlato in pubblico con il presidente cubano Raul Castro a proposito della fine delle tensioni tra i due paesi. Era la prima volta che Cuba partecipava al vertice, e si spera che questo segni l’inizio di una maggiore libertà di movimento di merci e uomini tra i due paesi. In precedenza, Obama aveva definito “datato”l’embargo americano contro Cuba e aveva espresso interesse per la normalizzazione delle relazioni.

Questo cambiamento dovrebbe essere il benvenuto. L’embargo, iniziato nel 1960, ha mancato miseramente l’obiettivo dichiarato di mettere fine al regime di Castro, che di fatto è ancora al potere. Gli embargo tendono a punire la popolazione per le azioni commesse dai loro governanti, indebolendo contemporaneamente l’opposizione. E non parlo degli americani che hanno perso la possibilità di fare affari con i cubani. L’americana Commissione per il Commercio Internazionale una volta ha stimato che l’embargo è costato alle imprese americana qualcosa come 1,2 miliardi di dollari l’anno in mancate vendite e esportazioni, una cifra che da allora è probabilmente cresciuta. Il governo cubano, dal suo canto, dice che il costo per la sua popolazione è di 685 milioni l’anno. Questi costi contribuiscono all’opposizione di moltissimi americani all’embargo.

L’embargo, unito alle sanzioni imposte alle compagnie internazionali che commerciano con Cuba, limita l’accesso di molti cubani agli alimenti, all’acqua potabile e alle medicine. È stato dimostrato che queste carenze sono alla base di molte malattie infettive e della cecità da malnutrizione. Le persone più colpite dall’embargo sono i cubani più poveri. L’embargo non ha fatto altro che accentuare la loro povertà.

Imporre queste punizioni sui poveri cubani è del tutto immorale, anche se non si tiene conto delle perdite subite dalle aziende americane, i consumatori e i contribuenti. Pieno appoggio alla libertà di viaggiare e scambiare beni, dunque, ma non bisogna confondere ciò per consenso agli accordi tra i due paesi. Gli Stati Uniti hanno la tendenza a negoziare accordi commerciali che favoriscono ingiustamente le grandi aziende americane a spese della concorrenza più piccola e spesso locale. Questo è vero soprattutto nel caso di accordi che proteggono i brevetti e i copyright americani, che non sono altro che monopoli protetti dallo stato che limitano la libertà di scambio delle persone. Per avere un vero libero mercato, e non un mercato fortemente regolato, basterebbe che lo stato togliesse gli ostacoli. Questo vale per tutti i paesi. Una politica di libero commercio unilaterale sarebbe un beneficio enorme per la gente ordinaria.

La guerra fredda è finita da decenni, e con essa è morta la ragione alla base dell’embargo. L’Unione Sovietica è scomparsa portandosi appresso il comunismo globale. Americani e cubani dovrebbero essere liberi di interagire pacificamente come desiderano. Il fatto tragico è che questo è solo uno dei tanti casi in cui lo stato si mette di mezzo tra persone che vogliono avere rapporti benefici tra loro. Per il momento, mettere fine a questo orribile embargo, così come alle sanzioni imposte alle aziende che commerciano con Cuba, è un buon punto da cui iniziare.

Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.

Studies
The Fulcrum of the Present Crisis

The Fulcrum of the Present Crisis: Some Thoughts on Revolutionary Strategy

Center for a Stateless Society Paper No. 19 (Winter 2015) [PDF]

The Cult of Mass, Lionization of Protest Culture & Other Industrial Age Holdovers

Protest Culture. The so-called “cargo cults” of New Guinea, Micronesia and Melanesia evolved in response to the influx of American manufactured goods during World War II. Native islanders identified the goods – at least in the received version of the story – not with any material process of production in the countries it came from, but with the proliferation of air bases and air fields in their own countries. The cargo cults, accordingly, operated on the principle of sympathetic magic to stimulate the further delivery of Western manufactured goods by building airplanes and air control centers out of woven bamboo.

Richard Feynman later applied this phenomenon, by analogy, to what he called “cargo cult science.” Cargo cult science equates “science” to incidental features of science like test tubes and lab coats, with no understanding of what constitutes real science: the experimental method.

More generally, a “cargo cult” in any field of human endeavor is an attempt to generate a social phenomenon by replicating all the incidents and stage props commonly identified with it in the public mind.

There’s a danger, in a period of upheavals like the Arab Spring, Occupy, M15, Syntagma, and subsequent networked movements, of our being led astray by a revolutionary cargo cult. The danger is that we will identify “revolution” with incidental things like demonstrations, barricades, slogans and posters.

But none of these things, individually or taken together – no matter how important each may be – is revolution as such. We can have all these things and still, if we lack a proper understanding of the true nature of the crisis of this system, in effect be attempting to create a new society by weaving a revolution from strips of bamboo.

Mass and Scale. Many on the establishment Left – not to mention centrist liberals – have criticized horizontalist movements like Occupy for lacking conventional signifiers of legitimacy like leaders and official demands. And on a more fundamental level, the very model of networked organization itself came under attack.

Decentralized networks are useless, Evgeny Morozov says, because they lack the mass and scale for taking over existing institutions.

Without well-organized, centralized, and hierarchical structures to push back against entrenched interests, attempts to make politics more participatory might stall, and further disempower the weak, and coopt members of the opposition into weak and toothless political settings. This was the case before the Internet, and, most likely, it will be the case long after.

And Malcolm Gladwell considers them pernicious not only because of the lack of mass and centralized coordination but because, unlike activist movements like the legacy Civil Rights movement, they involve only “weak ties.” Weak ties “seldom lead to high-risk activism”: “Social networks are effective at increasing participation – by lessening the level of motivation that participation requires.”

The civil-rights movement was high-risk activism. It was also, crucially, strategic activism: a challenge to the establishment mounted with precision and discipline. The N.A.A.C.P. was a centralized organization, run from New York according to highly formalized operating procedures. At the Southern Christian Leadership Conference, Martin Luther King, Jr., was the unquestioned authority….

This is the second crucial distinction between traditional activism and its online variant: social media are not about this kind of hierarchical organization. Facebook and the like are tools for building networks, which are the opposite, in structure and character, of hierarchies. Unlike hierarchies, with their rules and procedures, networks aren’t controlled by a single central authority. Decisions are made through consensus, and the ties that bind people to the group are loose.

A certain kind of verticalist is as fond of pulling out Jo Freeman’s “The Tyranny of Structurelessness,” as a certain kind of right-libertarian is of pulling out Hardin’s “Tragedy of the Commons.” Although Freeman’s essay is commonly drawn on today as a critique of consensus process, David Graeber argues that consensus process was in fact developed in response to the problems she described (i.e. informal cliques emerging, controlling information and setting agendas, as feminist groups grew to over twenty people or so).

…almost everyone who is not emerging from an explicitly anti-authoritarian position… completely misread Freeman’s essay, and interpret it not as a plea for formal mechanisms to ensure equality, but as a plea for more transparent hierarchy. Leninists are notorious for this sort of thing, but Liberals are just as bad…. First, Freeman’s argument about the formation of cliques and invisible power structures is taken as an argument that any group of over twenty people will always have to have cliques, power structures, and people in authority. The next step is to insist that if you want to minimize the power of such cliques, or any deleterious effects those power structures might have, the only way to do so is to institutionalize them: to take the de facto cabal and turn them into a central committee…. One needs to get power out of the shadows—to formalize the process, make up rules, hold elections, specify exactly what the cabal is allowed to do and what it is not. In this way, at least, power will be made transparent and “accountable.”….

From a practical, activist perspective, this prescription is obviously ridiculous. It is far easier to limit the degree to which informal cliques can wield effective power by granting them no formal status at all, and therefore no legitimacy; whatever “formal accountability structures” it is imagined will contain the cliques-now-turned-committees can only be far less effective in this regard, not least because they end up legitimating and hence massively increasing the differential access to information which allows some in otherwise egalitarian groups to have greater power to begin with…. [S]tructures of transparently inevitably… begin to become structures of stupidity as soon as that takes place.

An Alternative Approach … [Read the rest of Carson’s Study via PDF]

Center for a Stateless Society Paper No. 19 (Winter 2015) [PDF]

Books and Reviews
Nothing to Fear from New Technologies if the Market is Free

The Second Machine Age: Work, Progress and Prosperity in a Time of Brilliant Technologies by Erik Brynjolfsson and Andrew McAfee (W.W. Norton & Company 2014), 320 pages.

The subject of this book is the “second machine age,” in which “computers and other digital advances are doing for mental power — the ability to use our brains to understand and shape our environments — what the steam engine and its descendants did for muscle power.” The key technological building blocks for this second machine age are already in place, even if they aren’t yet completely mature.

Although these technologies are the culmination of several decades of gradual development, they have only recently reached the threshold of a fundamental phase transition in the way the economy operates. The first part of the book is a walk-through survey of the various technologies involved in the second machine age and the reasons we’re just now approaching a phase transition.

Second-machine-age technologies are exponential. But as Ray Kurzweil has pointed out, the early states of exponential growth are deceptively modest. He uses the example of the inventor who, offered a reward by an emperor, asked that one grain of rice be placed on the first square of a chessboard, two on the second, four on the third, and continuing to double the number through all sixty-four squares. While the numbers get large in the first 32 squares, they’re still the kinds of numbers we encounter in the real world. By the inventor’s arrangement, there would be about four billion grains of rice on the 32nd square — “about one large field’s worth.” It’s on the second half of the chessboard that things get weird, with the final amount of rice equaling the total agricultural output of many earths.

Thanks to Moore’s Law, machine-age technologies have been moving from square to square every couple of years since World War II. And we’re just now getting onto the second half of the chessboard, where things really take off and the elbow of the curve bends into a straight vertical line.

The new technologies are also combinatorial. Incremental improvement in the capabilities of existing technologies can bring them to the threshold of an exponential increase in their possible number of combinations. For example, Google’s Chauffeur project has produced results several orders of magnitude better than previous attempts at autopiloted cars a few years back, despite the fact that the same building-block technologies existed back then. Incremental improvements in those technologies, interacting synergistically with each other, enabled an exponential increase in performance. And continuing incremental improvement in building-block technologies increases the stock of off-the-shelf technologies available for developers to recombine at will to fit particular needs.

We’re rapidly approaching a range of cheap, modular, general-purpose, off-the-shelf building-block technologies sufficient to enable a near-infinite number of custom mash-ups for any conceivable purpose.

Reading Cory Doctorow’s novel Makers, a near-future story about open-source hardware hackers and micromanufacturing, Bruce Sterling commented that there was “hardly any engineering. Almost all of this is mash-up tinkering.” It’s just the recombination of modular components. But that’s just the point, Doctorow responded. “It’s not that every invention has been invented, but we sure have a lot of basic parts just hanging around, waiting to be configured.” The result is that “we now inhabit a world where knowing something is possible is practically the same as knowing how to do it.” (Doctorow, “Cheap Facts and the Plausible Premise,” Locus, July 5, 2009.)

Murray Bookchin’s essay “Toward a Liberatory Technology,” written in the 1970s, quoted something Vannevar Bush had said back in 1955:

Suppose, fifty years ago, that someone had proposed a device which would cause an automobile to follow a white line down the middle of the road, automatically and even if the driver fell asleep…. [His] idea would have been called preposterous…. But suppose someone called for such a device today, and was willing to pay for it, leaving aside the question of whether it would actually be of any genuine use whatever. Any number of concerns would stand ready to contract and build it. No real invention would be required. There are thousands of young men in the country to whom the design of such a device would be a pleasure. They would simply take off the shelf some photocells, thermionic tubes, servomechanisms, relays, and, if urged, they would build what they call a breadboard model, and it would work. The point is that the presence of a host of versatile, reliable, cheap gadgets, and the presence of men who understand all their cheap ways, has rendered the building of automatic devices almost straightforward and routine. It is no longer a question of whether they can be built, it is a question of whether they are worth building.

There was no little exaggeration in what Bush wrote almost 60 years ago. But today it is true almost beyond his (and Bookchin’s) wildest imaginings.

And with all the rest of this, throw in the fact that we’re rapidly approaching — if we haven’t already reached — artificial intelligence capable of running all these mash-up machineries with sufficient flexibility and discretion to replace human operators. The result will be the automation of human labor and the elimination of existing job categories to an unprecedented degree, very likely extending to the majority of work-hours and creating an enormous mass of unemployed or underemployed people.

Uneven benefits

That brings us to the next point. Despite the overall benefits of the new technologies, their benefits tend to be distributed unevenly, leading to what the authors call a “spread” in “wealth, income, mobility, and other important measures” between those at the top and bottom. And they warn that the spread in benefits from new technology — which they view as the natural outcome of increased productivity — will accelerate as the second machine age goes on, “unless we intervene.” It generally happens that “a relatively small group of people … earns most of the income from … new products or services.”

Of course the new information technologies, with almost zero-marginal cost, are also destroying GDP by radically deflating prices (just look at the 40-percent drop in revenue from music sales between 2004 and 2008 alone, or the 100-percent price drop for people who now choose Wikipedia over Britannica). But how are people to buy goods and services, even drastically cheapened ones, if they don’t have any income from jobs at all?

Part of the answer is that, under the existing model of corporate-state capitalism, the goods and services are still not cheap enough. They’re not allowed to be. The main reason so many benefits of new technology are monopolized by those at the top is that the state enforces, well, monopolies. Economic ruling classes are able to enclose the increased efficiencies from new technology as a source of rents mainly through artificial scarcities, artificial property rights, and entry barriers enforced by the state.

And perhaps the most important of these artificial property rights is so-called intellectual property, which the authors take for granted.

In reality, the natural course of affairs absent such state-enforced monopolies is not for a small group to monopolize most of the income, but for market competition to socialize all of the productivity gains in the form of lowered prices.

One of the most interesting things about the new technologies of this generation — the technologies of both ephemeral, small-scale physical production and more- powerful information processing — is that their basic logic undermines the scarcity logic by which ruling classes of the past have extracted rents from society. They render large concentrations of land and capital increasingly irrelevant, and put the potential for ownership and control of the means of production in the hands of ordinary people.

There’s one big difference between the effect of the steam engine in the first Industrial Revolution and the effect of cybernetic technology today. All the labor-displacing and impoverishing effects of steam power resulted from the facts that (1) steam engines and the kinds of machinery that ran off them were enormously expensive, and beyond the resources of individual workers or small groups of workers to acquire; (2) the resources for purchasing such machinery had been concentrated by a long historical process of enclosure and other state-enforced expropriations of land from the peasantry to a relatively small propertied class; and (3) the transaction costs of aggregating the small individual savings of ordinary working people into capital to finance cooperative production were enormous — even when they weren’t preempted or foreclosed by prohibitive state restrictions on freedom of association.

In contrast, new technology today is not only radically cheapening the means of both physical and mental production, but also eliminating the transaction costs for crowdsourced financing (or crowdfunding, defined by Oxford Dictionaries.com as “The practice of funding a project or venture by raising many small amounts of money from a large number of people, typically via the Internet”).

New technology is a source of “unemployment” for people who currently have “jobs,” rather than simply being tools for ordinary people to use to produce for their own subsistence and trade with others, if we assume the persistence of a framework in which production is carried out by “companies” that control access to the machinery. The authors cite a study which found that

companies used digital technologies to reorganize decision-making authority, incentives systems, information flows, hiring systems, and other aspects of their management and organizational processes. This coinvention of organization and technology not only significantly increased productivity but tended to require more-educated workers and reduce demand for less-skilled workers.

Note the assumption: the “company” owns the machines, decides how to organize production, and decides what workers it needs to hire to carry it out.

Obsolete assumptions

But the new production technology is making those assumptions obsolete. Let’s start instead from the assumption of a subsistence farmer. If he comes up with a new way of doing things that enables him to produce the same amount of corn with half the work, he doesn’t lament all the work that it will put him out of. That’s because he owns both the farm and the final product, and internalizes all the benefits.

All these predictions that big industrial companies will organize assembly lines with CNC routers, cutting tables, drill presses, and 3-D printers, with robots that transfer unfinished goods between them, ignore one thing: the open-source versions of most of those CNC tools can be built for under $1,000 each, and are entirely within the means of small neighborhood cooperative shops manufacturing for local barter-exchange networks in return for the output of other shops, of home microbakeries and microbreweries, surplus garden produce, babysitting and barbering, and the like. As John Robb wrote on his Twitter feed, “You can either compete with technology for a job, or use it to help you make a living outside of a job. Your choice.”

The main source of continued corporate control of the production process is all those artificial property rights such as patents, trademarks, and business licenses, that give corporations a monopoly on the conditions under which the new technologies can be used. But “intellectual property” is becoming increasingly unenforceable (take another look at that 40-percent drop in music revenue), and corporations that are going bankrupt from a collapse in aggregate demand and that will suffer from disintegration of their supply and distribution chains in the face of $15/gallon fuel (my projection) probably aren’t going to have the resources to notice or care about garage producers who fill in the gaps — let alone do anything about it.

And in the meantime the state barriers ordinary people face from the other direction — barriers that put an artificial floor under the cost of subsistence by criminalizing vernacular building technology (by means of building codes written by contractors) and criminalizing home-based enterprise (through zoning and occupational licensing) — will also become unenforceable as fiscally strapped local governments find themselves faced simultaneously with record homelessness and unemployment and record numbers of abandoned, foreclosed, and condemned vacant housing.

In other words, the solution is not a universal basic income or other expedient to reallocate the wealth that naturally accumulates in the hands of the few, or a Japanese-style school system to turn everyone into more-valuable corporate human resources. And it’s not massive new subsidies to “infrastructure” to make centralized, hierarchical firms serving large market areas artificially profitable (as railroad land grants and the Interstates did for mass-production dinosaur corporations). It’s to destroy all the state-enforced monopolies that shift wealth to the few in the first place, prevent the relocalization of production, and give corporations control over employment.

The upshot all these wonderful new technologies that Brynjolfsson and McAfee write about — and they are wonderful! — will reach their full potential not within the framework of the existing corporate power structure, but within the new economy that arises from the ruins of this one.

This article was originally published in the January 2015 edition of Future of Freedom.

Translations of this article:

Italian, Stateless Embassies
Libero Mercato Come Lotta di Classe

Un articolo recente a proposito delle elezioni britanniche citava una lettera che ammoniva gli elettori sostenendo che un governo laburista avrebbe danneggiato la ripresa economica del paese. Avallata dai leader delle maggiori industrie britanniche e inviata al quotidiano The Telegraph, la lettera sosteneva che l’elezione di un governo conservatore avrebbe mandato questo segnale al resto del mondo: “la Gran Bretagna è favorevole agli affari” e prosegue fermamente sulla strada tracciata da David Cameron con il suo taglio fiscale alle aziende. L’articolo continuava dicendo che l’attacco di Ed Milliband alle aziende aveva riportato l’orologio indietro agli anni ottanta, riportando la politica britannica “indietro alla vecchia formula della lotta di classe che qualcuno è abbastanza vecchio da ricordare.” Il titolo dell’articolo (“Lotta di classe contro libero mercato: non l’abbiamo già visto?”) è particolarmente interessante perché dà per scontato che la lotta di classe e il libero mercato stiano ai poli opposti della politica, e che non si possa avere l’una e l’altra cosa assieme.

L’idea che libero mercato significhi dominio corporativo e monopolizzazione è tra i presupposti di base di quasi tutte le discussioni politiche di oggi. Raramente messa seriamente in discussione, questa premessa sulla relazione di causa tra mercati e ingiustizia economica è diffusa anche nel linguaggio dei sostenitori del presunto libero mercato. Tutti, da una parte e dall’altra del dibattito politico, sembrano dare per scontato che chiunque si occupi di problemi come la diseguaglianza economica debba opporsi al libero mercato, e che essere antibusiness e essere antimercato siano la stessa cosa.

Da anarchico individualista, non credo a questa versione della realtà. Al contrario, credo che esistano buone ragioni per rigettarla. Tanto per cominciare, visti gli enormi privilegi e favoritismi concessi alle grandi aziende nel sistema economico, sembra strano che le discussioni finiscano sempre per accusare il puro e semplice libero scambio per le colpe commesse dalle grandi aziende. Apparentemente, è di moda pensare che il “capitalismo clientelare” sia un’eccezione al libero mercato, che ovviamente è un sistema basato sulla pura libertà d’impresa. Sarebbe molto più realistico pensare al capitalismo internazionale come ad un sistema caratterizzato essenzialmente dalla violazione del nostro concetto, normale e assennato, di libero mercato.

Se per “libero mercato” s’intende semplicemente un sistema in cui individui liberi possono associarsi e contrattare tra loro senza interferenze esterne, sotto la dovuta protezione del loro legittimo diritto alla proprietà privata, allora il sistema attualmente in uso in tutto il mondo è tutt’altro che libero mercato: tutto il sistema è l’eccezione alla norma. Forse quel fenomeno chiamato capitalismo storico non merita il beneficio del dubbio da parte dei libertari sostenitori del libero mercato. In questo caso, forse, chi difende coerentemente la competizione aperta, la proprietà privata e la sovranità dell’individuo in realtà appartiene alla sinistra radicale, è contro l’attuale sistema economico e rivendica i diritti di poveri e diseredati.

Allora il libero mercato è esso stesso una forma di lotta di classe. Non una rivolta violenta volta a riprendere il maltolto, ma un movimento graduale in direzione della libertà e dell’equità, una lenta sconnessione della politica dall’economica. In Gran Bretagna come nel resto del mondo, i lavoratori non hanno bisogno dello stato che garantisca loro particolari riconoscimenti o nuove protezioni. Al contrario, tutto ciò che occorre loro per recuperare il potere di contrattazione perduto è l’abolizione dei tanti trattamenti di favore che lo stato garantisce alle grandi aziende: agevolazioni, requisiti e licenze protettive, e leggi sulla proprietà intellettuale che impediscono alle persone della classe lavoratrice di spianare la propria strada e uscire dall’economia corporativa.

Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.

Odds & Ends, Stigmergy - C4SS Blog
The IRS Loves Anarchy!

The Center for a Stateless Society is delighted to announce that our parent institution, the Molinari Institute, has been declared by the IRS to be a tax-exempt 501(c)(3) nonprofit organization; hence donations to the Molinari Institute – and thus to the Center for a Stateless Society as well – are tax-deductible.

To quote from the IRS’s determination letter, dated 2 April 2015:

We’re pleased to tell you we determined you’re exempt from federal income tax under Internal Revenue Code (IRC) Section 501(c)(3). Donors can deduct contributions they make to you under IRC section 170. You’re also qualified to receive tax deductible bequests, devises, transfers or gifts under Section 2055, 2106, or 2522. … We determined you’re a public charity under the IRC section [509(a)(2)].

The mission of the Molinari Institute is to promote understanding of the philosophy of market anarchism as a sane, consensual alternative to the hypertrophic violence of the State. The Molinari Institute hosts an online open-access library of rare libertarian classics, including new translations of 19th-century French works, and publishes two periodicals: a magazine, The Industrial Radical, and an academic journal, the Molinari Review. The Molinari Society, a daughter organisation, hosts annual symposia at the Eastern and Pacific Divisions of the American Philosophical Association.

The Center for a Stateless Society (C4SS), an autonomous extension of the Molinari Institute, develops and publishes timely written commentary on current events, research pieces and other content from a market anarchist perspective. Each week the Center submits several op-ed pieces to thousands of newspapers and other media outlets globally, and has received about 2500 mainstream media pickups since 2010. The Center’s student affiliate network, the Students for a Stateless Society (S4SS), offers opportunities for campus outreach and activism.

Future projects for both the Institute and the Center include book publishing (both classic and original works), conferences, courses (online and otherwise), new translation projects, and media presentations.

Both the Institute and the Center are part of the Alliance of the Libertarian Left, which opposes statism, militarism, cultural intolerance, and the prevailing corporatist capitalism falsely called a free market. The Alliance’s Distro, in partnership with the Institute and Center, produces and distributes zines and booklets on anarchism, market anarchist theory, counter-economics, and other movements for liberation.

You can donate to support the work of the Molinari Institute here, and the work of the Center for a Stateless Society here.

Feature Articles
Why I Fight for $15

The Fight for $15 movement is usually identified with the fight for a $15 minimum wage. A call for government legislation is not the sort of thing you’d normally expect an anarchist to endorse. But in fact the movement to pay workers $15 or more is quite compatible with anarchist principles.

Back in the late 19th century, the American movement for an eight-hour day included people from a wide range of political ideologies. Some favored federal legislation to achieve their goal. But the movement also included numerous anarchist tendencies, including individualist anarchists affiliated with the New England Labor Reform League. The nationwide general strike for an eight-hour day was seen by some as a call for a government-mandated limit to the working day, but it was also a pressure campaign on employers. That’s how I see the Fight for $15 campaign.

Information and pressure campaigns against employers by unconventional labor organizations are arguably more effective than conventional campaigns under the umbrella of the AFL-CIO or SEIU, as witnessed by efforts like the Coalition of Immolakee Workers and OURWalmart. Such campaigns, allied with community social justice and civil rights organizations, and making use of direct action on the job, can make a tame AFL-CIO union certified under Wagner Act rules look comparatively appealing to an employer.

Right-wing libertarians frequently argue that labor action to raise wages is useless, because in a free market wages reflect workers’ marginal productivity. Hence forcing employers to pay a minimum wage will simply raise unemployment, by making workers whose marginal productivity is less than the minimum wage unemployable.

This argument makes several huge assumptions. First, it assumes that this is, in fact, a free market. But it is not. We have an economy in which the state has intervened in the market on behalf of capitalists and landlords to make capital and land artificially scarce and expensive, and acted in other ways to raise entry barriers against self-employment, so that wage employers are protected against the need to compete for workers against the possibility of self-employment or employment in worker-owned enterprise. As a result, employers are able to hire workers for a wage less than the full product of their labor; the difference between the free market wage of labor and what is actually paid under capitalism amounts to a substantial economic rent. Hence, an increase in wages resulting from increased bargaining power of labor can come out of this rent.

Second, it assumes that employers have some idea of what the marginal productivity of their workers is. But as Auburn University Professor Roderick Long argues, this is quite unlikely.

First of all, most employers do not know with any great precision their workers’ marginal revenue product. Firms are, after all, islands of central planning – on a small enough scale that the gains from central coordination generally outweigh the losses, but still they are epistemically hampered by the absence of internal markets…. A firm confronts the test of profitability as a unit, not employee by employee, and so there is a fair bit of guesswork involved in paying workers according to their profitability….

A firm that doesn’t pay adequate attention to profitability is doomed to failure, certainly; but precisely because we’re not living in the world of neoclassical perfect competition, firms can survive and prosper without being profit-maximisers. They just have to be less crazy/stupid than their competitors.

This leaves bargaining by workers as an important part of the discovery mechanism by which the marginal productivity of labor is determined.

And third, it assumes that the demand for labor is highly elastic. Right-wing libertarians are fond of claiming that increased minimum wages will increase unemployment, while leaving out the vital term “ceteris paribus” — all other things remaining equal. Factors like relatively inflexible consumer demand for fast food, the fact that labor cost is only one component of a business’s operating cost, and the fact that higher wages paid by all employers in a particular industry and locality would eliminate labor as an issue for cost competition, all complicate this simplistic assertion.

But let’s assume for a moment that labor is the main cost of service industry businesses. In that case, the fact that labor rather than capital outlays is the primary expense raises the question of why labor, as the scarce factor, isn’t calling the shots and hiring capital for worker-owned and -managed enterprises, rather than the other way around. The answer is that the owners of capital, working through the state by such expedients as bank licensing and capitalization laws, have preempted the avenues through which workers could advance capital to one another and given capitalists a monopoly on the issue of credit. And through zoning and safety codes, they have made renting expensive real estate and purchasing industrial-scale equipment a condition for establishing enterprises like restaurants, thereby foreclosing low-overhead micro-restaurants and -diners operated out of people’s homes, using the ordinary food preparation machinery in their own kitchens (along with similarly outlawing other home-based services like daycare, hair styling, ride-sharing, and the like).

Another common argument is that higher restaurant wages will result in employers automating fast food jobs out of existence. But remember that automats were once a thing, in the mid-20th century. They didn’t catch on for a reason. Interacting with actual human servers is part of the restaurant experience. Next time you’re in a retail establishment, take note of the number of people lined up to be checked out by a human cashier while the self-serve checkouts sit idle.

One practice of the nineteenth century labor movement that deserves revival is the formation of worker-owned and -managed enterprises by workers on strike. This has long been feasible in industries where human capital is the main cost, like temp agencies and various services. But current technological trends, which reduce the capital outlays for undertaking garage production with tabletop CNC machinery to the equivalent of a few months’ factory wages, greatly expand the number of industries where this is a possibility.

I for one am not interested in working through the state to impose a higher minimum wage. I think workers, acting through grassroots labor campaigns and direct action, should hit employers so hard that they beg government to protect them from us.

Commentary
A Shill for the Banksters Falls Prey to Mirror-Imaging

In a recent speech to the Mortgage Bankers Association, Sen. Ben Sasse — a freshman Republican from Nebraska — jokingly accused his colleague Elizabeth Warren of wanting to remove all risk from the economy. Presumably he means that Warren wants to insulate ordinary people from risks like mortgages with unsustainable payments relative to their unexpectedly reduced income, or negative equity in homes they’re making payments on because of a bad housing markets.

But he should get a Nobel prize in chutzpah for accusing Warren of wanting to eliminate risk, when he was speaking before representatives of the industry that gave birth to the phrase “too big to fail.” The federal government spent hundreds of billions bailing out the banking industry under the TARP plan, in order to save them from the consequences of their own foolish risk-taking. The TARP program, under both Paulson and Geithner, was aimed at preventing deflation of the rentier classes’ assets by buying up bad mortgages at face value. That’s basically identical to what Alexander Hamilton did in the first Washington administration, paying off Continental war bonds at face value despite the fact their market value had declined to a tiny percentage of that and most of them were held by investors who’d bought them at a very low price from their original holders. Of course, even though it was just fine for the government to bail out the banks at taxpayer expense, it was totally not OK to attach conditions to the aid, like marking the mortgage principals down to current market values, or limiting CEOs’ bonuses. See, that would be interference in the free market.

It’s decidedly odd for Sasse to talk as though eliminating risk is a bad thing, when socializing corporate risks and operating costs and privatizing profit is the main thing the capitalist state does. New Left historian Gabriel Kolko coined the term “political capitalism” to describe the 20th century regulatory-welfare state. Political capitalism is “the utilization of political outlets to attain conditions of stability, predictability, and security — to attain rationalization — in the economy.” That means political action to restrict price competition to manageable levels, enable big business to plan on the basis of long-term predictable expectations, and create a rational political economic environment in which business can obtain “reasonable profits” in the long run.

The entire industrial landscape takes the form it does because the state — either under the aegis of the permanent war economy or “progressive” programs like the creation of the civil aviation and Interstate Highway systems — assumed so much of the investment cost and risks of new industries, and enforced anti-competive regulatory cartels by such means as the ICC Act’s restrictions on price competition and the state-facilitated pooling and exchange of patents.

The state, in short, is — as Marx described it over a century ago — the executive committee of the capitalist ruling class. Socializing cost and risk, so that the corporate interests in charge can collect guaranteed monopoly profits, is what the state does. No one should know that better than Sasse and the bankster hogs who paid $100 a plate to belly up to the trough and listen to him. But I guess it only counts as “removing risk,” in Sasse’s view, when it’s done on behalf of the little people.

Translations for this article:

Italian, Stateless Embassies
Il Problema Conoscitivo delle Prerogative

Nel suo saggio classico, “The Use of Knowledge in Society” (L’Uso della Conoscenza nella Società, es), F. A. Hayek parla del concetto di conoscenza distribuita. Ogni individuo ha una conoscenza unica che deriva dalle sue esperienze e dalle sue preferenze, conoscenza a cui altri, per quanto informati, non possono accedere. Scrive Hayek:

Dire che la conoscenza scientifica non è la somma di tutte le conoscenze oggi è quasi un’eresia. Ma basta riflettere un po’ per capire che esiste indubbiamente un corpus di conoscenze, importantissimo ma non organizzato, che non si può definire scientifico, nel senso che non se ne conoscono le regole generali, cioè le particolari circostanze di tempo e luogo. È in questo senso che ognuno di noi possiede un qualche vantaggio su tutti gli altri. Perché è solo lui a possedere le informazioni necessarie alla creazione di un beneficio particolare. La condizione necessaria, dunque, è che le decisioni siano prese da lui o con la sua cooperazione attiva.

Hayek poi fa alcuni esempi di come questa conoscenza si applica in un contesto economico. Produttori, consumatori e altri individui che cooperano in un mercato, possiedono tutti quanti conoscenze accessibili soltanto a loro, conoscenze completamente inaccessibili da parte di qualunque burocrate o pianificatore centrale.

Ma il discorso che fa Hayek riguardo la conoscenza distribuita non si limita all’economia. Si applica anche a questioni sociali. Prendiamo le questioni legate al rapporto tra i sessi. Le donne nella loro vita quotidiana sono soggette a misoginia. Ci sono individui femminili che sanno cose riguardo le molestie sessuali, la discriminazione, e un’ampia gamma di problemi legati al sesso che io non conoscerò mai perché non sono una donna e non ho mai avuto esperienza di queste cose. Riconoscere l’esistenza della conoscenza distribuita è importante. Significa che non posso liquidare l’esperienza sessista subita da una donna né posso presumere di saperne più di lei. Significa che nel campo dell’attivismo femminista non potrò mai avere la voce in capitolo che ha una donna oppressa da una società patriarcale. In altre parole, il fatto di riconoscere che la conoscenza è distribuita mi porta a “controllare le mie prerogative”.

Vediamo un altro esempio: i disabili. Da anni il movimento per i diritti dei disabili opera sotto lo slogan “Niente su di Noi Senza di Noi”, e si oppone ai tanti gruppi che provano a prendere decisioni che influiscono sui disabili senza prima consultare un disabile. Ad esempio, Autism Speaks, una delle più grosse organizzazioni no-profit che si occupano di autismo, non ha mai avuto un autistico nel suo direttivo. A dispetto del nome, non parlano per noi autistici, ma su di noi. Sull’autismo hanno diffuso una propaganda del terrore che molte persone autistiche, io compreso, ritengono altamente offensiva. Promuovono programmi e “cure” che per gli autistici sono del tutto inutili e controproduttive. Dovrebbero tener conto delle conoscenze degli autistici, conoscenze che a loro mancano. In altre parole, dovrebbero riconoscere che la conoscenza è distribuita e dunque dovrebbero controllare le loro prerogative.

Detto questo, però, dato che Autism Speak non è un’organizzazione governativa e non è un monopolio, noi autistici possiamo, dobbiamo, dare vita alle nostre iniziative. L’Autistic Self Advocacy Network può fornire servizi realmente utili agli autistici, dando una voce autonoma all’autismo. E se l’Autistic Self Advocacy Network non dovesse soddisfare i bisogni di certi autistici, questi ultimi potrebbero dare vita ai loro organismi autonomi. Questo è giusto un esempio di come le associazioni volontarie trasformano la conoscenza distribuita in qualcosa di efficace, per quanto ci siano bigotti che si rifiutano di praticare questa umiltà epistemica. Certo, Autism Speak dovrebbe controllare la propria ignoranza e le proprie prerogative, ma è anche vero che questa loro ignoranza costituisce una minaccia minore perché non stiamo parlando di un’organizzazione governativa o di un monopolio.

Come nell’economia, anche in ambito sociale il problema dell’arroganza epistemologica diventa tanto più grande quanto più lo stato ne è coinvolto. I politici, per definizione, non hanno le conoscenze che hanno tutti quelli interessati dalle loro politiche. Spesso, quando ad essere colpiti sono gruppi marginalizzati, i politici tendono più che volentieri ad ignorarli. Il Congresso, ad esempio, ha organizzato degli incontri per cercare di capire se è lecito violare i diritti dei “malati di mente” americani, ma non ha ammesso a testimoniare proprio i disabili psichici giudicandoli non abbastanza “competenti”. Un altro esempio è quello dei carcerati privati del diritto di voto. Lo stato esaspera la sua tendenza naturale ad una conoscenza limitata privando dei diritti quei gruppi marginalizzati che cerca di dominare. I politici dovrebbero riflettere, come dice Hayek, “sulla pochezza del loro sapere quando credono di avere la capacità di pianificare.” Dovrebbero tenere conto dell’esperienza e delle conoscenze delle persone affette dalle loro politiche. Dovrebbero, insomma, controllare le loro prerogative.

Chiedere a qualcuno di controllare le proprie prerogative, però, non significa metterlo a tacere. Significa cercare di fargli capire i limiti della sua conoscenza. Noi libertari dovremmo avere l’umiltà di controllare le nostre prerogative, dovremmo ascoltare gli oppressi che raccontano le loro esperienze, rispettare il diritto di chiunque di dirigere da solo i propri sforzi verso la libertà.

Potete aiutare C4SS acquistando una copia di “The Knowledge Problem of Privilege”, di Nathan Goodman.

Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.

Portuguese, Stateless Embassies
O que diabos os Estados Unidos estão fazendo no Iêmen?

O governo dos Estados Unidos se jogou em outra guerra civil no Oriente Médio. Quando nós já nos perguntamos “quando é que eles vão aprender?”, talvez a resposta seja que os governantes não têm qualquer incentivo para fazer as coisas de forma diferente. O que parece um fracasso pode ser o resultado esperado. Esses atoleiros podem ser benéficos — para a elite governante — se as baixas americanas forem mínimas.

A administração Obama tem auxiliado a Arábia Saudita em seu bombardeio do Iêmen, criando — em conjunto com o embargo saudita — uma catástrofe humanitária no país mais pobre do Oriente Médio. Civis morrem e a pouca infraestrutura do país está sendo destruída.

Por quê? O Secretário de Estado John Kerry afirma que os EUA “não ficarão parados enquanto a região é desestabilizada”. Kerry é um veterano e, presumivelmente, um conhecedor da guerra americana na Indochina. Ele deve saber que um bombardeio é uma maneira terrível de evitar a desestabilização. Kerry não é burro — mas aparentemente é mentiroso e demagogo.

Note que ele fala da “região”, mas não do Iêmen. Por que uma guerra civil no Iêmen afetaria a região? Porque, de acordo com a narrativa oficial, religiosamente repetida pela maior parte da mídia, o Iêmen está sob ataque de agentes do Irã, os Houthis.

O Irã hoje em dia serve ao mesmo propósito que servia a União Soviética ou a Conspiração Comunista Internacional durante a Guerra Fria. O Irã é um arqui-inimigo para todos os propósitos, podendo ser responsável por qualquer dos males políticos do mundo. Assim, o partido da guerra e seus aliados sauditas e israelenses nos dizem todos os dias que o Irã está se movendo, controlando capitais em todo o Oriente Médio: Bagdá, Damasco, Beiture e, agora, Sanaá.

Isso tudo, porém, é absurdo. O Irã não está se movendo. George W. Bush entregou Bagdá aos xiitas iraquianos amigáveis ao Irã em 2003. Obama e sua primeira secretária de estado, Hillary Clinton, declararam temporada de caça ao regime de Assad na Síria, que é um aliado iraniano de longa data, e assim fortaleceram a al-Qaeda e sua mutação mais violenta, o ISIS. Os aliados do Irã no Líbano, o partido político Hezbollah, se formou em resposta à invasão e ocuapação israelense de 1982. Nada disso demonstra a agressividade do Irã. Uma explicação melhor é que essas alianças ajudam o Irã a lidar com o cerco americano. (Lembre-se: a CIA derrubou o governo democrático do Irã em 1953 e foi cúmplice na guerra ofensiva do Iraque nos anos 1980 contra o Irã, na qual Saddam Hussein utilizou armas químicas adquiridas com facilitação americana. Desde então, os presidentes dos EUA e o governo de Israel têm atacado o Irã de várias formas: economicamente, ciberneticamente, patrocinando terroristas e com operações secretas.)

E quanto ao Iêmen, onde os Houthis derrubaram o presidente autocrata apoiado pelos EUA enquanto lutavam contra inimigos declarados dos americanos, como a al-Qaeda sunita na Península Arábica e os aliados iemenitas do ISIS? Sim, os Houthis praticam um tipo de islamismo xiita, zaidi, mas ele difere de várias formas do xiismo iraniano. Na verdade, os Houthis são apenas a manifestação mais recente de uma minoria religiosa iemenita oprimida há muito tempo que busca autonomia do governo central. Depois de anos de frustração e mentiras, eles finalmente se moveram contra esse governo. Diga o que quiser sobre esse grupo, mas não o chame de agente do Irã.

A Arábia Saudita considera o Irã como ameaça, mas seu governo não tem qualquer credibilidade e a administração Obama provavelmente está apenas apaziguando a família real agora que um acordo nuclear com o Irã está em curso. Como o pesquisador independente Jonathan Marshall observa: “Décadas antes de o Irã se tornar o inimigo (…), a Arábia Saudita começou a intervir em seu vizinho do sul. Além de tomar terras, os sauditas enviaram grandes somas de dinheiro para o Iêmen para promover sua versão extrema de islamismo sunita chamada wahhabismo. Em 2009, ela invadiu o norte do Iêmen para atacar os Houthis, sem sucesso.”

Marshal ainda acrescenta: “Washington (…) tem se envolvido nos conflitos civis do Iêmen há décadas.”

Claro, Washington tem também matado iemenitas com drones — nem todos são mesmo “suspeitos de terrorismo” — desde 2001, quando o governo corrupto e repressivo em Sanaá se tornou um aliado na “guerra ao terror”.

“O governo iemenita repetidamente usava auxílio do exército americano para sustentar seu ataque contra os Houthis (‘Operação Scorched Earth’), causando um enorme número de fatalidades civis”, observa marshall.

Como já deveríamos saber a este ponto, a intervenção dos Estados Unidos não é um erro inocente.

Traduzido por Erick Vasconcelos.

C4SS Events, Stigmergy - C4SS Blog
C4SS at NYC (A) Book Fair!

Tomorrow, C4SS and ALL will be teaming up to provide good quality but still dirt cheap literature for ALL to enjoy at the anarchist book fair in New York City.

Darian Worden of C4SS, myself and others will be under the NJ Alliance of Libertarian Left banner as per usual so look for us under that name. We hope to present an alternative to both communist and capitalist forms of anarchism.

In pursuit of this goal, we’ll have copies of the Market Anarchy Series as well as Industrial Radical, Markets Not Capitalism and much more. There will also be some cheap pins and free pamphlets to round out our inventory.

You can find the book fair at the Judson Memorial Church, which is located near the Washington Square Park and Manhattan.

If you’re considering going, I’d personally recommend attending the following talks: “The Brooklyn Solidarity Network: Anarchism in Practice”, “Books that Burn: Radical Publishing Today and Tomorrow?”, Decentralism, Direct Democracy, and Federalism”, What Makes a Queer Relationship Queer?” and “Spreading the Anarchist Movement”.

And in terms of vendors make sure to check out: AK Press, Autonomedia, Institute for Anarchist Studies, Little Black Cart, NYC Anarchist Black Cross, PM Press and Wooden Shoe Books.

For a full listing of vendors check out the Facebook event page.

Hope to see you there!

Anarchy and Democracy
Fighting Fascism
Markets Not Capitalism
The Anatomy of Escape
Organization Theory