Commentary
Fear, Violence and the Absurd

Nearly a month after the tragic massacre at Sandy Hook Elementary School, the ensuing “debate” over gun control and gun violence still looks less like the exchange of ideas and discussion on systemic violence we need to be having, and more like an absurdist tragicomedy; the latest “act” of which is, of course, the recent “interview” between TV tabloid hack Piers Morgan and conspiranoid* fear-mongering talk radio host Alex Jones.

Ostensibly, the two got together in the same room to “debate” each other over gun control. That was how the show was billed, and what appeared on the lower third graphic when the exchange finally aired. And this makes sense: for the last several weeks Morgan has been calling for measures that many — if not most — libertarians and anarchists would no doubt oppose, while Jones is without a doubt one of the the most outspoken (some would say vitriolic) gun rights advocates with access to a microphone and Internet connection.

Those who saw the interview know that nothing like a reasonable conversation actually took place. For those who didn’t watch, this short analysis by fellow C4SS writer Jason Lee Byas captures the spirit of the spectacle nicely: “Within two minutes, (Jones) starts screaming. Within five minutes, he challenges Morgan to a boxing match. Towards the end he begins mocking Morgan’s accent.” In other words, viewers of the program were treated to a dramatic teleplay of epically absurd proportions.

It’s immediately clear that both players were aware of their assigned roles, and they performed them beautifully. Jones was the court jester (or perhaps a more apt description would be rodeo clown?), responsible for keeping us, the audience, riled up and agitated — and more importantly, entertained; Morgan was the quintessential “straight man,” a stoic voice of reason, remaining steadfast after Jones’ whirlwind of irrationality died down. You can find evidence of this in how Morgan described the interview during an appearance on “CNN Newsroom” early Tuesday:

“I can’t think of a better advertisement for gun control than Jones’ interview last night. […] It was startling, it was terrifying in parts, it was completely deluded.”

It almost sounds like Morgan was describing a particularly effective horror movie from the 1930s. “You’ll scream! You’ll shake! You’ll come back for more! Witness the horror masterpiece of the century!” you can very nearly hear him exclaim. In fact, the interview is so scary that it compels viewers to swing right back around to a pro-gun stance; as Laissez-Faire Books editor Jeffrey Tucker wrote in a tongue-in-cheek Facebook post, “If we get gun control, what means will the people have to protect themselves against Alex Jones?”

Joking aside, what no one — not Jones, not Morgan, not liberals or conservatives, nor (to a lesser extent) libertarians and anarchists — is willing to admit is that the problem of gun violence, and violence in general, is a wicked problem, eluding easy answers completely and teasing more complex ones unfairly. It is, like poverty or climate change, an absurd problem.

Liberals want a more powerful regulatory state concerning gun rights. Conservatives and right libertarians oppose this on constitutional grounds, and left-libertarians and anarchists oppose it on the grounds that they don’t want a stronger state, period. Conservatives want a bigger police state with armed guards in every school. Liberals (or, as Roderick Long calls them, the “aristocratic left”) agree with this proposal but disagree on the uniform the guards wear, while libertarians, anarchists and individual progressives (the anti-privilege left) definitively oppose it.

Right-libertarians would like to see a less-regulatory state and more guns in the hands of individuals for self-defense, which liberals oppose. Conservatives play lip-service to it but would probably oppose it if it meant the “wrong” people getting their hands on guns. Of course, left-libertarians and anarchists by and large want to dismantle a state that advocates and promotes violence on a systemic scale; this solution is one that liberals and conservatives alike strongly oppose.

The possibility no one will admit exists — or, at least, they won’t in any serious sense — is that there may not be a solution to gun violence. For all the good a conversation on systemic violence, state violence, militarism, etc. might do for a small percentage of the population, the fact that at the end of the day, the current state still exists, will serve to nullify that good. People will still deify military service. Children will still be raised to want to be police officers. And the absurd problem will continue on a systemic level. Therefore, we must, as oppositional forces often do, commit to an absurd answer; we must struggle to teach our own children to reject killing, to reject domination over each other, to reject that systemic violence.

*(portmanteau of conspiracy theorist and paranoid)

Distro of the Libertarian Left
Support C4SS with Charles Johnson’s “Socialize, Don’t Privatize”

C4SS has teamed up with the Distro of the Libertarian Left. The Distro produces and distribute zines and booklets on anarchism, market anarchist theory, counter-economics, and other movements for liberation. For every copy of Charles Johnson’s “Socialize, Don’t Privatize” that you purchase through the Distro, C4SS will receive a percentage. Support C4SS with Charles Johnson’s “Socialize, Don’t Privatize“.

$1.00 for the first copy. $0.75 for every additional copy.

Market Anarchists should oppose neoliberalism and its so-called “privatization” schemes because we are for free markets and private property. What they call “privatization” means only private profit from political power. What we mean is something entirely different, and it’s time to mint some new language in order to talk about the difference.

Left libertarians, like all libertarians, believe that all State control of industry and all State ownership of natural resources should be abolished. In that sense, libertarian Leftists advocate complete and absolute privatization of, well, everything. Governments, or quasi-governmental “public” monopolies, have no business building or running roads, bridges, railroads, airports, parks, housing, libraries, post offices, television stations, electric lines, power plants, water works, oil rigs, gas pipelines, or any­thing else of the sort. . . . Governments have no business building or running fire departments, police stations, courts, arm­ies, or anything else of the sort, because governments — which are necessarily coerc­ive and necessarily elitist — have no business existing or doing anything at all.

There is something called “privatization” which has been a hot topic for the past 15-20 years. It has been a big deal in Eastern Europe, in third world countries under the influence of the IMF, and in some cases in the United States, too. Naomi Klein has a new book on the topic, which focuses on the role that natural and artificial crises play in establishing the conditions for what she calls “privatization.” But “privatization,” as understood by the IMF, the neoliberal governments, and the robber baron corporations, is a very different beast from “privatization” as understood by free market radicals. . . . What we advocate is the devolution of state-confiscated wealth and state-confiscated industries back to civil society . . . the “socialization of the means of production.” Government outsourcing, government-backed monopoly capitalism, and government goon squads, might more accurately be described as “privateering.” . . .

Left-Libertarian - Classics
How Inequality Shapes Our Lives

How Inequality Shapes Our Lives (Part 1)

Those of us who regard socioeconomic inequality as a serious problem are often accused of “envy,” as though such concerns were simply a matter of begrudging someone else’s having more cookies than we do.

I think this reaction misses the point in a number of ways; let me say just a bit about just one of those ways:

Suppose you forget to pay your power bill (or your phone bill, or your cable tv bill, or your internet access bill, or your credit card bill, or whatever). What happens? Your provider disconnects you, and you’ll probably have to pay an extra fee to get service reestablished. You also get a frowny face on your credit report.

On the other hand, suppose that, for whatever reason (internet glitches, downed power lines after a storm, or who knows), you suffer a temporary interruption of service from your provider. Do they offer to reimburse you? Hell no. And there’s no easy way for you to put a frowny face on their credit report.

Now, if you rent your home, take a look at your lease. Did you write it? Of course not. Did you and your landlord write it together? Again, of course not. It was written by your landlord (or by your landlord’s lawyer), and is filled with far more stipulations of your obligations to her than of her obligations to you. It may even contain such ominously sweeping language as “lessee agrees to abide by all such additional instructions and regulations as the lessor may from time to time provide” (which, if taken literally, would be not far shy of a slavery contract). If you’re late in paying your rent, can the landlord assess a punitive fee? You betcha. By contrast, if she’s late in fixing the toilet, can you withhold a portion of the rent? Just try it.

Now think about your relationship with your employer. In theory, you and she are free and equal individuals entering into a contract for mutual benefit. In practice, she most likely orders the hours and minutes of your day in exacting detail. As with the landlord case, the contract is provided by her and is designed to benefit her. She also undertakes to interpret it; and you will find yourself subjected to loads of regulations and directives that you never consented to. And if you try inventing new obligations for her as she does for you, I predict you will be, shall we say, disappointed.

These aren’t merely cases of some people having more stuff than you do. They’re cases in which some people are systematically empowered to dictate the terms on which other people live, work, and trade. And we generally take it for granted. But it’s not obvious that things have to be that way.

When it comes to diagnosis and prescription, those of us who worry about socioeconomic inequality go in two different directions. Some identify the free market as the cause of such inequality, and government regulation as the cure; for others, it’s precisely the other way around. I’m obviously with the latter group; all the phenomena I mentioned are made possible by systematic restrictions on competition. Libertarians need to spend more time focusing on liberty as the solution to these pervasive asymmetries of power, rather than giving the impression that they find them unproblematic.

How Inequality Shapes Our Lives (Part 2)

My friend Bryan Caplan has a response to my recent post about inequality. I’m preparing to leave town for the Alabama Philosophical Society and so probably won’t have a chance to reply in detail until I get back. (This also applies to the comments section of my previous post, which I haven’t had a chance to look at.) But three short points just for now:

a) Bryan’s response focuses on the ways in which free markets would solve the problems I point to if they were really problems. But the whole point of my position is that we don’t have a free market! Left-libertarians have pointed out in detail the ways in which the housing and labour markets, for example, are skewed in ologopolistic and oligopsonistic directions respectively. By ignoring these analyses rather than refuting them, Bryan in effect assumes the problems out of existence; he might just as well say “taxes can’t really be too high, because if they were, consumers would just switch to a rival protection agency with lower fees.”

b) The fact that workers can shirk, that tenants can be delinquent, etc., is beside the point. We already know upfront that each party to a contract can potentially screw over the other. The point is that, giventhat context, the contracts are then skewed to favour one side. That skewing isn’t counterbalanced by the other side’s capacity for delinquency, because each side has that capacity, and one side has the favourable contract in addition.

c) Yes, there are various regulations that purport to help the weaker party to the contract; but left-libertarians have argued in detail that those regulations in practice actually tend to help the stronger party instead. Maybe we’re right about that and maybe we’re wrong, but as far as I know, Bryan hasn’t addressed those arguments, and we can hardly be expected to pretend we haven’t made them.

 

Stigmergy - C4SS Blog, Supporter Updates
Another Successful C4SS Tor Fundraiser

In three days, thanks to our wonderful and charitable supporters, we have successfully funded the C4SS Tor node for another quarter.

We did receive a couple of comments and questions about the Tor Project, what is it and how it works.

Wendy Seltzer – what is the tor project?

How governments have tried to block Tor.

http://youtu.be/GwMr8Xl7JMQ

Thank you again for your support. The state is damage, we will find a route around it.

Commentary
Authority is the Enemy of Rationality

In a Washington Post commentary piece last month (“Why rental apartments have more inefficient fridges,” December 22), Brad Plumer investigated why rental units tend to have less efficient refrigerators than privately-owned homes. The answer, obviously, is that while the fridges are generally purchased by the landlord or property manager, it’s the tenant who pays the electric bill.

This is a classic example of an externality: That is, the positive and negative consequences of a decision are not fully borne by the person making it; or put another way, the person who bears the consequences of a decision lacks the authority to decide. Under such circumstances, decisions that optimize the utility of a rational individual may result in suboptimal utility for the system as a whole. Maximum rationality and efficiency require that all the costs and benefits of the decision of any particular actor be included in the bottom line that actor uses to calculate personal utility.

Externalities result from authority. Authority enables one actor to maximize her personal utility, while making socially suboptimal choices, by imposing the negative consequences of her choices on other actors with less authority.

A hierarchy is a mechanism by which an actor at one rung of authority is able to shift cost and effort downward, while appropriating the benefits from others’ efforts. In a hierarchy, the authority of those above is substituted for the experience-based judgment of those in direct contact with a situation. The judgment of the person best qualified to do a job is always subject to interference from someone with less knowledge, whose primary interest is in living off the surplus effort of those below.

When authority-based rules are allowed to interfere with the experience-based judgement of those actually in a situation, the result can only be a net reduction in efficiency and rationality. So the question is, how does such a suboptimal state of affairs continue?

The answer, to put it bluntly, is that it makes us easier to milk. The self-interest of those in authority lies not in optimizing the efficiency of the system as a whole, but in maximizing their own extraction of rents from it. Their interest is in maximizing the absolute size of their slice of the pie, even if doing so results in a smaller pie overall.

Those in authority cannot afford to do the most efficient thing — stop interfering with the judgments of those who actually know what they’re doing — because they know their interests are diametrically opposed to ours.

Efficiency is possible only when the skills and experience-based knowledge to do a job, the full decision-making authority to use one’s own judgment, and the full internalization of the rewards of one’s own activity, are all united in the same actor. But severing these things one from the other is the most basic structural presupposition of our economic system.

Economic privilege — authority — exists so that those at the top can live off the unearned wealth created by others. Those on the bottom who produce the actual wealth cannot be trusted with the discretion to use their own judgment, because they have no rational interest in maximizing the extraction of rent by their superiors.

Hierarchies exist in situations where those engaged in an activity have a fundamental conflict of interest with those who direct and profit from that activity.

Shevek, the anarchist protagonist of Ursula LeGuin’s The Dispossessed, came to the conclusion that hierarchy is a way to do as efficiently as possible what ought not to be done at all. A hierarchy is a machine — basically a steam engine straight out of the factory age — for compelling people to do what they have no direct rational interest in doing, for the benefit of those with whom they have a fundamental conflict of interest.

We anarchists want to eliminate authority as the mechanism by which some people live at other people’s expense and impose their judgment on others. We want to create a society in which all decision making authority is possessed by those with the judgment to do the work, and all common social action results from agreement and voluntary cooperation. We want to create a society in which no one is compelled to work to feed a class of rentiers, and in which all effort receives its full reward.

Authority is the Enemy of Rationality” on C4SS Media.

Distro of the Libertarian Left
Support C4SS with ALL Distro’s “Mutualist Methods: Two Essays on Practical Anarchy”

C4SS has teamed up with the Distro of the Libertarian Left. The Distro produces and distribute zines and booklets on anarchism, market anarchist theory, counter-economics, and other movements for liberation. For every copy of Clarence L. Swartz & Francis D. Tandy’s “Mutualist Methods: Two Essays on Practical Anarchy” that you purchase through the Distro, C4SS will receive a percentage. Support C4SS with Clarence L. Swartz & Francis D. Tandy’s “Mutualist Methods: Two Essays on Practical Anarchy

$2.00 for the first copy. $1.75 for every additional copy.

“The ballot is only a bullet in another form. An appeal to the majority is an appeal to brute force. . . . Instead of actually fighting over questions, it is more economical to count noses and see which side would probably win. . . . The result shown at the polls indicates a certain stage of mental development in the community. As that mental development is changed, the political manifestations of it change also. So we are brought back to the original starting point. If we wish to effect the abolition of the State through politics, we must first teach people how we can get along without it. When that is done, no political action will be necessary. The people will have outgrown the State and will no longer submit to its tyranny. It may still exist and pass laws, but people will no longer obey them, for its power over them will be broken. Political action can never be successful until it is unnecessary. . .” — Francis D. Tandy, VOLUNTARY SOCIALISM: A SKETCH

“Thus the immediate program of Mutualism is presented: In the social sphere, it is the creation and support of such voluntary associations as will be able to supersede the present coercive system, and, in the economic field, the creation and support of such vol­untary agencies as will sharpen individual initiative and responsibil­ity, and free economic life from the oppressive hand of authority and privilege. . . . Mutualists, therefore, advocate the forming of voluntary associations which can demonstrate in actual practice that the various services and functions performed by governments can be furnished and discharged better and cheaper by such associations. . . . By withdrawing support from the State, where it may be done with im­punity, and by ignoring it wherever possible, and where its hand bears most heavily upon the non­invasive citizen, the rigors of governmental interference with individual liberty and with the practice of the princi­ples of Mutualism may be modified by creating a vacuum around the arch­-aggressor.” — Clarence L. Swartz, WHAT IS MUTUALISM?

Stigmergy - C4SS Blog
James M. Buchanan, RIP

Nobel laureate James M. Buchanan has died at the age of 93.

Buchanan thought of himself as a classical liberal and an Austrian economist — but neither a leftist nor an anarchist. But that doesn’t mean left-wing market anarchists don’t have important lessons to learn from him, particularly with regard to two of his most important contributions to social theory.

First, Buchanan pioneered public choice analysis — looking at the behavior of institutional actors, and especially state actors, as ordinary people with ordinary motivations who don’t acquire new fundamental values and attitudes and goals simply because they occupy particular positions. Public choice analysis emphasizes the fact that there’s no reason to expect politicians and other state functionaries to be more “public-spirited” than their counterparts in the corporate sector (and perhaps even less so, given the difficulty of measuring their performance and holding them accountable).

Embracing public choice analysis is, in particular, quite compatible with seeing politicians and bureaucrats as acting in light of motives as shaped by their cronyish relationships with business elites or, indeed, their ability to maximize their own wealth using political power. Public choice analysis isn’t identical with class analysis, not least because the latter assumes not merely that politicians’ motives aren’t any better than ordinary people’s, but, in fact, that they’re worse, for predictable reasons. But the two are naturally complementary. Public choice analysis points to one way in which the state functions as a tool of economic redistribution — not from the rich to the poor, but from everyone, including the poor, to the privileged. Buchanan’s notion that politics should be viewed “without romance” helps to make clear why the hope that the state will save ordinary people from the predatory corporate elite is naïve at best. A one-time self-described socialist, who remembered the arbitrary preference given to people with wealth during his time in the military during World War II, Buchanan could hardly be displeased by this result.

Second, Buchanan called attention to the importance of constitutional constraints on the exercise of state power. His work in constitutional economics focused on, among other things, the logic of institutional design—on the formulation of rules for political decision-making that could be expected to yield desirable economic outcomes. His own work employed a broadly contractarian approach to the justification of a state with limited powers. But it could certainly be taken in a more radical direction. When he rehearsed his Nobel acceptance speech at George Mason University, he observed, in the course of responding to criticism from his audience, “If this argument fails, I’m an anarchist.” And, precisely in light of his own concerns about the potential abuse of state power, there’s a plausible case to be made for the view that the right sort of constitutional order, the sort capable of fostering prosperity and protecting autonomy, is a polycentric one: market anarchism is the best sort of constitutionalism. It is perfectly possible to argue, building on Buchanan’s own analyses of the behavior of state officials and of the logic of constitutionalism, that the best way to constrain state rapacity is, as a number of Buchanan’s students have argued, by doing without the state altogether.

Buchanan’s elegant and careful analyses were not the last word on public choice or constitutional economics. From a left-wing market anarchist perspective, they were insufficiently critical of the status quo. But they paved the way for more radical analyses of the political and legal order, analyses which will doubtless continue to be enriched by Buchanan’s own.

Feature Articles
Reflections after Sandy Hook: Rampage Killings and Concepts of Liberty

I had intended to write this essay five years ago, in the wake of the Virginia Tech Massacre of April 2007. For various reasons this did not happen, and if it did not happen now it would probably have been only a few years before there was another incident with sufficient prominence in the media to elicit a response from me. And I should expect the general trend of the discourse thereafter to cover the same range of irrelevance and misapprehension.

The most obvious is perhaps merely the illusion of novelty that adheres to all that is ill in the world; that this is a phenomenon of our age and that it is getting worse. This may or may not be so. It is nevertheless surprising that records exist of comparable incidents going back as far as the 18th century. Likewise, and if anything more markedly, these suggest that this is not even a predominantly American or even Western phenomenon, as comparable incidents have occurred in all cultures, at all levels of affluence and technological sophistication.

Nor do these incidents represent a “snapping” or sudden loss of temper upon the day, exacerbated by the presence of firearms at that moment; nor does the heinousness of the deeds reflect a moral deterioration in the perpetrator – except in a tragically oblique way (more on which below) – much less in society as such.

Worst, perhaps, is the refusal even to attempt understanding on the part of some, as if that somehow constituted an offense to the victims; an insistence on ascribing the motivations involved to “evil incarnate,” but evil undefined, ungrasped, and hence unchecked. Surely understanding the nature of the phenomenon would go a long way to preventing similar tragedies in future?

My admittedly cursory investigation led me to an incident in my home town of Cape Town. In 1786 a Javanese Malay convict named Soera Brotto rampaged through the streets of the city, killing seven people and injuring  a further ten. It might be objected that this was an instance of amok, a phenomenon deemed specific to Malay culture; the circumstances nevertheless suggest an existential situation identical to many American rampage killing incidents.

The salient element in Soera Brotto’s story is that it seemed to be the loss of the prospect of returning to Java that had precipitated his rampage. He had been sentenced by the Dutch colonial authorities to banishment to the Cape. Once here he had impressed his captors and was soon promoted. He served the Dutch East India Company for many years as a sort of overseer of slaves and general policeman. But when he learned that his application to return to Java would not be granted, then or ever, he began to collect knives and other weapons and to plan his rampage.

Soera Brotto had been enduring an interruption of his life, wholly absorbed in the prospect of the interruption coming to an end and his life being resumed. He had played the faithful servant for years in order to earn his freedom. He had strained, given years of his life, for that dream. When it was irrevocably lost, his purpose and indeed his life itself were also lost. I believe that this element of irrevocable loss of prospect is a determining feature of many of the rampage killing incidents that achieve notoriety today.

The prospect of living in a future that is chosen and different to how one lives now describes a prospect of liberty at a fundamental level. But it is a testament to the power of nefarious ideas that humans do not recognize in other humans this motivation that is so basic to humanity, so universal. For we are told that the very concept of liberty is a recent Western invention, and more often than not, mere spin and propaganda; that it is wholly absent in the culture and history of other peoples, and that your and my aspiration to selfhood in our own right is therefore anomalous and aberrant, that we ought instead to be content with seamless subsumption in fictitious  collectives.

I take issue with this. I believe that there is an idea of “natural liberty” universal to all people, somewhat analogous to a Thomist conception of natural law. There have indeed been relatively recent emaciations of the idea in the West, but these derive more from obsessions with the natural sciences than from the prior tradition of Western thought. Thus we have liberty conceived as a luxury, a sort of leisure or time off; or as a mechanical concept like a steel ball on a plate of glass, free to roll. The underlying idea of liberty as self-authorship, the right – and indeed the duty – to define, shape, and articulate who and what one is, has become comparatively obscure. The most basic freedom of all is the freedom to ascribe value, to attach importance; but some modern conceptions of liberty ascribe any such attachment to some kind of cock-eyed Gramsciesque idea of “slavery of the mind”.

It might really be anomalous that most people tend immediately to agree that there is no telling what people might do, if they are free. Instead it ought to be obvious that there is no telling what people might do, if people are not free. For if people are not free they have no power of self-authorship, no essential alignment with conviction and principle, no chosen restraint; no capacity to proclaim, “x is important; therefore I  shall not do y”. This is moral agency. Morality is not the corollary of liberty, much less the antithesis; it is the foremost manifestation of liberty.

We are all capable of immense destruction. We count ourselves blessed, if we may live entire lives without manifesting that capability. But it is not the threat of violence or the machinery of control that assures this, but the “law written in [our] hearts” of Jeremiah and St. Paul. Erase that law, and Virginia Tech results. Sandy Hook results.

Rampage killers do not mow down innocent children because they have become convinced that children are evil and ought to be eradicated, or because they blame children for some misfortune or wrong they seek to avenge; nor because they are products of a society in which “life has become cheap;” certainly not because they are unaware that they are not playing a computer game. They mow down innocent children precisely because they are convinced that children are infinitely precious, uniquely vulnerable, and therefore in need of especial protection; precisely because their capacity to hold that moral conviction has been rendered null and void. It has been treated as worthless, reduced to a trifle – and some occurrence has given irreversible effect to this.

Thus rampage killers often specifically choose the most heinous crime possible in the circumstances. Their intention is to demonstrate publicly the result of their moral agency being taken away from them. The message in many of these acts seems to be, “This is what happens when I am not permitted to be responsible for what I am.”

We shall never learn the precise incident which led to the irrevocable loss of moral agency in most of these cases – especially if we do not know what to look for – but the sense of it is palpable in many of them. Something, the death of a dream long held, occurs to make a moral zombie, retaining volition enough to plan a rampage but morally – i.e. in terms of liberty – already dead. For a life can survive the loss of liberty only in so far as it retains the hope that liberty might be regained, as Soera Brotto shows.

And without moral agency the category of moral responsibility cannot apply. Thus the rampage killer can be no more guilty of a crime than the Biblical tower in Siloam, which fell on eighteen people and killed them. Hence the inevitable final suicide arises not from sudden remorse but merely confirms the condition of death.

It should by now be clear that understanding this is socially necessary. Liberty is thus socially necessary; as is a subtler theory of liberty than has often recently prevailed. This is of course not to suggest that most rampage killings are in any way ideologically motivated, but rather that the causes of many of the conditions that lead to rampage killings may be found in the structures of the State. The common element is asymmetrical power relations capable of killing dreams.

As for would-be rampage killers – may we never have occasion to learn who they are – they do not need a firm hand, or disarmament, or medication, or strait-jackets of any kind, nor bread and circuses, whisky and television. What they need is a role in which the exercise of their liberty is required. They need opportunities for real creative liberty, to build their world and to help others to build their world, opportunities increasingly managed and regulated to extinction except for the privileged expert answerable to the powers that be.

Above all, they need hope. Pray that they remain unconvinced that a better world (whatever that might mean in their respective lives) is not possible.

Markets Not Capitalism - YouTube, Stigmergy - C4SS Blog
Charles Johnson’s “Libertarianism Through Thick and Thin” on YouTube

From the Markets Not Capitalism audiobook read by C4SS fellow Stephanie Murphy.

You can help support C4SS by purchasing a zine copy of Charles Johnson’s “Libertarianism Through Thick and Thin“.

Left-Libertarian - Classics
Beyond Patriarchy: A Libertarian Model of the Family

The Family: Friend or Foe?

The family is one of the issues that divide liberals from conservatives. In general, conservatives tend to see private associations — the family, the church, the corporation — as bulwarks of freedom against the state. Few conservatives question the need for a powerful state apparatus, but they insist that it operate in the service of private associations rather than supplant them. Liberals, by contrast, are more likely to see these private associations themselves — family, church, corporation — as threats to autonomy, and to view state intervention as a guarantor of freedom against the oppressive tendencies of private associations. Few liberals seek to abolish such associations, but they do want to subordinate them to the state — just as conservatives want to subordinate the state to the private associations.

This dispute, like so many between the right and the left, is one that libertarians have to sit out. Libertarians agree with conservatives that the state is the chief threat to freedom, and that private associations must be protected from governmental interference. But libertarians are also sensitive to the potential for oppression in private associations, especially when these associations are the beneficiaries of government favoritism. The conservative approach of putting the state in the service of family, church, and corporation simply hands the reins of power to these institutions, which are no more to be trusted with such power than are governmental bureaucracies.

Conservatives see the family as the fundamental unit of society. But for libertarians the fundamental unit is the individual. Hence libertarians have traditionally been ambivalent about the family (as about its kin, the church and the corporation). The family, as a locus of influence and loyalty separate from the state, is certainly something that opponents of centralized power are eager to defend. But on the other hand, libertarians are keenly aware that the family has not always been a sphere of individual freedom, particularly for women and children. How, then, should libertarians think about the family?

The Origin of the Family

In biological terms, the family originates in the need to nurture offspring. The lowest animals often have no families, because they do not need them; they come into the world with a full adult repertoire of survival behavior genetically programmed into them. In many insect and fish species, the parent is either dead or long since absent by the time the young organism hatches. But the learning-to-instinct ratio is higher in more intelligent, more flexible species, and such species therefore need a longer period of childhood. In such species, one or both parents stay with the young until this vulnerable learning period has passed. This is the most primitive form of the family.

This first family is often ephemeral. In many animal species, the family unit dissolves as soon as the young are full-grown; from then on, offspring and former mates are treated in more or less the same way as any other member of one’s species.

But the evolutionary process is resourceful. A trait that initially emerges to meet one need, may then be pressed into service to meet another. There are evolutionary advantages to maintaining a cooperative relationship among family members beyond the point needed to ensure the continuation of the species. And with the highest animals, not only biological evolution but cultural evolution can come into play (e.g., a cat who is raised to regard mice as playmates rather than prey may in turn raise a whole generation of peacenik cats).

Among humans, the family still serves the original function of childrearing, but it has acquired a robust range of new functions as well, serving both the economic and the emotional needs of its members. The family has grown beyond its original biological basis, thus dramatically increasing the number of possible family structures.

A parallel can be made to language. Presumably, language first evolved in order to convey information vital for survival, such as “There’s a sabretooth tiger behind that outcropping” or “Don’t eat those, they’re the mushrooms that made me sick before.” And language still serves that function. But today language also serves a broad range of spiritual needs whose relation to physical survival is tenuous at best. To condemn (as many conservatives do) family relationships that are not for the purpose of childrearing is like condemning Shakespeare’s Hamlet for not telling us where the sabretooth tiger is.

In his book The Psychology of Romantic Love, libertarian psychologist Nathaniel Branden traces the institution of marriage from primitive times to the present. In ancient times, he points out, it was expected that marriage would be based on economic and social considerations, not on love; the phenomenon of romantic love was regarded as an antisocial obsession, an unfortunate madness that people sometimes fell into. In the Middle Ages, marriage for love remained socially impracticable for most, but the literature of the time (in opposition to official Church doctrine) began to celebrate romantic love as one of the highest human experiences, and to portray marriage not based on love as an oppressive institution. But the mediæval romancers were not social revolutionaries; rather than conceiving of a fundamental change in the nature of marriage, they generally portrayed romantic love as glorious but adulterous and tragically doomed. It was the rise of industrial capitalism, Branden argues, that first gave women enough economic independence to postpone marriage, and this greater equality, he says, along with the capitalistic ethic of individualism, is what led to the expectation in present-day society that marriage will ordinarily center on romantic attachment above everything else. To the extent that this change is a good thing, as I think it is, human beings have managed to make out of the sexual pair-bond something superior to what nature originally provided.

Unfortunately, the human intellectual and social skills that allow us to improve on nature, also allow us to do worse than nature. Historically, human families have often been oppressive and exploitative institutions, in a way that animal families do not seem to be. The purest example of this is the Roman family, in which the male head of household (the paterfamilias) was legally entitled to put his wife and children (even grown children) to death. This aspect of family relationships is called patriarchy (“father-rule”), signifying the subordination of wives to husbands and of children to parents. Those who defend patriarchy as “natural” often point to the animal kingdom as a model; but traditionally, parental authority and sexual inequality have been far more pronounced in human societies than in most animal societies. Recent political developments — springing in part from the libertarian urge to subordinate patriarchal authority to individual rights, and in part from the welfare-liberal urge to subordinate patriarchal authority to that of the state — have weakened the institution of patriarchy, but not eliminated it entirely. In her valuable book Justice, Gender, and the Family, Susan Okin points out some of the ways in which contemporary society still systematically reinforces patriarchal family structures. [1] How might families in a truly free society develop beyond this patriarchal paradigm?

Family Structures as Voluntary

As mentioned above, human reliance on learning over instinct allows us to progress beyond the limitations of our genetic programming, thus increasing the number of family structures available to us. Kinship relations and procreative unions, while they will remain one important basis for family structures, are no longer the only such basis. Yet most human societies have laws mandating only certain sorts of family structure, and forbidding others. Conservatives argue that such laws are necessary if society is not to collapse; they see heterosexual monogamy as a prerequisite for a healthy culture, and thus as an institution deserving legal protection. Yet conservatives also see themselves as defenders of the Western cultural tradition originating with the ancient Jews and Greeks, two groups whose commitment to heterosexuality (in the case of the Greeks) and monogamy (in the case of the Jews) is hardly notable; were their cultures defective?

A libertarian legal system would not grant special protection to certain types of family, but would allow any arrangement that was consensual and peaceful. Monogamy or polygamy; heterosexual or homosexual marriage; [2] extended families or nuclear families or single-parent families; [3] group marriages (sexual or nonsexual) — any of these relationships would be permitted. It is a mistake to suppose that there is just one kind of family structure that is right for everybody; and even if there were, it would be a mistake to think we could be justifiably confident that we had found it if we did not allow the discovery process of competition among alternative family structures to operate freely.

Another way in which libertarian society would differ is in the greater variety of marriage contracts that legal institutions would be willing to recognize and enforce. (I say “legal institutions” rather than “the state,” to leave open the possibility of an anarchist society.) There would be some limits here, however; I have argued in previous articles that indentured-servitude contracts are not legitimate on libertarian principles, and the same reasoning would apply to contracts forbidding divorce. Many statists (originally on the right, but they are now being joined by voices on the left) argue that marriage laws should make divorce more difficult, primarily in order to “protect children.” While this might have worked in the days when social mores were different, the result of such legislation if it were implemented today would be, not unhappy couples staying together, but unhappy couples separating without divorce, and moving in with new partners without remarrying. How this would make the children any better off is unclear. (Conservatives say we should try to encourage stable marriages by “restoring the stigma of illegitimacy.” The notion that this would benefit the children involved is still more bizarre.) In any case, the parents as sovereign individuals have the right of free association and disassociation, and to force them to remain in a relationship with someone they no longer love is tyrannical. (I also think the idea that parents should stay in a phony marriage for the sake of the children is immoral, a kind of sacrilege against marriage itself — though of course the parents have the right to make such a decision if they choose.) But, leaving aside no-exit contracts, libertarian legal institutions would respect a greater variety of marriage contracts. Couples who find themselves in a dispute not covered by their contract, or who do not have a contract, may be treated by the courts as if they had signed whatever the “default” contract is in the society — though they can always opt out of any of the provisions of the default contract by making an explicit contract to the contrary.

How would children and women fare, under a libertarian model of family? To this question I now turn.

The Rights of Children

The libertarian ideal is one of independence. Yet we all come into the world as dependent beings, beings who must obey people who in turn must provide us with care. Such a situation seems contrary to libertarian values, yet it is one of the basic facts of our existence; how can libertarianism accommodate the fact of childhood? The parental right to make decisions for one’s child is an exception to the libertarian principle that no one should make decisions for another; the parental duty to provide care for one’s child is an exception to the libertarian principle that no one should be required to provide assistance to another. What justifies these exceptions?

One possible reply is that these exceptions are beneficial. Consider the toddler who starts to wander into traffic, until the parent swoops down and pulls the child back to safety. Hasn’t the parent coerced the child, preventing it from doing what it wanted to do? It seems so. But if the parent hadn’t intervened, the child might have been injured or killed; so it is in the interest of the toddler to be coerced.

No doubt it is; but can this be what justifies parental authority? After all, libertarians generally reject the paternalistic notion of coercing people in order to benefit them, and argue instead that people have the right to make their own mistakes. Why doesn’t this apply to children? If we allow adults to engage in risky behavior like bungee jumping or mountain climbing or engaging in unprotected sex, why not allow toddlers to engage in risky behavior like walking into traffic or drinking Clorox?

Some libertarians have concluded that the anti-paternalist argument does indeed apply to children, and maintain that it is wrong to restrain children in any way as long as the children aren’t hurting anybody else; such libertarians maintain that children should have full rights to sign contracts or have sex with adults. Reacting against this, other libertarians have gone to the opposite extreme, holding that children are their parents’ property and that parents may do with them as they please. Most libertarians take an intermediate position, regarding parents neither as the equals nor the owners of their children, but rather as their guardians, entitled to make decisions for them and obligated to provide for their welfare. This is surely the commonsensical position; but does it constitute a departure from strict libertarianism?

I don’t think so. In my view, what justifies paternalistic treatment of children is not simply that such treatment benefits children (it might benefit foolish adults as well), but rather that children lack the capacity to make rational decisions about their lives (whereas foolish adults may have that capacity even if they don’t use it much). Consider the analogy of a person in a coma; we make medical decisions for such persons without their consent, because we assume they would consent if they were able to do so. If a person in a coma has left instructions not to use certain kinds of treatment, then most libertarians will agree that we should refrain from using them. So this is not a case of paternalistically overriding someone’s will, but rather of acting as an agent for someone currently unable to exercise his will. We can also extend the analysis to cases where the capacity for rational decision-making is not completely blocked (as in the case of an unconscious person), but simply diminished, as with persons who are drugged or delirious or mentally impaired. I suggest that children may be considered as instances of diminished capacity; guardians act as agents for children, treating the children as they judge the children would consent to be treated if their faculties were fully developed. The standard that justifies paternalism is not benefit but counterfactual consent; the two are different because a person with fully developed faculties can still fail to use them and so make dumb decisions.

This helps to explain why the rights and responsibilities of guardianship go together in the way that they do. Specifically, guardianship is a bundle of one right (the right to make decisions about what happens to the child) and one responsibility (the duty to care for the child’s welfare). These come as a unit because it is only when the decisions we make are those that the impaired person would consent to if unimpaired (as far as we can determine) that we are justified in acting as an agent and substituting our judgment for his.

The fact that the guardian-ward relationship depends on diminished capacity has an important implication for children’s rights. Diminished capacity is a matter of degree; a 13-year-old’s capacity for rational decision-making is not as impaired as a 4-year-old’s, which in turn is not as impaired as a newborn’s. So it is unrealistic to have an absolute cut-off age, below which a child is completely under his guardian’s authority (and unable to engage in any binding financial transactions, from buying a house to buying a pack of gum) and above which he is suddenly a fully responsible agent. The older a child is, the stronger the presumption becomes that a child’s expressed will is an accurate reflection of the will he would have if unimpaired. So, for example, a teenager’s desire to have an ear pierced has to be given more weight than a toddler’s desire to have an ear pierced; and a rational capacity that is not up to giving informed consent in the case of purchasing a house may be quite up to the task of purchasing gum. These sorts of grey areas could probably be handled better by evolving court precedents than by statutory fiat.

I have said that the standard for how a child should be treated is not the child’s benefit, but rather that to which the child would consent if its rational faculties were not impaired — a standard that will presumably track fairly closely with the child’s welfare, but will not match it entirely, especially as the child grows older. (For example, we may think little Nemo would be better off as a stockbroker than as a sidewalk artist, but if all the evidence suggests that Nemo is overwhelmingly likely to choose sidewalk art as his career when he is an adult, then we are not justified in forcing him to go to stockbrokers’ camp, if there is such a thing.) But of course, what the child is likely to consent to retroactively, as an adult, is to a large extent (though not completely) determined by decisions made by the parents in early childhood. In other words, if you were raised a Muslim you will probably look back later and say, “I’m glad I was raised a Muslim”; but if you were not raised a Muslim, then you’ll probably be glad you weren’t. In cases where the child’s likely future preferences are being shaped by present treatment, how do we then turn around and use those likely future preferences as a standard by which to evaluate that present treatment?

This is a difficult case. On the one hand, libertarians generally want to say that the parent is in a better position than anyone else to decide, e.g., which religion a child should be raised in, and this is a matter in which outsiders representing the child’s interests should not interfere, even if we think being raised in one religion is objectively better for the child than being raised in another. On the other hand, when it comes to abusive procedures like female genital mutilation (popularly known by the euphemism “female circumcision,” falsely conveying the impression of being comparable in seriousness to male circumcision), we generally think parents do not have the right to do this, even though women who have had this procedure done when young will usually endorse it in retrospect when they are grown, because they have been inculcated with the relevant cultural attitudes and values. (Cases like Christian Scientists and Jehovah’s Witnesses denying their children medical care seem to come somewhere in between.)[4] Neither the benefit standard nor the counterfactual-consent standard gives precisely the answers we want in such cases, which suggests that I may need to do more tinkering with my theory and somehow incorporate aspects of the benefit standard into the counterfactual-consent standard, without doing so in such a way as to justify a like paternalism toward adults. I haven’t fully figured out how to do this, but perhaps something along the following lines would work: when we consider the child’s likely future preferences, those preferences include both a generic preference for being benefited, and a (possibly mistaken) specific preference for particular treatment regarded as beneficial. Since these preferences are non-actual, we cannot treat one as more expressive of the child’s will than another (whereas once the child is grown and acts on the latter preference, that does give it priority over the former one). So the guardian is obligated to balance the generic desire to be benefited (which requires the guardian to provide what is actually beneficial) with the specific desire for whatever the child is likely to regard, in the future, as having been beneficial. So the more harmful a particular treatment actually is, the more weight the case for abstaining from that treatment has against the contrary weight that the child will end up endorsing it when grown.

How are guardianships acquired? Presumably in the same way as other property rights: by homesteading or transfer. The simplest way to homestead a guardianship would be finding an abandoned infant and undertaking to provide care for it. Another way to homestead guardianship of a child is to give birth to the child; the mother starts out as the child’s guardian, a position to which no one else (not even the father) can have a claim unless the mother grants it. (I do not think an expectant mother could grant guardianship rights in advance, by contract, for the same reason one cannot sell one’s blood before it has been removed from one’s body; one cannot alienate a possession that is still incorporated into oneself.) [5] One can also obtain a guardianship by gift or sale from someone else who relinquishes it (i.e., adoption).

The fact that what is owned is guardianship over a child, rather than simply the child itself, places restrictions on how one can get rid of a guardianship. As long as one has the guardianship, one is required to use it in ways consistent with the child’s welfare, and so (since renouncing guardianship is itself an exercise of guardianship) one cannot renounce guardianship by throwing the baby in a trash bin or selling it to someone you know plans to cook and eat it. By analogy, if you rescue a comatose patient from a hospital fire, you cannot renounce your guardianship duties by dumping your patient in a river, but must convey the patient to another hospital.

The Status of Women

Libertarians have an uneasy relationship with feminism. Many endorse Christina Sommers’ distinction between “liberal feminism” and “gender feminism.” Liberal feminists, Sommers says, are concerned with legal equality, i.e., with ensuring that men and women have the same rights before the law, while gender feminists go beyond this and assert that sexual inequality pervades every aspect of society, and that a mere equality before the law is insufficient to redress this problem. Sommers’ distinction, and her preference for liberal feminism over gender feminism, is shared by many in the libertarian community.

Libertarian feminist Wendy McElroy offers a more subtle analysis [6] in the introduction to her book Freedom, Feminism, and the State. There she distinguishes not two but three kinds of feminism. First there is “mainstream feminism,” which simply seeks to include women equally with men in whatever the existing legal status quo is. If there are male Senators, there should also be female Senators; if males can be drafted into the army or compulsory labor camps, so should females; and so on. This position is contrasted with what McElroy calls “radical feminism,” which sees sexual equality as a symptom of a deeper inequality that pervades society as a whole and is inherent in the status quo (so that mere inclusion in the status quo won’t do). There are, says McElroy, two kinds of radical feminism: “socialist feminism,” which sees socioeconomic inequality as the culprit, and individualist (i.e., libertarian) feminism, which regards the problem as stemming from political inequality (where by “political inequality” McElroy means any coercive subordination of one person to another person’s will — statism being the paradigm case of political inequality).

McElroy’s distinction is better than Sommers’, because Sommers would lump mainstream feminists and individualist feminists together into the single camp of liberal feminism, ignoring the important differences between them. But even McElroy’s distinction, it seems to me, does not go far enough. McElroy seems to believe that it is un-libertarian to care about socioeconomic differences between men and women, except to the extent that those differences are the result of coercive state action. Now it is true that libertarian feminists should avoid seeking governmental solutions to such inequalities, but that is not to say they should not regard such inequalities as undesirable, and in need of some sort of (non-governmental) solution. Surely the so-called “gender feminists” are right to point out that undesirable sexual inequalities are extremely pervasive in our society.

As Susan Okin points out in the book I mentioned above, most political theories (and this is certainly true of libertarianism) tend to assume as their subject-matter a mature agent who has been raised by someone else’s labor, usually female labor. The employment conditions in our society (working hours, structure of leaves and benefits, etc.) also seem to be designed with the assumption that the worker has a wife at home, even when the worker is female. Women still do the majority of unpaid household labor, even when they are working, and tend to put their husbands’ careers ahead of their own; as a result, if the marriage breaks up it is the man, not the woman, who is best prepared to prosper on the job market.[7] Okin argues that this fact gives the husband disproportionate power in the relationship, since he has less to lose by exiting. (Okin also points out ways in which existing marriage laws exacerbate this situation; her chapter “Vulnerability by Marriage” is one that libertarian judges and legislators might well read with profit.) In addition, Okin emphasizes that the family is the first school of morality, that is, it is the first context in which people learn about appropriate interpersonal behavior, and if the family is characterized by one-sided exploitative relationships, it will not produce the sort of citizens who can be relied upon to maintain a just society.

I think Okin’s concerns are important ones. Okin’s own solutions, of course, are coercive and statist in nature; but we need not dismiss her account of the problems simply because we doubt both the morality and the utility of her solutions.

A libertarian society would not automatically solve all the problems Okin mentions; cultural biases can survive even without governmental support. However, the absence of such support does weaken the effectiveness of those biases, thus making it easier to combat them through voluntary means, if only we undertake to do so. In particular, the explosion of prosperity that a libertarian society would see, would go a long way toward providing women with an economic safety net more effective than any government welfare program. (One possibility is that women could form mutual-support networks of a kind that today’s governmental regulations would render impossible.) And I have discussed in previous articles why competition would tend to undermine the impact of sexist bias in the marketplace.

I want to close by saying a bit about the issue of spousal abuse, one of the ugliest remnants of patriarchy in the modern family. How should a libertarian legal system handle this problem? Today, our predominantly male (and often macho-oriented) police force is well-known for not being particularly helpful at addressing this question. Tracy Chapman’s song “Behind the Wall” (from the album Tracy Chapman) expresses a familiar complaint:

Last night I heard the screaming
loud voices behind the wall
another sleepless night for me
it won’t do no good to call
the police always come late
if they come at all

and when they arrive
they say they can’t interfere
with domestic affairs
between a man and his wife
and as they walk out the door
the tears well up in her eyes

last night I heard the screaming
then a silence that chilled my soul
I prayed that I was dreaming
when I saw the ambulance in the road

and the policeman said
I’m here to keep the peace
will the crowd disperse
I think we all could use some sleep

Could the fact that current police forces enjoy a coercive monopoly on the provision of security within their respective territories have anything to do with this situation? Imagine a scenario in which different kinds of police agencies, specializing in different kinds of problem, could compete on the open market. A feminist police agency (perhaps a mutual-support network, perhaps a fee-for-service business, perhaps a nonprofit organization depending on charitable contributions, perhaps some combination of the above) would most likely be far more sensitive and responsive to issues of spousal abuse than are present-day police agencies. A wife batterer might have to contend with three feminists armed with Uzis showing up on his doorstep to investigate. (In this connection, remember that gun control (which would not exist in a free nation) is one of the most effective tools of patriarchy, since it favors those with greater physical strength; widespread gun ownership and training undermine female vulnerability to male violence by compensating for average strength differences between men and women.)

A related issue is that of self-defense against spousal abuse. In a number of recent cases, a woman has killed or maimed her abusive husband because she feared a continuation of abuse, even though he was not abusing her at the precise moment she attacked him. Our legal system tends to treat these women as criminals, on the grounds that violent self-defense is justified only when the threat is immediate (except when it’s government that is doing the defending, at which point the criteria for justifiable pre-emptive violence seem to become extremely lax). The argument is that an abused woman should flee the home rather than staying and assaulting her abuser. But why should she have to leave her own home, simply because it is also the abuser’s home? Even our degraded legal system generally recognizes that one has no duty to retreat from an attacker when one is in one’s own home. If you are the victim of a persistent pattern of severe rights-violations, a pattern you have every reason to expect will continue, and if external authorities offer no reliable protection, it seems to me that you are justified in undertaking your own defense, and that a libertarian court should recognize this. A competitive legal system would allow women’s perspectives a greater voice in deciding the treatment of such cases than is possible under our monopolistic system.

Beyond Patriarchy

Conservatives are right: the family is an institution of paramount value and importance, both in its own right and as a bulwark against the encroachments of the state. Liberals are also right: the family has often served as a sphere of oppression and exploitation, thanks to the tradition of patriarchy, in which women are unjustly subordinated to men, and children are unjustly subordinated to parents. The proper libertarian response to both concerns is to see how, consistent with our anti-interventionist principles, we can foster a family structure free of patriarchal influence.

In the case of parents and children, this means recognizing that in deciding how to treat their children, parents must attempt to track not just the child’s welfare but also what the child is likely (once mature) to prefer; since a child’s expressed preferences become a more and more accurate guide to its mature preferences as time passes, this means that parents have less and less justification, as their child grows older, for imposing on it their own conceptions of benefit when these clash with the child’s. This model of the parent-child relationship is thus anti-patriarchal, in that it gives children a greater right to a say in their own treatment than the benefit standard does, while at the same time recognizing enough distance between expressed and mature preferences to avoid the extreme consequences of “kid lib.”

In the case of husbands and wives, going beyond patriarchy means seeking to foster both a work environment and a home environment that do not systematically disadvantage women in relation to men. In the economic sphere, this involves removing regulatory barriers to competition, thus giving employees generally, including women, more clout in the job market, thus putting them in a better position to negotiate for higher pay, parental leave, and the like (which the employers, also benefiting from the economic boom that freedom would bring, would be in a better position to provide). In the legal sphere, it involves abolishing laws that discriminate against women, and more importantly, opening up the services of adjudication and enforcement to competition so that the concerns of women could be more adequately represented. And in the cultural sphere, it involves inculcating an attitude of reciprocity and mutual respect.

Some libertarians may say that we don’t need this last aspect: if there is any serious problem, the market will take care of it, so we don’t need to do any cultivating. I think this attitude is a mistake, and tends to encourage discriminatory attitudes (if the market hasn’t taken care of it, then it must not be a serious problem; e.g., if women aren’t making as much money as men on the market, it must be their own fault). Libertarians are often reluctant to recognize entrenched power structures when they don’t come attached to governmental offices; but we should always remember that power and tyranny are older than the state. Indeed, Herbert Spencer intriguingly suggests (in his Principles of Sociology) that the subordination of women by men is the initial form of oppression from which all later ones grew, including the state. We should also remember, when we say “the market will take care of it,” that we are the market, that its successful operation depends on the alertness of Kirznerian entrepreneurs, and that we who have noticed a problem are in the best position to fill that entrepreneurial role. Stressing the Hayekian strand within Austrian socioeconomic thought at the expense of the Kirznerian strand can lead to excessive passivity in the face of the omniscient, omnipotent forces of history.

Translations for this article:

Notes:

[1] Susan Moller Okin, Justice, Gender, and the Family (New York: Basic Books, 1989). This book has gotten something of a bad press among libertarians, first because of its bizarre attack on libertarianism, and second because of Okin’s own rather socialistic policy proposals. It is true that Okin tends to misunderstand and misrepresent the positions of her opponents, and her chapter on libertarianism is particularly egregious in this regard; it is also true that her policy proposals would be a statist nightmare if enacted. Nevertheless, I think there is a great deal of value in her book that libertarians need to consider carefully.

[2] The argument is sometimes made that even if homosexual relationships should be permitted, they should not be called “marriage,” because marriage has historically been a relationship between men and women. But by that logic, contemporary heterosexual relationships should not count as marriages either. After all, marriage has historically involved the wife’s legal absorption into and subordination to her husband, so one could argue that no relationship between equals should be considered a marriage. (In fact, this is exactly what many 19th-century “free love” advocates did; the free-love movement’s antagonism toward marriage was not (in most cases) an endorsement of promiscuity, but rather a hostility to what they saw as an inherently one-sided and exploitative relationship.) But I think this would be a mistake; the nature of marriage is not inherently determined by the particular form it takes in a given society. Marriage and the family are historical phenomena, and cannot be defined in separation from the way they develop over time.

[3] Single-parent families are currently under attack from conservatives, who cite statistics showing that children from two-parent homes tend to do better than those from one-parent homes. One question that is seldom asked is how much of this difference derives from an inherent advantage of two parents over one, and how much instead from the economic hardship and reduced parent-child time that a (politically manufactured) low-wage economy imposes on single-parent families?

[4] Actually, the two cases are somewhat different. As I understand it, Jehovah’s Witnesses simply refuse certain kinds of medical treatments on religious grounds, without offering alternative treatment, arguing that the child is better off dead than alive but damned. Christian Scientists, by contrast, treat their children by means of spiritual healing, a method that has an impressive success rate but many unexplained failures, just as mainstream medicine has an impressive success rate but many unexplained failures; so disputes over Christian Science treatment for children have more to do with the medical profession’s claiming a government-sanctioned monopoly in the field of health care than with issues of child neglect and so forth.

[5] This raises the complicated issue of surrogacy contracts. One side wants to enforce them, the other side to forbid them. As I see it, the correct position is that specific performance should not be enforceable (because an expectant mother cannot alienate guardianship rights while the child is still in her body), but money damages should be enforceable.

[6] At least, she once did. In more recent writings, however, she unfortunately seems to have adopted Sommers’ terminology.

[7] Okin cites statistics showing that after divorce, the average man’s economic position improves while the average woman’s declines. Since she wrote her book, the particular study on which she relied has been discredited; but this shows only that the post-divorce difference is less extreme than Okin supposed, not that it is insignificant.

Distro of the Libertarian Left
Support C4SS with Benjamin Tucker’s “Market Anarchy Vs. Corporate Power”

C4SS has teamed up with the Distro of the Libertarian Left. The Distro produces and distribute zines and booklets on anarchism, market anarchist theory, counter-economics, and other movements for liberation. For every copy of Benjamin Tucker’s “Market Anarchy Vs. Corporate Power” that you purchase through the Distro, C4SS will receive a percentage. Support C4SS with Benjamin Tucker’s “Market Anarchy Vs. Corporate Power“.

$1.00 for the first copy. $0.75 for every additional copy.

The classic Market Anarchist take on corporate power and the political privileges that prop it up — Benjamin Tucker’s talk at the Conference on Trusts by the Chicago Civic Federation in September 1899.

The trusts, instead of growing out of competition, as is so generally supposed, have been made possible only by the absence of competition, only by the difficulty of competition, only by the obstacles placed in the way of competition . . . by those arbitrary limitations of competition which we find in those law ­created privileges and monopolies . . . . The trusts owe their power to vast accumulation and concentration of wealth . . . But for interest, rent, and monopolistic profit . . . trusts would be impossible. Now, what causes interest, rent, and monopolistic profit? For all there is but one cause, — the denial of liberty, the suppression or restriction of competition, the legal creation of monopolies. . . .

Free access to the world of matter, abolishing land monopoly; free access to the world of mind, abolishing idea monopoly; free access to an untaxed and unprivileged market, abolishing tariff monopoly and money monopoly, — secure these, and all the rest shall be added unto you. For liberty is the remedy of every social evil, and to Anarchy the world must look at last for any enduring guarantee of social order.

Media Appearances, Stigmergy - C4SS Blog
Advocates of Freed Markets Should Oppose Capitalism

C4SS Media would like to present one of our signature political position pieces, from C4SS Senior Fellow Gary Chartier:

“Defenders of freed markets have good reason to identify their position as a species of ‘anti-capitalism.’ To explain why, I distinguish three potential meanings of ‘capitalism’ before suggesting that people committed to freed markets should oppose capitalism in my second and third senses. Then, I offer some reasons for using ‘capitalism’ as a label for some of the social arrangements to which freed-market advocates should object.” —Gary Chartier

A ready for print version.

Portuguese, Stateless Embassies
Acabem com a Guerra Dentro do País, Acabem com a Guerra no Exterior

The following article is translated into Portuguese from the English original, written by Nathan Goodman.

De acordo com a Tribuna de Salt Lake, às 2:30 da madrugada de 20 de dezembro Eric Hill foi acordado por sua amedrontada filha, que havia ouvido batidas perto do guarda-roupa dela. Em seguida ele ouviu batidas fortes na porta da frente.

Amedrontado com a perspectiva de invasão de sua casa ou arrombamento, Hill armou-se com um taco de beisebol e abriu a porta. Seis homens de preto, armados com rifles de assalto e armas táticas, ordenaram-lhe que deixasse cair o taco e algemaram-no. Um dos homens disse que se Eric estivesse empunhando uma arma de fogo em vez de um taco, eles o teriam  “fuzilado.”

Vários daqueles homens entraram na casa de Hill empunhando suas armas, amedrontando a mulher dele, Melanie Hill, e os filhos deles. Eric Hill declarou: “Depois dos disparos [de Newtown, Conn.] que haviam acontecido havia pouco, meu filho [mais velho] já estava com medo de ir à escola,” e que seus filhos “estão simplesmente traumatizados com isso.”

Os invasores da casa que traumatizaram os filhos de Hill eram do Departamento de Polícia de Ogden. No entanto, Hill não estava sendo procurado por nenhum crime. Ele fora confundido com outro homem, acusado de “deserção” da instituição militar.

Além da específica incompetência da polícia que esse incidente reflete, o fato diz-nos muito acerca da militarização da polícia. Perseguindo um suspeito acusado de ofensa não violenta, a polícia se armou com múltiplos rifles de assalto e armas táticas e optou por invadir um lar no meio da noite. Declarou sua disposição de matar qualquer pessoa que empunhasse uma arma de fogo para defender seu lar de tal incursão. E essa foi a polícia de Utah, onde propriedade de armas é comum.

Essa não foi a primeira incursão militarizada levada a efeito pela polícia de Ogden a ganhar o noticiário da mídia. Em 2010, o residente de Ogden Todd Blair foi morto numa incursão a propósito de drogas em seu lar. A Tribuna de Salt Lake informou à época que “Os disparos foram considerados legalmente justificáveis.” Matthew Stewart foi sujeitado a incursão similar no meio da noite no início de 2012, mas teria disparado contra os invasores da casa. Está há meses na prisão e enfrenta acusações de assassínio. O promotor, Dee Smith, busca a pena de morte. Smith é também o encarregado de investigar disparos feitos pela polícia, e até hoje não considerou nenhum disparo injustificável.

A militarização das forças policiais estadunidenses é uma tendência nacional, levada a efeito em concerto com o resto do estado beligerante. Radley Balko escreve que “Diversas polícias federais têm estimulado essa tendência, inclusive oferecendo a departamentos da polícia no país treinamento militar, permitindo treinamento junto a organizações militares, usando programas “contratação de veteranos de guerra como policiais” e oferecendo equipamento e armamento militar excedente  a departamentos de polícia no país de graça ou com grandes descontos.” Já há anos a guerra no exterior vem chegando ao país, com a polícia atuando menos como “autoridades da paz” e mais como soldados.

Entretanto, o recente incidente com Eric Hill torna mais óbvia a conexão entre a militarização da polícia dentro do país e o militarismo estadunidense no exterior. A polícia fez incursão no lar de Hill no meio da noite e traumatizou sua família porque o confundiu com um homem que alegadamente decidira parar de trabalhar para a instituição militar dos Estados Unidos.

Em qualquer emprego comum, quando você não comparece o chefe não manda homens com armas de fogo prender você. Entretanto, se você resolver parar de trabalhar para a instituição militar, a polícia armada aparecerá com armas de fogo disparando para punir você. A instituição militar dos Estados Unidos é uma instituição que espalha violência no exterior impunemente. Seus aviões não tripulados bombardeiam funerais e equipes de salvamento no Paquistão e despejam bombas de fragmentação no Iêmen. Suas tropas ocupam, torturam e matam no Iraque e no Afeganistão. A instituição militar dos Estados Unidos promove violência até em Honduras e Guatemala atualmente. Isso significa que Eric Hill foi atacado pela polícia não por ser suspeito de estar cometendo violência agressora, e sim por ser suspeito de recusar-se a cometer violência agressora.

A mensagem parece ser: Se você não conseguir participar de violência no exterior, o estado sujeitará você a violência dentro do país.

É hora de acabar com as guerras, tanto dentro do país quanto no exterior.

Artigo original afixado por Nathan Goodman em 31 de dezembro de 2012.

Traduzido do inglês por Murilo Otávio Rodrigues Paes Leme.

Distro of the Libertarian Left
Support C4SS with Lysander Spooner’s “A Plan for the Abolition of Slavery”

C4SS has teamed up with the Distro of the Libertarian Left. The Distro produces and distribute zines and booklets on anarchism, market anarchist theory, counter-economics, and other movements for liberation. For every copy of Lysander Spooner’s “A Plan for the Abolition of Slavery” that you purchase through the Distro, C4SS will receive a percentage. Support C4SS with Lysander Spooner’s “A Plan for the Abolition of Slavery“.

$2.00 for the first copy. $1.50 for every additional copy.

“The state of Slavery is a state of war. . .”

This rare, incendiary classic of radical Abolitionism, printed at Boston in 1858, was circulated in secret by the Abolitionist lawyer and radical libertarian, Lysander Spooner (1808-1887), later the author of No Treason, the “Letter to Bayard,” and “Vices Are Not Crimes.” Spooner defended the natural right of revolution against slaveholders and detailed a plan to destroy the slave system by overturning Southern society from the bottom up: emancipation brought about not by government wars, invasions or occupations; and not by legislative authority and political compromises; but with power taken into the hands of slaves themselves rising up to defend themselves from enslavement, free themselves of masters, claim the land and the fruits of their forced labor, and destroy the slave system by rendering the South ungovernable by the slavemasters.

“It is only those who have a false and superstitious reverence for the authority of governments, and have contracted the habit of thinking that the most tyrannical and iniquitous laws have the power to make that right which is naturally wrong, or that wrong which is naturally right, who will have any doubt as to the right of the Slaves (and those who would assist them) to make war, to all possible extent, upon the property of the Slaveholders and their abettors. . . .Make slavery unprofitable, in this way, if it can be done in no other. . . .” — Anonymous.

The “Plan” called on abolitionists and non-slaveholders to declare their support for uprisings and campaigns of sabotage against slaveholders and pro-slavery governments, guerrilla militias uniting enslaved blacks with poor Southern whites, and solidarity from Northern Abolitionists to provide aid to fugitive slaves, local slave uprisings and free maroon communities.

“We specially advise the flogging of individual Slaveholders. . . .” — Anonymous.

Originally published as a two page, anonymous circular in the radical abolitionist underground, only about 200 copies were ever printed. Spooner himself withdrew the circular at the request of John Brown — who feared that the appeal might tip off the government to his own plans for the raid on Harper’s Ferry the next year.

Dutch, Stateless Embassies
Sociaaldemocratie: “Socialisme” met een bulk aan overhead

The following article is translated into Dutch from the English original, written by Kevin Carson.

Ongeveer een eeuw geleden betoogde G.D.H. Cole dat de sociaaldemocraten een belangrijke strategische keuze maakten door de verdeling van eigendom en de organisatie van productie onder het kapitalisme niet langer te bestrijden. In plaats daarvan zouden zij in het vervolg hun tijd gaan besteden aan het nivelleren van de verschillende manieren waarop de winsten van dit systeem werden verdeeld.

Doorslaggevende factor bij het maken van deze keuze was het feit dat de bestrijding van het verdeeld eigendom politiek onhaalbaar zou zijn. Bijkomende factor die Cole beredeneerde, kwam erop neer dat het oorspronkelijk socialistisch project – met als uitgangspunt de aanval op de institutionele structuren van het kapitalisme en het centraal stellen van de arbeiders binnen het productieproces – de kracht van leidinggevende en professionele klassen binnen de sociaaldemocratische en progressieve bewegingen zou ondermijnen.

Verschillende denkers – van Hilaire Belloc tot William English Walling – stelden dat dergelijke overwegingen zouden resulteren in een strategische overeenkomst waarbij voor de kapitalisten minimale inkomsten en kleine markten zeker werden gesteld, dat de professioneel-leidinggevende klasse haar positie binnen de organisaties die de samenleving beheersten kon behouden, en de werkende klasse van een baan en een verzorgingssysteem werden verzekerd. De leidinggevende klasse werd onderdeel van het staatskapitalisme met als functie: Managers van de Armen.

Het sociaaldemocratisch model houdt de basisstructuren van het kapitalisme in stand – terwijl het iedereen toegang biedt tot een minimaal aandeel in de opbrengst.

Wanneer sociaaldemocraten of progressieven zeggen dat het een of ander – zorg, onderwijs, etc. – een ‘mensenrecht’ is, dan bedoelen zij eigenlijk dat de dienst georganiseerd moet blijven onder het oude institutionele model: hoge overhead, autoritair, hiërarchisch, bureaucratisch, inefficiënt en onder leiding van een technocratisch genootschap. Maar alle burgers, zelfs de allerarmsten onder hen, zullen toegang hebben tot de dienst of het product.

Bijgevolg zijn wij opgezadeld met een openbaar onderwijssysteem dat door Ivan Illich en John Taylor Gatto wordt beschreven als een proces waardoor menselijk kapitaal wordt geraffineerd tot menselijke middelen voor commerciële werknemers – maar de student kan er zoveel van ontvangen als deze wil, zelfs gratis, en aan universeel beschikbare universiteiten en hogescholen. We zijn opgezadeld met een zorgsysteem waarin artsen een zeer bovenmodaal inkomen wordt gegarandeerd d.m.v. patenten – maar je krijgt wel (bijna) gratis zorg.

Het probleem is dat dit hoge-overhead model – ook al is het ‘gratis’ in de zin dat je niet betaalt voor directe dienstverlening – indirect zwaar weegt op werknemers vanwege de noodzakelijke heffing van een hoge algemene belasting. Ook al is de werkweek veel korter en zijn de vakanties langer voor West-Europeanen dan voor Amerikanen, deze is nog altijd veel langer dan die zou kunnen zijn wanneer onnodige kosten weggesneden zouden worden door het elimineren van het door de overheid gesteunde monopolie waarop het huidige kapitalisme rust.

Ziehier de donkere kant van het recht op ‘gratis’ diensten: op de een of andere manier zijn deze tegelijkertijd vaak verplicht. Technologische vooruitgang heeft geleid tot het drastisch verlagen van het vereiste kapitaal, opleidingsniveau en de noodzakelijke manuren om een product te maken, maar nog altijd garandeert de overheid desondanks volledige teruggave op het geïnvesteerde kapitaal, alsmede een stabiel inkomen voor de professioneel geschoolde klasse en een complete werkweek voor de arbeider. Zodoende wordt schaarste op kunstmatige wijze gehandhaafd. Technologie met als doel schaarste te bestrijden, wordt gezien als een bedreiging en vervolgens geneutraliseerd door deze illegaal te verklaren of producenten een monopolie op deze technologieën te garanderen

Hoe meer diensten zoals onderwijs gratis worden, des temeer deze worden verplicht. Gratis, universeel beschikbaar hoger onderwijs leidt tot een inflatie in vergunningen, papieren en cursussen die verplicht worden gesteld om zelfs maar een basis beroep te kunnen en mogen uitoefenen. Het versterkt de institutionele band tussen universiteitsbewindvoerders en commerciële human resource afdelingen, en versterkt eveneens het toezicht van licentie-kartels op de uitoefening van een beroep. Derhalve staat de overheid onder een constante druk om commerciële, coöperatieve en andere – lees: alternatieve – zelf-georganiseerde verbanden door zowel particulieren als door bedrijven op het gebied van onderwijs, zorg en voeding met kracht te onderdrukken. Uiteraard worden dergelijke regelingen steevast verkocht alsof zij de consument zouden beschermen – maar zeker niet omdat zij in werkelijkheid de farmaceutische bedrijven en licentie-kartels beschermen tegen lagere inkomsten.

Als waarachtig vrije markt libertarier, wil ik dat de werknemer de volledige vrucht van zijn arbeid ontvangt, zonder geld te hoeven afdragen aan grootgrondbezitters, woekeraars of eigenaren van kunstmatig eigendom zoals patenten, copyrights en licenties. Ik wil dat eerlijke concurrentie de prijs van producten naar beneden drijft, opdat de marktwaarde hetzelfde wordt als de kosten van productie, zonder kunstmatige schaarste welke wordt gecreëerd door de overheid, en zonder daarmee technologische vooruitgang te degraderen tot bron van rent-seeking waardoor deze creativiteit wordt afgeremd danwel buiten bereik gehouden. Ik wil dat de gemiddelde werkweek een reële afspiegeling wordt van de hoeveelheid tijd die nodig is om een levensvergoeding te produceren, zonder dat we gesubsidieerde rent-seekers de kaas van ons brood laten eten.

Dit alles betekent heel concreet: als vrije markt libertarier, ben ik – in tegenstelling tot sociaaldemocraten en progressieven – een waarachtig socialist.

Originele artikel geplaatst op 28 December 2012 door Kevin Carson
Vertaald vanuit het Engels door: Christiaan Elderhorst

Center Updates, Stigmergy - C4SS Blog
The State is Damage, Time to Find a Route Around

For more than a year and a half, C4SS has been maintaining a Tor relay node with a freedom friendly data center in the Netherlands. The relay is part of a global network dedicated to the idea that a free society requires freedom of information. Since June 2011 C4SS has continuously added nearly 10 Mbps of bandwidth to the network (statistics).

Although we can’t know, by design, what’s passed through the relay, it’s entirely likely that it has facilitated communications by revolutionaries, agorists, whistleblowers, journalists working under censorious regimes and many more striving to advance the cause of liberty.

Operating the node does come at a cost. Just under $150 of hosting will cover the relay for the next six months.

If you believe, as we do, that Tor is one of the technologies that’s serving to make both state and corporate oppression not only obsolete, but impossibleplease click through and contribute today.

The State is damage, liberty will route around!

All the best,
-C4SS

P.S. The hardcore can send bitcoins to 1DnumwHUq1uGp1c4sRasbXipvkMNsy7ixg.

Portuguese, Stateless Embassies
Esquerda Libertária: Anticapitalismo de livre mercado, o ideal desconhecido

The following article is translated into Portuguese from the English original, written by Sheldon Richman.

A campanha presidencial de Ron Paul de 2008 deu a conhecer a muitas pessoas a palavra “libertário.” Como Paul é Republicano e os Republicanos, do mesmo modo que os libertários, usam a retórica dos livres mercados e da empresa privada, as pessoas naturalmente assumem que os libertários são algum tipo de rebento peculiar da direita estadunidense. Na verdade, algumas posições libertárias encaixam-se mal no conservadorismo convencional — completa descriminação das drogas, casamento legal entre pessoas do mesmo sexo, e crítica do estado de segurança nacional alienam muitas pessoas da direita do libertarismo.

Nada obstante, a cepa dominante do libertarismo ainda parece à vontade naquele lado do espectro político. Loas aos direitos de propriedade e à livre empresa — a convicção libertária convencional de que o sistema capitalista estadunidense, a despeito de intervenção do governo, encarna fundamentalmente esses valores — parece justificar essa conclusão.

Em seguida, porém, surgem passagens como esta: “O capitalismo, surgindo como nova sociedade de classes diretamente da antiga sociedade de classes da Idade Média, foi fundado num ato de roubo tão maciço quanto a mais precoce conquista feudal da terra. Tem sido sustentado, até o presente, por contínua intervenção do estado na proteção de seu sistema de privilégio sem o qual sua sobrevivência é inimaginável.” E esta: “construir solidariedade entre os trabalhadores. De um lado, isso significa organização formal, inclusive sindicalização — mas não estou falando do modelo prevalente de ‘sindicatos de empresas’ … e sim de sindicatosreais, à moda antiga, comprometidos com a classetrabalhadora e não apenas com membros do sindicato, e interessados em autonomia dos trabalhadores, não em patrocínio do governo.”

Essas passagens — a primeira do erudito independente Kevin Carson, a segunda do professor de filosofia da Universidade Auburn Roderick Long — parecem vir não de libertários, e sim de esquerdistas radicais, marxistas até. Essa conclusão seria apenas a metade errada: essas palavras foram escritas por libertários de esquerda favoráveis ao livre mercado. (O termo preferido para expressar seu ideal econômico é “mercado libertado/emancipado,” cunhado por William Gillis.)

Esses autores — e crescente grupo de colegas — veem-se tanto como libertários quanto como esquerdistas. São libertários típicos na medida em que acreditam na legitimidade moral da propriedade privada e do livre intercâmbio, e se opõem a toda interferência do governo em assuntos pessoais e econômicos — uma dicotomia sem fundamento e perniciosa. No entanto, são esquerdistas por compartirem preocupações esquerdistas tradicionais, por exemplo quanto a exploração e desigualdade, que são em grande parte ignoradas, se não desqualificadas, por outros libertários. Os libertários de esquerda são favoráveis a solidariedade dos trabalhadores diante de seus chefes, ao apoio à ocupação, pelas pessoas, de propriedade do governo ou abandonada, e preferem que os privilégios corporativos sejam rejeitados de preferência a restrições normativas acerca de como esses privilégios possam ser exercidos. Veem a Walmart como símbolo de favoritismo corporativo — apoiada por subsídios a rodovias e por desapropriações — veem a pessoa fictícia da corporação de responsabilidade limitada com suspeita, e duvidam de que os locais de trabalho em condições vis do Terceiro Mundo constituam a “melhor alternativa” quando haja ausência de manipulação pelo governo.

Os libertários de esquerda tendem a distanciar-se da política eleitoral, tendo pouca confiança em estratégias que funcionem por meio do governo. Preferem desenvolver soluções e métodos alternativos contornando o estado. A Aliança da Esquerda Libertária estimula a formação de organizações locais ativistas e de ajuda mútua, enquanto seu website promove grupos afins e afixa artigos explicitando sua filosofia. O novo Centro por uma Sociedade sem Estado (C4SS) estimula os libertários de esquerda a levar ao público em geral suas análises de eventos correntes, por meio de artigos opinativos.

Esses libertários de esquerda do laissez-faire não devem ser confundidos com outras variedades de libertários de esquerda, tais como Noam Chomsky ou Hillel Steiner, os quais, cada um a seu modo, objetam à apropriação individualista de recursos naturais sem dono e à desigualdade econômica que os mercados libertados podem produzir. Os libertários esquerdistas ora considerados têm sido chamados de “libertários de esquerda orientados para o mercado” ou “anarquistas de mercado,” embora nem todos os nesse arraial sejam anarquistas.

Há fundamento histórico para situar o libertarismo pró-mercado na esquerda. Na primeira metade do século 19, o economista liberal do laissez-faire Frederic Bastiat sentava-se no lado esquerdo da Assembleia Nacional Francesa com outros opositores radicais do ancien régime, incluindo uma cepa de socialistas. O lado direito era reservado para defensores reacionários da monarquia absoluta e da plutocracia. Por longo tempo “esquerda” significou radical, revolucionário mesmo, oposição à autoridade política, incendido por esperança e otimismo, enquanto “direita” significava simpatia por um statu quo de privilégio ou retorno a uma ordem autoritária. Esses termos foram utilizados até nos Estados Unidos, até bem dentro do século 20, e só começaram a mudar durante o Novo Pacto, que deflagrou lamentáveis alianças de conveniência que se estenderam até a era da Guerra Fria e depois.

Com risco de simplificação excessiva, há duas fontes do moderno libertarismo esquerdista pró-mercado: a teoria de economia política formulada por Murray N. Rothbard e a filosofia conhecida como “mutualismo” associada ao anarquista pró-mercado Pierre-Joseph Proudhon — que se sentava com Bastiat no lado esquerdo da assembleia enquanto argumentava com ele incessantemente acerca de teoria econômica — e o anarquista individualista estadunidense Benjamin R. Tucker.

Rothbard (1926-1995) foi o principal teórico do libertarismo lockeano radical conjugado com a economia Austríaca, a qual explica que os livres mercados produzem prosperidade disseminada, cooperação social, e coordenação econômica sem monopólio, depressão, ou inflação — males cujas raízes hão de ser encontradas na intervenção do governo. Rothbard, que se denominava “anarcocapitalista,” primeiro via-se como homem da “Antiga Direita,” a frouxa coleção de opositores do Novo Pacto e do Império Estadunidense personificada pelo Senador Robert Taft, o jornalista John T. Flynn e, mais radicalmente, Albert Jay Nock. Sem embargo, Rothbard entendia as raízes esquerdistas do libertarismo.

Em seu clássico e abrangente ensaio de 1965 “Esquerda e Direita: Perspectivas para a Liberdade,” Rothbard identificou “liberalismo” — aquilo que hoje é chamado de libertarismo — com a esquerda como “o grupo da esperança, do radicalismo, da liberdade, da Revolução Industrial, do progresso, da humanidade.” A outra grande ideologia a surgir depois da Revolução Francesa “foi o conservadoriosmo, o grupo da reação, o grupo que sonhava em restaurar hierarquia, estatismo, teocracia, servidão, e exploração de classe da Antiga Ordem.”

Quando a Nova Esquerda surgiu nos anos 1960 para opor-se à Guerra do Vietnã, ao complexo industrial-militar e à centralização burocrática, Rothbard prontamente fez causa comum com ela. “A Esquerda mudou muito, e é obrigação de toda pessoa interessada em ideologia entender essa mudança… . [Essa] mudança marca dramática e esplêndida infusão de libertarismo nas fileiras da Esquerda,” escreveu ele em “A liberdade e a Nova Esquerda.” Seu radicalismo de esquerda ficou claro em seu interesse em descentralização e democracia participativa, reforma agrária favorável aos camponeses no Terceiro Mundo feudal, “poder preto,” e “assunção,” pelos trabalhadores, de corporações estadunidenses cujos lucros viessem principalmente de contratos com o governo.

Entretanto, com o declínio da Nova Esquerda, Rothbard desenfatizou essas posições e moveu-se estrategicamente para o paleoconservadorismo de direita. Seu colega libertário de esquerda, o antigo escritor de discursos de Goldwater Karl Hess (1923-1994), manteve a tocha acesa. Em Caros Estados UnidosHess escreveu: “Na extrema direita, lei e ordem significam a lei de quem manda e a ordem que atende ao interesse de quem manda, usualmente a ordem dos trabalhadores sem vontade própria, dos estudantes submissos, dos mais velhos ou totalmente intimidados até à lealdade ou totalmente doutrinados e treinados nessa lealdade,” enquanto a esquerda “tem sido o lado da política e da economia que se opõe à concentração de poder e riqueza e, pelo contrário, defende e trabalha no sentido de distribuição do poder pelo número máximo de mãos.”

Benjamin Tucker (1854-1939) foi editor de Liberty, a principal publicação do anarquismo individualista estadunidense. Como mutualista, Tucker defendia rigorosamente livres mercados e intercâmbio voluntário isentos de todo privilégio e regulamentação do governo. Na verdade, ele se intitulava “homem de Manchester coerente,” uma referência à filosofia econômica dos livres-mercadistas ingleses Richard Cobden e John Bright. Tucker desdenhava dos defensores do statu quo estadunidense os quais, ao mesmo tempo em que favoráveis à livre competição entre trabalhadores em busca de emprego, apoiavam a supressão capitalista de competição entre os empregadores por meio dos “quatro monopólios” do governo: terra, tarifa, patentes, e dinheiro.

“O que causa a distribuição iníqua da riqueza?” perguntava Tucker em 1892. “Não é a competição, e sim o monopólio, que priva o trabalhador de seu produto. … Destruam o monopólio bancário, estabeleçam liberdade na finança, e cairão os juros sobre o dinheiro por meio da benéfica influência da competição. O capital será libertado, os negócios florescerão, novas empresas começarão, haverá demanda por trabalho, e gradualmente a remuneração do trabalho ascenderá ao nível de seu produto.”

Os rothbardianos e mutualistas têm alguns desacordos acerca de posse da terra e teorias do valor, mas sua polinização cruzada intelectual trouxe os dois grupos um para mais perto do outro filosoficamente. O que os une, e os distingue de outros libertários de mercado, é sua adoção de preocupações de esquerda, inclusive as consequências do poder corporativo plutocrático para os trabalhadores e outros grupos vulneráveis. Contudo, os libertários de esquerda diferem de outros esquerdistas ao identificarem o culpado como sendo a parceria histórica entre governo e empresas — seja ela chamada de estado corporativo, capitalismo de estado, ou simplesmente de capitalismo — e ao verem a solução no laissez faire radical, na separação total entre economia e estado.

Assim, pois, por trás da filosofia econômica-política há uma visão da história que separa os libertários de esquerda tanto dos esquerdistas comuns quanto dos libertários comuns. As variedades comuns de ambas essas filosofias entendem que mercados essencialmente livres tiveram lugar na Inglaterra desde o tempo da Revolução Industrial, embora avaliem o resultado de maneira muito diferente. Os libertários de esquerda, porém, são revisionistas, insistindo em que a era de quase laissez faire é um mito. Em vez de radical libertação das atividades econômicas, a Inglaterra viu a elite dominante viciar o sistema social em benefício dos interesses da classe dententora de propriedades. (A análise de classes originou-se com economistas franceses do livre mercado anteriores a Marx.)

Por meio do cerco, camponeses foram destituídos da terra que eles e seus familiares haviam trabalhado por gerações e foram transformados pela força em arrendatários pagadores de aluguel ou assalariados nas novas fábricas, com seus direitos de organizarem-se e até de se mudarem restringidos por leis de assentamento, leis dos pobres, e outras. Nas colônias estadunidenses e no início da república, o sistema foi similarmente viciado por meio de doações de terra e especulação (para e por ferrovias, por exemplo), restrições ao voto, tarifas, patentes, e controle do dinheiro e da atividade bancária.

Em outras palavras, o crepúsculo do feudalismo e a alvorada do capitalismo não encontraram todo mundo postado na linha de largada em condições de igualdade — longe disso. Como o sociólogo pró-mercado Franz Oppenheimer, que desenvolveu a teoria da conquista do estado, escreveu em seu livro O Estado, não foram talento superior, ambição, poupança, e nem mesmo sorte que separaram a minoria detentora de propriedades da maioria proletária sem propriedade — e sim a pilhagem legal, para tomar de empréstimo a famosa expressão de Bastiat.

Eis aqui algo que Marx entendeu corretamente. Na verdade, Kevin Carson endossa a “passagem eloquente” de Marx: “esses novos homens livres só se tornaram vendedores de si próprios depois de terem sido roubados de todos os seus meios próprios de produção, e de todas as garantias aportadas pelos antigos acordos feudais. E a história disso, de sua expropriação, está escrita nos anais do gênero humano em letras de sangue e fogo.”

Esse sistema de privilégio e exploração tem tido efeitos de duradoura distorção que continuam a afligir a maior parte das pessoas até hoje, enquanto beneficia a elite dominante; Carson chama isso de “o subsídio da história.” Isso não significa negar que os padrões de vida têm de modo geral aumentado em economias mistas orientadas para o mercado, e sim enfatizar que os padrões de vida para os trabalhadores médios seriam ainda mais altos — para não mencionar menos baseados em dívidas — e as disparidades de riqueza menos pronunciadas num mercado emancipado.

O “anticapitalismo de livre mercado” do libertarismo de esquerda não é uma contradição, nem desdobramento recente. Ele permeava a Liberdade de Tucker, e a identificação da exploração dos trabalhadores remonta a pelo menos Thomas Hodgskin (1787-1869), radical de livre mercado que foi um dos primeiros a aplicar o termo “capitalista” depreciativamente aos favores concedidos pelo governo ao capital a expensas do trabalho. Nos séculos 19 e início do 20 “socialismo” não significava exclusivamente propriedade coletiva ou pelo governo dos meios de produção, e sim era termo abrangente, para qualquer pessoa que acreditasse que o trabalho tinha seu produto natural ilegitimamente subtraído pelo capitalismo histórico.

Por vezes Tucker referia-se a si próprio como socialista, mas denunciava Marx como representante do “princípio da autoridade, que combatemos de alto a baixo.” Ele considerava  Proudhon o teórico superior e real campeão da liberdade. “Marx nacionalizaria as forças produtivas e distributivas; Proudhon as individualizaria e associaria.”

O termo capitalista sugere que o capital deve ser privilegiado acima do trabalho. Como o autor libertário de esquerda Gary Chartier, da Universidade La Sierra, escreve, “[F]az sentido para [os libertários de esquerda] dar àquilo a que eles se opõem o nome ‘capitalismo.’ Fazer isso … assegura que os defensores da liberdade não sejam confundidos com pessoas que usam a retórica do mercado para dar sustentação a um injusto statu quo, e expressa solidariedade entre os defensores dos livres mercados e os trabalhadores — do mesmo modo que as pessoas comuns ao redor do mundo usam ‘capitalismo’ como rótulo abreviado do sistema mundial que restringue sua liberdade e estiola suas vidas.”

Em contraste com os libertários não esquerdistas, que parecem não se interessar pelas, isso quando não são hostis às, preocupações com o trabalho enquanto tais, os libertários de esquerda naturalmente simpatizam com os esforços dos trabalhadores para melhorarem suas condições. (Bastiat, do mesmo modo que Tucker, apoiava associações de trabalhadores.) Entretanto, há pouca afinidade com sindicatos burocráticos certificados pelo governo, que representam pouco mais do que supressão corporatista do movimento  espontâneo e autodigirido/de ajuda mútua anterior ao Novo Pacto, com sua simpatia “não autorizada” por greves e boicotes. Antes da Lei Wagner do Novo Pacto, grandes líderes de negócios, como Gerard Swope, da GE, já por muito tempo haviam apoiado legislação trabalhista por esse motivo.

Ademais, os libertários de esquerda tendem a abrigar viés contra emprego assalariado e a amiúde autoritária hierarquia corporativa à qual aquele está sujeito. Os trabalhadores, hoje, são prejudicados por um séquito de normas, impostos, leis de propriedade intelectual e subsídios às empresas que, em conjunto, tolhem a entrada no mercado de empregadores alternativos em potencial e a atividade de emprego autônomo. Bem assim, crises econômicas periódicas deflagradas por empréstimos contraídos pelo governo e pela gerência do dinheiro e da atividade bancária pela Reserva Federal ameaçam os trabalhadores com desemprego, colocando-os ainda mais à mercê dos chefes.

A cartelização inibidora da competição diminui o poder de barganha dos trabalhadores, permitindo que os empregadores os privem de uma porção da renda que eles receberiam numa economia libertada e plenamente competitiva, onde os empregadores teriam de competir por trabalhadores — em vez do contrário — e o emprego autônomo livre de exigências de licenciamentos ofereceria, de modo geral, escape em relação ao emprego assalariado. Obviamente, a atividade autônoma tem seus riscos e não seria para todos, mas seria mais atraente para mais pessoas se o governo não tornasse o custo de vida, e portanto o custo de sobrevivência decente, artificialmente alto de mil maneiras diferentes — desde códigos de construção e restrições ao uso da terra a padrões de produtos, subsídios a rodovias, e medicina gerida pelo governo.

Num mercado libertado os libertários de esquerda esperam ver menos emprego assalariado e mais empresas de propriedade dos trabalhadores, cooperativas, parcerias, e propriedades individuais. A revolução do baixo custo do desktop, da Internet e das máquinas operatrizes não dispendiosas torna isso mais viável do que nunca. Não haveria socialização de custos por meio de subsídios ao transporte para favorecer o comércio nacional em vez do regional e local. Pode ser esperado espírito de independência que dê início a movimento rumo a essas alternativas pelo simples motivo de que o emprego, até certo ponto, implica sujeitar a pessoa à vontade arbitrária de outrem, e à probabilidade de dispensa abrupta. Por causa da competição do emprego autônomo, o emprego assalariado que remanecesse mais provavelmente teria lugar em empresas menos hierárquicas, mais humanas que, sem gozar de favores políticos, não poderiam socializar deseconomias de escala tão grandes quanto as grandes corporações de nossos dias.

Os libertários de esquerda, abeberando-se da obra dos historiadores da Nova Esquerda, também discrepam do ponto de vista conservador e libertário comum de que as regulamentações econômicas da Era Progressista e do Novo Pacto foram impostas pelos social-democratas goela abaixo a uma comunidade de negócios amante da liberdade. Pelo contrário, como Gabriel Kolko e outros mostraram, a elite corporativa — a Casa de Morgan, por exemplo — voltou-se para intervenção do governo ao perceber, no final do século 19, que a competição era forte demais para assegurar-lhe fatia de mercado.

Assim, pois, os libertários de esquerda veem os Estados Unidos posteriores à Guerra Civil não como era dourada de laissez faire, e sim como rebento altamente corrupto da guerra dominado pelas empresas, caracterizado pela usual contratação militar e pela especulação com títulos do governo. Como em todas as guerras, o governo ganhou poder, e homens de negócios com boas conexões ganharam fortunas financiadas pelos contribuintes e portanto vantagem injusta no alegadamente livre mercado da Era Dourada.  “A guerra é a saúde do estado,” escreveu o intelectual esquerdista Randolph Bourne. A guerra civil também.

Esses pontos de vista históricos conflitantes são bem ilustrados nos escritos da novelista pró-capitalista Ayn Rand (1905-1982) e de Roy A. Childs Jr. (1949-1992), escritor-editor libertário com definida inclinação esquerdista. Nos anos 1960 Rand escreveu um ensaio com o título autoexplicativo de “A Minoria Perseguida dos Estados Unidos: as Grandes Empresas,” ao qual Childs respondeu com “as Grandes Empresas e a Ascensão do Estatismo Estadunidense.” “Em grande medida foram e continuam sendo os grandes homens de negócios as fontes do estatismo estadunidense,” escreveu Childs.

Uma das maneiras de ver a distinção entre os libertários de esquerda e outros libertários de mercado é a seguinte: os outros olham a economia estadunidense e veem um mercado essencialmente livre recoberto por fina camada de intervenção Progressista e do Novo Pacto que só precisa ser raspada para que a liberdade seja restaurada. Os libertários de esquerda veem uma economia corporatista até o cerne, embora com limitada livre empresa competitiva. Os programas que constituem o estado assistencialista são vistos como secundários e remediadores, isto é, visantes a evitar descontentamento social potencialmente perigoso mediante dar assistência às — e controlar as — pessoas prejudicadas pelo sistema.

Os libertários de esquerda colidem com os libertários convencionais mais frequentemente quando esses últimos exibem o que Carson chama de “libertarismo vulgar” e o que Roderick Long chama de “equivalentismo de Direita.” Essa atitude consiste em julgar os negócios estadunidenses no ambiente estatista de nossos dias como se estivessem tendo lugar num mercado emancipado. Assim, embora os libertários não esquerdistas teoricamente reconheçam que as grandes empresas gozam de privilégios de monopólio, também defendem as corporações quando elas ficam sob ataque da esquerda, argumentando que se elas não estivessem servindo aos consumidores, o mercado competitivo as puniria. “Os libertários vulgares apologistas do capitalismo usam a expressão ‘livre mercado’ em sentido equívoco,” escreve Carson, “[E]les parecem ter dificuldade em lembrar, de um momento para o seguinte, se estão defendendo o capitalismo realmente existente ou princípios de livre mercado.”

Sinais de equivalentismo de Direita podem ser vistos na defensividade dos libertários convencionais comuns diante da crítica esquerdista de desigualdade de renda, estrutura corporativa dos Estados Unidos, altos preços do petróleo, ou sistema de saúde. Se não há livre mercado, por que ser defensivo? Geralmente você pode deixar um libertário não esquerdista louco ao comparar a Europa Ocidental favoravelmente em relação aos Estados Unidos. Quanto a isso, Carson escreve: “[S]e você se denomina libertário, não tente enganar ninguém dizendo que o sistema estadunidense é menos estatista do que o alemão só porque mais aproveitadores de assistencialismo excessivo vestem terno com colete… . [S]e estivermos escolhendo entre níveis iguais de estatismo, obviamente ficarei com aquele que pese menos no meu pescoço.”

Fiéis a sua herança, os libertários de esquerda lutam em favor de outros grupos oprimidos: os pobres, as mulheres, pessoas de cor, gays, e imigrantes, documentados ou não. Os libertários de esquerda veem os pobres não como oportunistas preguiçosos, e sim como vítimas das miríades de barreiras do estado à ajuda autônoma, ajuda mútua, e educação decente. Os libertários de esquerda naturalmente opõem-se à opressão das mulheres e das minorias pelo governo, mas desejam também combater formas não violentas de opressão social tais como racismo e sexismo. Visto essas não serem levadas a efeito pela força, as medidas usadas para oposição a elas também não podem implicar força ou o estado. Assim, pois, discriminação sexual e racial devem ser combatidas por meio de boicotes, publicidade e manifestações, não violência ou leis antidiscriminação. Para os libertários de esquerda, o racismo sulista de balcão de lanchonete foi melhor combatido por meio de as pessoas sentarem-se pacificamente do que com legislação de Washington, que meramente ratificou o que a ação direta vinha conseguindo sem ajuda da elite branca.

Por que os libertários de esquerda qua libertários se preocupam com opressão não violenta e não estatal? Porque o libertarismo tem como premissa a dignidade e a posse, por si próprio, do indivíduo, que sexismo e racismo negam. Portanto, todas as formas de hierarquia coletivista solapam a atitude libertária e portanto as perspectivas de uma sociedade livre.

Numa palavra, os libertários de esquerda são a favor da igualdade. Não igualdade material — que não pode ser conseguida sem opressão e sufocamento da iniciativa. Não mera igualdade sob a lei — pois a lei pode ser opressora. E não apenas igual liberdade — pois quantidade igual de pouca liberdade é intolerável. Eles são a favor do que Roderick Long, recorrendo a John Locke, chama de igualdade de autoridade: “A igualdade lockeana envolve não apenas igualdade perantelegisladores, juízes e polícia mas, muito mais crucialmente, igualdade com legisladores, juízes, e polícia.”

Finalnmente, como a maioria dos libertários comuns, os libertários de esquerda opõem-se inflexivelmente à guerra e ao império estadunidense. Eles adotam uma análise essencialmente econômica do imperialismo: empresas privilegiadas buscam acesso a recursos, a mercados externos em busca de lucros, e a maneiras de impor leis de propriedade intelectual a sociedades industriais emergentes para impedir que fabricantes externos reduzam os preços graças a competição. (Isso não é dizer não haver fatores políticos adicionais por trás do ímpeto em busca de império.)

Nos dias de hoje os libertários de esquerda veem sua posição reconhecida. A política externa estadunidense atolou o país em infindáveis guerras abertas e secretas, com seu alto custo em sangue e tesouro, no Oriente Médio e na Ásia Central ricos de recursos — com tortura, detenção por tempo indefinido e escutas, entre mais outras agressões a liberdades civis. Enquanto isso, a histórica aliança Washington-Wall Street — na qual a irresponsabilidade com o dinheiro das outras pessoas, promovida por meio de garantias, socorros financeiros e simulacros de liquidez da Reserva Federal apresentados como desregulamentação — levou a mais uma crise financeira com seu pesado tributo sobre o estadunidense médio, com mais insegurança no emprego e potencialização da influência de Wall Street.

Tal nocividade só pode apressar o dia quando as pessoas descubram a alternativa libertária de esquerda. É essa expectativa realista? Talvez. Muitos estadunidenses sentem que algo está profundamente errado com seu país. Sentem que suas vidas são controladas por grandes burocracias do governo e corporativas que consomem seu patrimônio e os tratam como súditos. No entanto, não lhes agrada a social-democracia de estilo europeu, muito menos o socialismo de estado pleno. O libertarismo de esquerda poderá ser o que eles estão buscando. Como escreve o mutualista Carson, “Por causa de nossa afeição por livres mercados, os mutualistas por vezes conflitam com aqueles que têm afinidade estética com o coletivismo, ou com aqueles para os quais ‘pequeno-burguês’ é palavrão. São porém nossas tendências pequeno-burguesas que nos colocam na corrente majoritária da tradição populista/radical estadunidense, e nos tornam relevantes para as necessidades dos trabalhadores médios estadunidenses.”

Carson acredita que os cidadãos comuns estão começando a “descrer das organizações burocráticas que controlam suas comunidades e vidas de trabalho, e desejam mais controle sobre as decisões que os afetam. Estão abertos à possibilidade de alternativas descentralistas, de baixo para cima, ao sistema presente.” Esperemos que ele esteja certo.

Artigo original afixado por Sheldon Richman em 3 de fevereiro de 2011.

Traduzido do inglês por Murilo Otávio Rodrigues Paes Leme.

Left-Libertarian - Classics
Libertarian Left: Free-Market Anti-Capitalism, The Unknown Ideal

Ron Paul’s 2008 presidential campaign introduced many people to the word “libertarian.” Since Paul is a Republican and Republicans, like libertarians, use the rhetoric of free markets and private enterprise, people naturally assume that libertarians are some kind of quirky offshoot of the American right wing. To be sure, some libertarian positions fit uneasily with mainstream conservatism — complete drug decriminalization, legal same-sex marriage, and the critique of the national-security state alienate many on the right from libertarianism.

But the dominant strain of libertarianism still seems at home on that side of the political spectrum. Paeans to property rights and free enterprise — the mainstream libertarian conviction that the American capitalist system, despite government intervention, fundamentally embodies those values — appear to justify that conclusion.

But then one runs across passages like this: “Capitalism, arising as a new class society directly from the old class society of the Middle Ages, was founded on an act of robbery as massive as the earlier feudal conquest of the land. It has been sustained to the present by continual state intervention to protect its system of privilege without which its survival is unimaginable.” And this: “build worker solidarity. On the one hand, this means formal organisation, including unionization — but I’m not talking about the prevailing model of ‘business unions’ … but real unions, the old-fashioned kind, committed to the working class and not just union members, and interested in worker autonomy, not government patronage.”

These passages — the first by independent scholar Kevin Carson, the second by Auburn University philosophy professor Roderick Long — read as though they come not from libertarians but from radical leftists, even Marxists. That conclusion would be only half wrong: these words were written by pro-free-market left-libertarians. (The preferred term for their economic ideal is “freed market,” coined by William Gillis.)

These authors — and a growing group of colleagues — see themselves as both libertarians and leftists. They are standard libertarians in that they believe in the moral legitimacy of private ownership and free exchange and oppose all government interference in personal and economic affairs — a groundless, pernicious dichotomy. Yet they are leftists in that they share traditional left-wing concerns, about exploitation and inequality for example, that are largely ignored, if not dismissed, by other libertarians. Left-libertarians favor worker solidarity vis-à-vis bosses, support poor people’s squatting on government or abandoned property, and prefer that corporate privileges be repealed before the regulatory restrictions on how those privileges may be exercised. They see Walmart as a symbol of corporate favoritism — supported by highway subsidies and eminent domain — view the fictive personhood of the limited-liability corporation with suspicion, and doubt that Third World sweatshops would be the “best alternative” in the absence of government manipulation.

Left-libertarians tend to eschew electoral politics, having little confidence in strategies that work through the government. They prefer to develop alternative institutions and methods of working around the state. The Alliance of the Libertarian Left encourages the formation of local activist and mutual-aid organizations, while its website promotes kindred groups and posts articles elaborating its philosophy. The new Center for a Stateless Society (C4SS) encourages left-libertarians to bring their analysis of current events to the general public through op-eds.

These laissez-faire left-libertarians are not to be confused with other varieties of left-wing libertarians, such as Noam Chomsky or Hillel Steiner, who each in his own way objects to individualistic appropriation of unowned natural resources and the economic inequality that freed markets can produce. The left-libertarians under consideration here have been called “market-oriented left-libertarians” or “market anarchists,” though not everyone in this camp is an anarchist.

There are historical grounds for placing pro-market libertarianism on the left. In the first half of the 19th century, the laissez-faire liberal economist Frederic Bastiat sat on the left side of the French National Assembly with other radical opponents of the ancien régime, including a variety of socialists. The right side was reserved for reactionary defenders of absolute monarchy and plutocracy. For a long time “left” signified radical, even revolutionary, opposition to political authority, fired by hope and optimism, while “right” signified sympathy for a status quo of privilege or a return to an authoritarian order. These terms applied even in the United States well into the 20th century and only began to change during the New Deal, which prompted regrettable alliances of convenience that carried over into the Cold War era and beyond.

At the risk of oversimplifying, there are two wellsprings of modern pro-market left-libertarianism: the theory of political economy formulated by Murray N. Rothbard and the philosophy known as “Mutualism” associated with the pro-market anarchist Pierre-Joseph Proudhon — who sat with Bastiat on the left side of the assembly while arguing with him incessantly about economic theory — and the American individualist anarchist Benjamin R. Tucker.

Rothbard (1926-1995) was the leading theorist of radical Lockean libertarianism combined with Austrian economics, which demonstrates that free markets produce widespread prosperity, social cooperation, and economic coordination without monopoly, depression, or inflation — evils whose roots are to be found in government intervention. Rothbard, who called himself an “anarcho-capitalist,” first saw himself as a man of the “Old Right,” the loose collection of opponents of the New Deal and American Empire epitomized by Sen. Robert Taft, journalist John T. Flynn, and more radically, Albert Jay Nock. Yet Rothbard understood libertarianism’s left-wing roots.

In his 1965 classic and sweeping essay “Left and Right: The Prospects for Liberty,” Rothbard identified “liberalism” — what is today called libertarianism — with the left as “the party of hope, of radicalism, of liberty, of the Industrial Revolution, of progress, of humanity.” The other great ideology to emerge after the French revolution “was conservatism, the party of reaction, the party that longed to restore the hierarchy, statism, theocracy, serfdom, and class exploitation of the Old Order.”

When the New Left arose in the 1960s to oppose the Vietnam War, the military-industrial complex, and bureaucratic centralization, Rothbard easily made common cause with it. “The Left has changed greatly, and it is incumbent upon everyone interested in ideology to understand the change… . [T]he change marks a striking and splendid infusion of libertarianism into the ranks of the Left,”  he wrote in “Liberty and the New Left.” His left-radicalism was clear in his interest in decentralization and participatory democracy, pro-peasant land reform in the feudal Third World, “black power,” and worker “homesteading” of American corporations whose profits came mainly from government contracts.

But with the fading of New Left, Rothbard deemphasized these positions and moved strategically toward right-wing paleoconservatism. His left-libertarian colleague, the former Goldwater speechwriter Karl Hess (1923-1994), kept the torch burning. In Dear America Hess wrote, “On the far right, law and order means the law of the ruler and the order that serves the interest of that ruler, usually the orderliness of drone workers, submissive students, elders either totally cowed into loyalty or totally indoctrinated and trained into that loyalty,” while the left “has been the side of politics and economics that opposes the concentration of power and wealth and, instead, advocates and works toward the distribution of power into the maximum number of hands.”

Benjamin Tucker (1854-1939) was the editor of Liberty, the leading publication of American individualist anarchism. As a Mutualist, Tucker rigorously embraced free markets and voluntary exchange void of all government privilege and regulation. Indeed, he called himself a “consistent Manchester man,” a reference to the economic philosophy of the English free-traders Richard Cobden and John Bright. Tucker disdained defenders of the American status quo who, while favoring free competition among workers for jobs, supported capitalist suppression of competition among employers through government’s “four monopolies”: land, the tariff, patents, and money.

“What causes the inequitable distribution of wealth?” Tucker asked in 1892. “It is not competition, but monopoly, that deprives labor of its product. … Destroy the banking monopoly, establish freedom in finance, and down will go interest on money through the beneficent influence of competition. Capital will be set free, business will flourish, new enterprises will start, labor will be in demand, and gradually the wages of labor will rise to a level with its product.”

The Rothbardians and Mutualists have some disagreements over land ownership and theories of value, but their intellectual cross-pollination has brought the groups closer philosophically. What unites them, and distinguishes them from other market libertarians, is their embrace of traditional left-wing concerns, including the consequences of plutocratic corporate power for workers and other vulnerable groups. But left-libertarians differ from other leftists in identifying the culprit as the historical partnership between government and business — whether called the corporate state, state capitalism, or just plain capitalism — and in seeing the solution in radical laissez faire, the total separation of economy and state.

Thus behind the political-economic philosophy is a view of history that separates left-libertarians from both ordinary leftists and ordinary libertarians. The common varieties of both philosophies agree that essentially free markets reigned in England from the time of the Industrial Revolution, though they evaluate the outcome very differently. But left-libertarians are revisionists, insisting that the era of near laissez faire is a myth. Rather than a radical freeing of economic affairs, England saw the ruling elite rig the social system on behalf of propertied class interests. (Class analysis originated with French free-market economists predating Marx.)

Through enclosure, peasants were dispossessed of land they and their kin had worked for generations and were forcibly turned into rent-paying tenants or wage-earners in the new factories with their rights to organize and even to move restricted by laws of settlement, poor laws, combination laws, and more. In the American colonies and early republic, the system was similarly rigged through land grants and speculation (for and by railroads, for example), voting restrictions, tariffs, patents, and control of money and banking.

In other words, the twilight of feudalism and the dawn of capitalism did not find everyone poised at the starting line as equals — far from it. As the pro-market sociologist Franz Oppenheimer, who developed the conquest theory of the state, wrote in his book The State, it was not superior talent, ambition, thrift, or even luck that separated the property-holding minority from the propertyless proletarian majority — but legal plunder, to borrow Bastiat’s famous phrase.

Here is something Marx got right. Indeed, Kevin Carson seconds Marx’s “eloquent passage”: “these new freedmen became sellers of themselves only after they had been robbed of all their own means of production, and of all the guarantees afforded by the old feudal arrangements. And the history of this, their expropriation, is written in the annals of mankind in letters of blood and fire.”

This system of privilege and exploitation has had long-distorting effects that continue to afflict most people to this day, while benefiting the ruling elite; Carson calls it “the subsidy of history.” This is not to deny that living standards have generally risen in market-oriented mixed economies but rather to point out that living standards for average workers would be even higher — not to mention less debt-based — and wealth disparities less pronounced in a freed market.

The “free-market anti-capitalism” of left-libertarianism is no contradiction, nor is it a recent development. It permeated Tucker’s Liberty, and the identification of worker exploitation harked back at least to Thomas Hodgskin (1787-1869), a free-market radical who was one of the first to apply the term “capitalist” disparagingly to the beneficiaries of government favors bestowed on capital at the expense of labor. In the 19th and early 20th centuries, “socialism” did not exclusively mean collective or government ownership of the means or production but was an umbrella term for anyone who believed labor was cheated out of its natural product under historical capitalism.

Tucker sometimes called himself a socialist, but he denounced Marx as the representative of “the principle of authority which we live to combat.” He thought Proudhon the superior theorist and the real champion of freedom. “Marx would nationalize the productive and distributive forces; Proudhon would individualize and associate them.”

The term capitalism certainly suggests that capital is to be privileged over labor. As left-libertarian author Gary Chartier of La Sierra University writes, “[I]t makes sense for [left-libertarians] to name what they oppose ‘capitalism.’ Doing so … ensures that advocates of freedom aren’t confused with people who use market rhetoric to prop up an unjust status quo, and expresses solidarity between defenders of freed markets and workers — as well as ordinary people around the world who use ‘capitalism’ as a short-hand label for the world-system that constrains their freedom and stunts their lives.”

In contrast to nonleft-libertarians, who seem uninterested in, if not hostile to, labor concerns per se, left-libertarians naturally sympathize with workers’ efforts to improve their conditions. (Bastiat, like Tucker, supported worker associations.) However, there is little affinity for government-certified bureaucratic unions, which represent little more than a corporatist suppression of the pre-New Deal spontaneous and self-directed labor/mutual-aid movement, with its “unauthorized” sympathy strikes and boycotts. Before the New Deal Wagner Act, big business leaders like GE’s Gerard Swope had long supported labor legislation for this reason.

Moreover, left-libertarians tend to harbor a bias against wage employment and the often authoritarian corporate hierarchy to which it is subject. Workers today are handicapped by an array of regulations, taxes, intellectual-property laws, and business subsidies that on net impede entry to potential alternative employers and self-employment. As well, periodic economic crises set off by government borrowing and Federal Reserve management of money and banking threaten workers with unemployment, putting them further at the mercy of bosses.

Competition-inhibiting cartelization diminishes workers’ bargaining power, enabling employers to deprive them of a portion of the income they would receive in a freed and fully competitive economy, where employers would have to compete for workers — rather than vice versa — and self-employment free of licensing requirements would offer an escape from wage employment altogether. Of course, self-employment has its risks and wouldn’t be for everyone, but it would be more attractive to more people if government did not make the cost of living, and hence the cost of decent subsistence, artificially high in myriad ways — from building codes and land-use restrictions to product standards, highway subsidies, and government-managed medicine.

In a freed market left-libertarians expect to see less wage employment and more worker-owned enterprises, co-ops, partnerships, and single proprietorships. The low-cost desktop revolution, Internet, and inexpensive machine tools make this more feasible than ever. There would be no socialization of costs through transportation subsidies to favor nationwide over regional and local commerce. A spirit of independence can be expected to prompt a move toward these alternatives for the simple reason that employment to some extent entails subjecting oneself to someone else’s arbitrary will and the chance of abrupt dismissal. Because of the competition from self-employment, what wage employment remained would most likely take place in less-hierarchical, more-humane firms that, lacking political favors, could not socialize diseconomies of scale as large corporations do today.

Left-libertarians, drawing on the work of New Left historians, also dissent from the conservative and standard libertarian view that the economic regulations of the Progressive Era and New Deal were imposed by social democrats on an unwilling freedom-loving business community. On the contrary, as Gabriel Kolko and others have shown, the corporate elite — the House of Morgan, for example — turned to government intervention when it realized in the waning 19th century that competition was too unruly to guarantee market share.

Thus left-libertarians see post-Civil War America not as a golden era of laissez faire but rather as a largely corrupt business-ruled outgrowth of the war, which featured the usual military contracting and speculation in government-securities. As in all wars, government gained power and well-connected businessmen gained taxpayer-financed fortunes and hence unfair advantage in the allegedly free market of the Gilded Age. “War is the health of the state,” leftist intellectual Randolph Bourne wrote. Civil war too.

These conflicting historical views are well illustrated in the writings of the pro-capitalist novelist Ayn Rand (1905-1982) and Roy A. Childs Jr. (1949-1992), a libertarian writer-editor with definite leftist leanings. In the 1960s Rand wrote an essay with the self-explanatory title “America’s Persecuted Minority: Big Business,” which Childs answered with “Big Business and the Rise of American Statism.” “To a large degree it has been and remains big businessmen who are the fountainheads of American statism,” Childs wrote.

One way to view the separation of left-libertarians from other market libertarians is this: the others look at the American economy and see an essentially free market coated with a thin layer of Progressive and New Deal intervention that need only to be scraped away to restore liberty. Left-libertarians see an economy that is corporatist to its core, although with limited competitive free enterprise. The programs constituting the welfare state are regarded as secondary and ameliorative, that is, intended to avert potentially dangerous social discontent by succoring — and controlling — the people harmed by the system.

Left-libertarians clash with regular libertarians most frequently when the latter display what Carson calls “vulgar libertarianism” and what Roderick Long calls “Right-conflationism.” This consists of judging American business in today’s statist environment as though it were taking place in the freed market. Thus while nonleft-libertarians theoretically recognize that big business enjoys monopolistic privileges, they also defend corporations when they come under attack from the left on grounds that if they were not serving consumers, the competitive market would punish them. “Vulgar libertarian apologists for capitalism use the term ‘free market’ in an equivocal sense,” Carson writes, “[T]hey seem to have trouble remembering, from one moment to the next, whether they’re defending actually existing capitalism or free market principles.”

Signs of Right-conflationism can be seen in the common mainstream libertarian defensiveness at leftist criticism of income inequality, America’s corporate structure, high oil prices, or the healthcare system. If there’s no free market, why be defensive? You can usually make a nonleft-libertarian mad by comparing Western Europe favorably with the United States.  To this, Carson writes, “[I]f you call yourself a libertarian, don’t try to kid anybody that the American system is less statist than the German one just because more of the welfare queens wear three-piece suits. … [I]f we’re choosing between equal levels of statism, of course I’ll take the one that weighs less heavily on my own neck.”

True to their heritage, left-libertarians champion other historically oppressed groups: the poor, women, people of color, gays, and immigrants, documented or not. Left-libertarians see the poor not as lazy opportunists but rather as victims of the state’s myriad barriers to self-help, mutual aid, and decent education. Left-libertarians of course oppose government oppression of women and minorities, but they wish to combat nonviolent forms of social oppression such as racism and sexism as well. Since these are not carried out by force, the measures used to oppose them also may not entail force or the state. Thus, sex and racial discrimination are to be fought through boycotts, publicity, and demonstrations, not violence or antidiscrimination laws. For left-libertarians, southern lunch-counter racism was better battled through peaceful sit-ins than with legislation in Washington, which merely ratified what direct action had been accomplishing without help from the white elite.

Why do left-libertarians qua libertarians care about nonviolent, nonstate oppression? Because libertarianism is premised on the dignity and self-ownership of the individual, which sexism and racism deny. Thus all forms of collectivist hierarchy undermine the libertarian attitude and hence the prospects for a free society.

In a word, left-libertarians favor equality. Not material equality — that can’t be had without oppression and the stifling of initiative. Not mere equality under the law — for the law might be oppressive. And not just equal freedom — for an equal amount of a little freedom is intolerable. They favor what Roderick Long, drawing on John Locke, calls equality in authority: “Lockean equality involves not merely equality before legislators, judges, and police, but, far more crucially, equality with legislators, judges, and police.”

Finally, like most ordinary libertarians, left-libertarians adamantly oppose war and the American empire. They embrace an essentially economic analysis of imperialism: privileged firms seek access to resources, foreign markets for surplus goods, and ways to impose intellectual-property laws on emerging industrial societies to keep foreign manufacturers from driving down prices through competition. (This is not to say there aren’t additional, political factors behind the drive for empire.)

These days left-libertarians feel vindicated. American foreign policy has embroiled the country in endless overt and covert wars, with their high cost in blood and treasure, in the resource-rich Middle East and Central Asia — with torture, indefinite detention, and surveillance among other assaults on domestic civil liberties thrown in for good measure. Meanwhile, the historical Washington-Wall Street alliance — in which recklessness with other people’s money, fostered by guarantees, bailouts, and Federal Reserve liquidity masquerades as deregulation — has brought yet another financial crisis with its heavy toll for average Americans, additional job insecurity, and magnified Wall Street influence.

Such nefariousness can only hasten the day when people discover the left-libertarian alternative. Is that expectation realistic? Perhaps. Many Americans sense that something is deeply wrong with their country. They feel their lives are controlled by large government and corporate bureaucracies that consume their wealth and treat them like subjects. Yet they have little taste for European-style social democracy, much less full-blown state socialism. Left-libertarianism may be what they’re looking for. As the Mutualist Carson writes, “Because of our fondness for free markets, mutualists sometimes fall afoul of those who have an aesthetic affinity for collectivism, or those for whom ‘petty bourgeois’ is a swear word. But it is our petty bourgeois tendencies that put us in the mainstream of the American populist/radical tradition, and make us relevant to the needs of average working Americans.”

Carson believes ordinary citizens are coming to “distrust the bureaucratic organizations that control their communities and working lives, and want more control over the decisions that affect them. They are open to the possibility of decentralist, bottom-up alternatives to the present system.” Let’s hope he’s right.

<< Back to the Market Anarchism FAQ page

Translations for this article:

Feature Articles
How Slut Shaming Undermines Liberty

Recently there has been something of a kerfuffle among libertarians surrounding a video by Julie Borowski on why there are so few women in the libertarian movement. Some libertarian feminists, notably Sarah Skwire and Steve Horwitz, have criticized Borowski for promoting stereotypical views of women and denigrating women’s choices.  But Thomas Woods is not pleased with Skwire and Horwitz, and contends in a recent blog that they are “Libertarian Thought Police.”

Among other objections, Skwire and Horwitz contend that Borowski “slut shames women who engage in casual sex.”  Woods seems confused by this and writes, “Shows how sheltered I am: evidently there are people in the world who use the phrase ‘slut shames.'”  He then sarcastically dismisses the idea that casual sex is a legitimate choice made by women.

Now, I’m one of the “people in the world who use the phrase ‘slut shames.'”  And since the concept is apparently totally foreign to Dr. Woods, I hope I can explain to him why I think libertarians ought to oppose slut shaming. Slut shaming is the denigration of women as unacceptably sexual, often perpetuated using epithets like “slut” and “whore.”  While it is typically associated with shaming women for activities like casual sex, women can be slut shamed for practically anything. Dressing a particular way, having large breasts, flirting, rebuking sexual advances, being bisexual, and more can all be used as the impetus for slut shaming. Any woman can be slut shamed and there is no concrete definition of a “slut,” leading some feminists to argue that it is more accurate to simply refer to slut shaming as “woman hating.

But whatever we call it, slut shaming can have dire consequences.  It certainly did for Hope Witsell. After this 13-year-old girl sent a topless photo to a boy she had a crush on, she faced persistent slut-shaming and harassment from her peers. While school administrators did little to stop this harassment, they did see fit to suspend her for sending the photo. Hope eventually committed suicide. And she’s not alone. Felicia Garcia, Jessica Laney, and Amanda Todd are a few other teenage girls who have committed suicide in response to persistent slut shaming.

The tragic impacts of slut shaming can also be seen in many rape cases. Women who are deemed “sluts” are treated as no longer credible witnesses, because if they want sex or have lots of it, it is apparently inconceivable that they might ever not consent to it.  This form of slut shaming was seen in a 2010 gang rape case that was dismissed when it was revealed that the victim had fantasized about group sex. The judge said of the victim, “her credibility was shot to pieces.”  In a 2008 sexual battery case in Georgia, the judge made the victim reveal a litany of intimate details about her sex and dating history. This was used to slut shame and humiliate the victim.

Slut shaming is even wielded against the youngest rape victims. When the New York Times covered of a case in which an 11 year old was gang raped, the paper of record saw fit to focus on the girl’s makeup and clothing. Later in the same case, defense attorney Steve Taylor blamed this 11 year old girl for being gang raped, comparing her to a spider luring men into her web.

And these are just the stories we can read about in the news. But there are likely plenty more instances of rape survivors being slut shamed that we will never read news stories about. After all, 54% of rapes and sexual assaults are never reported to the police, according to data from the National Crime Victimization Survey. This under-reporting can be understood as partially a response to a culture that slut shames and degrades rape survivors who come forward. YouTube user chescaleigh recently posted a video about her experiences with slut shaming after her rape. She provides a powerful look at how rape survivors are slut shamed in the cases that never make it into news media.

And this is why slut shaming ought to be opposed by libertarians. Woods writes that, “The core libertarian value is nonaggression.” I hope we can all agree that rape and sexual assault are clear acts of aggression. Slut shaming and victim blaming are cultural practices that make the victims of this aggression suffer more, all while helping the perpetrators of aggression escape accountability. We should vigorously oppose slut shaming and victim blaming in the same way we should oppose any excuses offered for state violence.

That reminds me: Slut shaming also functions as an excuse for state violence. In particular, it relates closely to the state’s persistent use of violence against sex workers. A recent Human Rights Watch report examined four major US cities where cops will use a woman’s possession of condoms as evidence that she is a sex worker. Because apparently, in the slut shaming minds of police, being prepared to practice safe sex means you’re a prostitute. And apparently being a prostitute means you can be “legitimately” targeted for state aggression. In addition to the usual statist practices of kidnapping people at gun point and locking them in cages, the report also found that police sexually assaulted suspected sex workers. Transgender women were regularly profiled as sex workers, showing how gender stereotypes structure state violence.

Now, none of this necessarily proves that Borowski was in the wrong, as her video did not contain the kind of overtly destructive slut shaming discussed here. Indeed, all she said was that media promotes casual sex and that casual sex is not empowering. It could be argued that Borowski was just making a point that many feminist media critics have also made. However, Borowski made her point in a way that easily could also be seen as denigrating women who choose casual sex and makeup, thus furthering a cultural climate of slut shaming.

But this is not an issue that can simply be dismissed as irrelevant, minor, or “just a joke.” Studies have shown a relationship between sexist humor and sexist attitudes or actions. Casual slut shaming preserves the social environment that makes more severe forms of slut shaming powerful.

Think what you will about Julie Borowski’s video. Whether she promoted slut shaming in it is debatable. But I believe libertarians should conclude that slut shaming, and the social environment it creates, are worth opposing. Because we care deeply about aggression, we should seek a world where aggressors are held accountable and the victims of aggression are not shamed and degraded. Slut shaming stands directly in the way of such a world.

Moreover, as a libertarian I favor human dignity. Slut shaming is a real threat to human dignity. For many teen girls, it means relentless and vicious harassment in public school halls, largely unimpeded by school administrators, who are more likely to punish the victims for their sexuality. As we have seen, this can end in suicide. For rape victims, slut shaming means a shifting of blame. It means their sexual history, their fantasies, and their appearance are all turned into weapons to degrade them when they are already wounded by sexual violence. And for those targeted by police, slut shaming can mean that they will be kidnapped, sexually assaulted, and locked in a cage all under the cover of law. It can even mean that their attempts to practice safe sex become used as evidence to legally justify caging and abusing them. This is what a slut shaming culture looks like. Libertarians must join with feminists to stop it.

Distro of the Libertarian Left
Support C4SS with Roderick T. Long’s “Reclaim the Commons!”

C4SS has teamed up with the Distro of the Libertarian Left. The Distro produces and distribute zines and booklets on anarchism, market anarchist theory, counter-economics, and other movements for liberation. For every copy of Roderick T. Long’s “Reclaim the Commons!: Public Property Without the State” that you purchase through the Distro, C4SS will receive a percentage. Support C4SS with Roderick T. Long’s “Reclaim the Commons!: Public Property Without the State“.

$1.00 for the first copy. $0.75 for every additional copy.

An individualist anarchist analysis and defense of rights to public property — not property that belongs to government, but property that belongs to the public — you and me and our neighbors.

Libertarians often assume that a free society will be one in which all (or nearly all) property is private…. To most people, ‘public property’ means ‘government property.’ As an anarchist, I do not advocate government property of any sort. But this is not the only kind of public property. Throughout history, legal doctrine has recognized, alongside property owned by the the public as organized into a state and represented by government officials, an additional category of property owned by the unorganized public. This was property that the public at large was deemed to have a right of access to, but without any presumption that government would be involved in the matter at all. It is public property in this sense that I am defending….

It is true that private property provides a protected sphere of free decision-making – for the property’s owners. But what is the position of those who are not property owners? A system of exclusively private property certainly does not guarantee them ‘a place to stand.’ Far from providing a sphere of independence, a society in which all property is private thus renders the propertyless completely dependent on those who own property…. It is true that users of public property face a somewhat greater risk from their fellow users than users of private property do. By the same token, however, public property allows more freedom. That is why the best option is a society that makes room for both public and private property. Those who place a high value on security, and are willing to put up with burdensome restrictions in order to get it, will be free to patronize private property, while those who seek self-expression, are averse to restrictions, and are willing to put up with more risk from others will likewise be free to patronize public property….

Anarchy and Democracy
Fighting Fascism
Markets Not Capitalism
The Anatomy of Escape
Organization Theory