Italian, Stateless Embassies
Per la Nostra Terra, Contro il Capitalismo Coloniale ad Aotearoa

Di Henry Laws. Originale pubblicato il 17 febbraio 2020 con il titolo Ihumātao: Reclaiming the land and resisting settler colonial capitalism in Aotearoa/New Zealand. Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.

Art by Huriana Kopeke-Te Aho

Ihumātao, Nuova Zelanda

Ad Aotearoa, uno dei più importanti conflitti sociali è rappresentato dalla lotta delle popolazioni indigene Maori per riavere le proprie terre, rubate dal governo coloniale neozelandese per favorire lacolonizzazione insediativa capitalista di Aotearoa. Iniziata nel 2015, la lotta per la terra ha luogo principalmente a Ihumātao, nella regione di Tāmaki Makaurau/Auckland, dove popolazioni Maori e non hanno dato vita alla campagna Save Our Unique Landscape/SOUL occupando le terre per impedire alla società di costruzioni Fletcher Building di dare inizio ad una lottizzazione socialmente e ambientalmente dannosa e rendere le terre ai mana whenua. La lotta rappresenta l’evento più recente nella lunga storia di Ihumātao.

Ihumātao fu uno dei primi luoghi in cui si insediarono le popolazioni Maori ottocento anni fa. Qui nacque il primo insediamento di Aotearoa, nella zona attualmente conosciuta come  Ōtuataua Stonefields. Ottomila ettari di terra furono coltivati a kūmara, taro, yam e zucche per uso alimentare umano. I Maori fornirono cibo anche ai primi coloni britannici Pākehā quando iniziarono a colonizzare Tāmaki Makaurau, per poi dar vita ad Auckland in seguito alla firma dell’accordo Te Tiriti O Waitangi tra alcuni Maori delle sottotribù hapu e l’impero britannico. Lo spirito di collaborazione tra Maori e Pākehā non durò a lungo. La voglia di accumulare capitale propria del capitalismo spinse il governo neozelandese a fare ricorso a diverse strategie per convertire le terre comuni dei Maori in terre demaniali o private. Per porre in pratica quella che è una versione neozelandese delle britanniche enclosure, l’appropriazione delle terre comuni, il governo ricorse alla Native Land Court, la vendita di terre e la guerra vera e propria.

Le cose precipitarono con la guerra di Waikato, che rientrava tra le guerre neozelandesi iniziate nel 1863 tra il governo neozelandese, guidato dal governatore George Grey, con i suoi alleati MaoriKūpapa/Queenitanga, e il Kingitanga, ovvero il movimento del re, che chiedeva il rispetto dell’accordo di Te Tiriti. Nel corso della guerra, un ufficiale britannico fu mandato a Ihumātao a chiedere che i Maori facessero un giuramento di fedeltà alla corona britannica; in caso contrario, minacciò l’espulsione al Waikato. I Maori rifiutarono l’accordo e in risposta la corona confiscò illegalmente Ihumātao, che nel 1869 fu donata alla famiglia Pākehā dei Wallace al fine di ricavarne un’azienda capitalista, mentre i Maori rimasero senza terre e senza proprietà.

Nel corso del ventesimo secolo, mentre la famiglia Wallace gestiva l’azienda, tra il 1960 e il 2000 nei terreni contigui fu costruito l’impianto per la depurazione delle acque Māngere Wastewater Treatment Plant, che inquina l’aria, l’acqua e il fondo marino, mentre si scavavano le aree vulcaniche per costruire l’aeroporto di Auckland e ampliare la rete stradale. Nel 2009, la costruzione della seconda pista dell’aeroporto ha significato lo sbancamento del cimitero vecchio di sei secoli di urupa, sulla spiaggia di Manukau Harbour, con il disinterramento di 89 tombe. Nel 2012, il consiglio comunale di Auckland ha cercato di trasformare l’area in spazio pubblico, ma l’atto è stato impugnato presso la corte per le questioni ambientali e l’area è stata riqualificata a futuri sviluppi economici. A febbraio la iwi/tribù locale Te Kawerau ā Maki ha firmato un trattato con ilgoverno al fine di sanare le violazioni fatte dal governo all’accordo di Te Tirti. A luglio del 2014, il governo assieme al consiglio comunale di Auckland hanno destinato 32 ettari adiacenti la Otuataua Stonefields Historic Reserve ad area edificabile in vista di futuri sviluppi edilizi.

All’annuncio, nel 2015 il locale Ihumātao Pania Newton, assieme a diversi suoi cugini, ha deciso di formare SOUL con l’intento di fermare la modifica della destinazione d’uso. Nel 2016, la famiglia Wallace ha venduto l’area alla società di costruzioni capitalista Fletcher Building, che aveva in progetto la costruzione di 480 abitazioni. SOUL ha iniziato a novembre del 2016 l’occupazione delle terre chiedendo che la Fletcher Building rinunciasse al suo progetto e che la modifica fosse cancellata. Un mese più tardi, Joe Hawke, leader dell’occupazione di Bastion Point, è andato a sostenere l’occupazione di SOUL e dare consigli. Nei tre anni seguenti, SOUL ha cercato di fermare i programmi della Fletcher in vari modi, ad esempio ricorrendo alle Nazioni Unite, intentando una causa presso la corte ambientale e fare petizioni presso il parlamento di Wellington/Pōneke e il consiglio comunale di Auckland e iniziando una grossa campagna sui social media. Niente di tutto ciò è servito e la Fletcher è andata avanti per la sua strada. In risposta Te Kawerau ā Maki ha fatto un negoziato con la Fletcher per destinare parte dei futuri alloggi agli iwi in cambio del sostegno al piano di sviluppo, dicendo che questo rappresentava il miglior accordo e che SOUL non era mana whenua.

Tolti di mezzo gli ultimi ostacoli, la Fletcher ha iniziato a costruire. Il 23 luglio 2019 la polizia è arrivata a Ihumātao per consegnare gli avvisi di sfratto e arrestare tre manifestanti. A questo punto, i tre anni della campagna di SOUL hanno cominciato a dare i loro frutti, con centinaia di persone arrivate per bloccare Ihumātao e impedire l’inizio dei lavori. Tra loro anche anarchici Tāmaki Makaurau. Vista la prosecuzione del blocco, il governo, dopo aver dichiarato il 24 luglio che non sarebbe intervenuto, due giorni dopo ha annunciato il fermo dei lavori iniziando allo stesso tempo un negoziato tra Te Kawerau ā Maki, la Fletcher e il consiglio comunale di Auckland.

Purtroppo SOUL è rimasta fuori dai negoziati, cosa che l’ha spinta a continuare la protesta, anche perché sia la polizia che la Fletcher restavano a Ihumātao. Il 5 agosto, i protettori/katiaki di Ihumātao riuscivano aspingersi fino ai confini di Ihumātao nonostante la pressione della polizia. Il giorno dopo c’è stata la giornata nazionale dell’azione in solidarietà con le richieste di Ihumātao. Questo è servito a tenere alta la pressione sul governo, mentre i Kingitanga proponevano un hui tra SOUL e Te Kawerau ā Maki al fine di arrivare ad una soluzione accettabile da parte di tutti.

Mentre continuavano i negoziati, e il blocco andava avanti, gran parte della polizia il 16 agosto andava via da Ihumātao, e SOUL organizzava una hikoi/marcia diretta verso l’ufficio del ministro Jacinda Ardern di Mount Albert per costringerla a presentarsi a Ihumātao, cosa che non ha fatto. I negoziati sono terminati il 18 settembre con  SOUL e Te Kawerau  ā Maki che concordavano che Ihumātao sarebbe stata restituita a mana whenua. Dalla metà di settembre del 2019, i negoziati hanno ripreso, pur con l’esclusione di SOUL. C’erano comunque segnali positivi che facevano pensare che la risoluzione era in vista: il sedici novembre il governo ha annunciato di voler concedere un prestito al comune di Auckland per l’acquisto di Ihumātao al fine di trasformare l’area in uno spazio pubblico, mentre Pania Newton il 23 dicembre annunciava l’imminenza di unarisoluzione. L’annuncio per Ihumātao è arrivato come un Meri Kirhimete, Buon Natale.

Il 2020 è iniziato bene con la Fletcher che ha rimosso le recinzioni da Ihumātao. La risoluzione dovrebbe arrivare prima di Waitangi Day, con i Kingitangi che ammainano la loro bandiera per simboleggiare la fine della loro lotta. Waitangi Day 2020 è arrivato e ancora nessuna risoluzione. Il Kingitanga ha comunque annunciato che una risoluzione è imminente, ma che occorre ancora finalizzare la risoluzione, pertanto la lotta potrebbe essere giunta alla fine.

A posteriori, la campagna di SOUL #Protect Ihumātao appare un grosso successo, con i protagonisti che riescono a trasformare una piccola richiesta in una campagna che invitava all’azione diretta, la quale a sua volta si è trasformata in un movimento di massa che a Tāmaki Makaurau e Aotearoa puntava a fermare la lottizzazione della Fletcher, il tutto sostenuto da un eccellente campagna sui social. La lotta ha portato anche ad un diverso approccio nei confronti dei Maori, con le nuove generazioni che confidano sull’azione diretta per riavere le terre rubate piuttosto che sui negoziati tra le strutture aziendali iwi (ad esclusione di hapu) e il governo, con conseguente accordo su una compensazione monetaria e la restituzione di terre demaniali, il che serve solo ad arricchire una nuova classe capitalista Maori. Ma la lotta non è finita, l’azione del governo deve essere vista con scetticismo, è chiaro che farà di tutto per evitare che la disputa in questione sia usata come precedente per futuri accordi sulla restituzione ai Maori di terre private. Se si dovesse arrivare ad altre decisioni simili, tutte le terre rubate ad Aotearoa potrebbero tornare ai Maori, destabilizzando una delle colonne portanti del colonialismo capitalista, ovvero la proprietà privata o demaniale delle terre. Nonostante tutto, la campagna SOUL ha finalmente realizzato il grido di battaglia della lotta anticoloniale del rangatira/capo Maori Rewi Maniapoto durante la guerra di Waikato: ‘Ka whawhai tonu mātou, Ake! Ake! Ake! (Continueremo a combattere sempre! Sempre! Sempre!).

Feature Articles
Ihumātao: Reclaiming the land and resisting settler colonial capitalism in Aotearoa/New Zealand

Artist: Huriana Kopeke-Te Aho

In Aotearoa, one of the major forms of social struggle is the indigenous Māori struggling to reclaim the land stolen from them by the New Zealand colonial government as part of the capitalist settler colonisation of Aotearoa. Since 2015, the greatest land struggle in a decade has been happening at Ihumātao in Tāmaki Makaurau/Auckland, where Māori and non-Māori from the Save Our Unique Landscape/SOUL campaign have been occupying the land to stop the capitalist construction firm Fletcher Building from beginning a socially and environmentally harmful housing development and return the land to mana whenua. This land struggle is the most recent event in Ihumātao’s long history.

800 years ago, Ihumātao was one of the first places where Māori arrived and established settlements in Aotearoa, in the area now known as the Ōtuataua Stonefields. There, they cultivated 8,000 hectares of land to grow kūmara, taro, yams and gourds to feed themselves. They also fed the British settlers/Pākehā when they began to colonise Tāmaki Makaurau to create Auckland following the signing of Te Tiriti O Waitangi between some Māori hapu/sub-tribes and the British Empire. However, such co-operation between Māori and Pākehā did not last, as the drive to accumulate capital inherent to capitalism led to the New Zealand government using various means to transform communal Māori land into state and private land, including the Native Land Court, land sales and war, in Aotearoa’s version of the enclosure of the commons.

This came to a head when the Waikato War, part of the broader New Zealand Wars, began in 1863 between the New Zealand government, led by Governor George Grey, their Māori allies the Kūpapa/Queenitanga and the Kingitanga/King movement that wanted Te Tiriti to be honoured, began. During the war, a British official was sent to Ihumātao and demanded that the Māori there take an oath of allegiance to the Crown and give up arms or be expelled to the Waikato. The Māori there refused, and in response the Crown illegally confiscated Ihumātao and in 1869 gave it to a Pākehā family – the Wallaces – to be developed into a capitalist farm, while the Māori there were left landless and destitute.

Over the course of the 20th century, while the Wallaces were running their farm, in the surrounding land from 1960 to 2000 the Māngere Wastewater Treatment Plant was built, polluting the air, water and sea bed, and volcanoes are quarried for airport construction and Auckland’s road network. In 2009, Auckland Airport’s second runway construction led to the bulldozing of a 600 year old urupa/grave site on the Manukau Harbour foreshore, unearthing 89 graves. In 2012, Auckland Council tried to make the land a public space, but this was challenged in the Environment Court and they had to rezone the land for future economic development. In February 2014, the local iwi/tribe Te Kawerau ā Maki signed a treaty settlement with the Government to settle breaches of Te Tirti by the Government. In July 2014, the Government and Auckland Council designated 32 hectares adjacent to the Otuataua Stonefields Historic Reserve as Special Housing Area/SHA 62 for a future housing development.

When this was announced, Ihumātao local Pania Newton, along with several of her cousins, formed SOUL in 2015 to stop the rezoning. In 2016, the Wallaces sold the land to capitalist construction firm Fletcher Building, which planned to construct 480 homes. In response, in November 2016 SOUL began their occupation of the land and demanded that Fletcher Building end their plans and that SHA 62 be dissolved. A month later, Joe Hawke, leader of the Bastion Point occupation, visited to support the occupation and provide advice. For the next three years, SOUL would use a diversity of tactics to try and stop Fletcher’s plans, including going to the United Nations, taking Fletcher’s to the Environment Court as well as taking petitions to Parliament in Wellington/Pōneke and to Auckland Council with this all being complemented with an extensive social media campaign. However, none of these measures succeeded, with Fletcher’s development going ahead. In response, Te Kawerau ā Maki negotiated with Fletcher Building to set aside some of the homes to be for the iwi and then supported the development, claiming that this was the best deal possible and that SOUL weren’t mana whenua.

With no more obstacles facing it, Fletcher’s now tried to begin construction at Ihumātao. Police were sent on 23rd July 2019 to Ihumātao to serve eviction notices and arrest three protestors. When this happened, the three years of SOUL’s campaigning now bore fruit, with hundreds arriving to blockade Ihumātao to prevent construction from beginning. Members from Tāmaki Makaurau Anarchists being amongst them. Due to holding this blockade the Government, after initially saying that they wouldn’t intervene on 24th July then said on 26th July that construction at Ihumātao would stop while a solution was being negotiated between Te Kawerau ā Maki, Fletchers and Auckland Council.

Unfortunately SOUL was not invited to negotiations and they continued the blockade due to this as well as due to the Police and Fletcher’s remaining at Ihumātao, with the katiaki/protectors of Ihumātao being able to push the blockade line closer to Ihumātao while also facing an increased police presence by 5th August. On the following day, there was a national day of actions in solidarity with the reclamation of Ihumātao. This helped keep pressure on Fletcher’s and the Government after the Kingitanga offered to hold a hui between SOUL and Te Kawerau ā Maki to come to a common position on Ihumātao that both sides accepted.

As the negotiations continued, the blockade held, with the majority of the Police withdrawing from Ihumātao on 16th August, while SOUL organised a hikoi/march to Prime Minister Jacinda Ardern’s Mount Albert office to get her to visit Ihumātao, which she refused to do. The negotiations ended on 18th September, with SOUL and Te Kawerau ā Maki agreeing that Ihumātao should be returned to mana whenua. Since mid-September 2019, negotiations have continued, although SOUL have been locked out of them. There are positive signs that a resolution may be reached soon however, with the Government stating on 16th November that it’s considering loaning Auckland Council money to purchase Ihumātao from Fletcher’s to turn it into a public space, while Pania Newton announced on 23rd December that a resolution would be announced soon. This great news led to Ihumātao having a very Meri Kirhimete/Merry Christmas in 2019.

The struggle for Ihumātao in 2020 started well with Fletcher’s removing their fences at Ihumātao. In addition, there was an expectation that a resolution would be reached before Waitangi Day, with the Kingitangi lowering their flag from Ihumātao to symbolise, as their work in helping to resolve this struggle had finished. Unfortunately, Waitangi Day 2020 came and went without a resolution being announced. However, the Kingitanga has said that a resolution was imminent, but that some work still needed to be done to finalise the resolution, so this long struggle may at last be coming to an end.

Looking back, SOUL’s campaign to #Protect Ihumātao has been a phenomenal success, with them being able to transform their initially small reclamation action into a direct action campaign that has created a mass movement in Tāmaki Makaurau and across Aotearoa to stop Fletcher’s housing development backed by an excellent social media campaign. It’s also led to a new approach to Māori politics, with a new generation seeking to engage in direct action to return stolen land instead of relying on corporate iwi structures (to the exclusion of hapu) negotiating with the Government to get treaty settlements that provide monetary compensation and only return Government land, enriching a new Māori capitalist class. However, this struggle has not yet ended, and the Government’s actions must be viewed with scepticism, as they will do anything to stop this dispute being used to as precedent to return private land to Māori in future treaty settlements. If that happens, then all stolen land in Aotearoa could possibly be returned to Māori, destabilising one of the pillars of settler colonial capitalism in Aotearoa: private and state land ownership. No matter what happens, SOUL’s campaign to reclaim Ihumātao has put into practice the anti-colonial cry from the Māori rangatira/chief Rewi Maniapoto during the Waikato War: ‘Ka whawhai tonu mātou, Ake! Ake! Ake! – We will fight on for ever and ever!’

Italian, Stateless Embassies
Il Libero Mercato del Lavoro e Altre Fole Capitaliste

Di Kevin Carson. Originale pubblicato l’undici febbraio 2020 con il titolo The Free Labor Market and Other Capitalist Just-So Stories. Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.

Alcuni anni fa coniai l’espressione “libertarismo volgare” per indicare quella forma particolare, singolarmente odiosa, di analisi fatta dai libertari di destra. Sul mio blog ormai perlopiù inattivo pubblicai una serie di articoli (“Vulgar Libertarianism Watch”) in cui applicavo il concetto ad una massa enorme di questo pattume articolistico. Ad un certo punto, visto che non c’era più nulla, ho lasciato perdere. Ma poi sono incappato nella madre di tutti i libertarismi volgari — “The Exploitation of Labor and Other Union Myths,” by Mark S. Pulliam (The INDEPENDENT REVIEW, Winter 2019/20) — e non ho resistito alla tentazione di slacciarmi la cinta e riprendere l’attività.

“Libertarismo volgare” parafrasava in parte il marxismo volgare della Seconda e Terza Internazionale che, da Engels e Kautsky in poi, trasformò il “materialismo storico” nella parodia di se stesso. Ma alludeva anche a quella che Marx chiamava “economia politica volgare” della generazione dopo Ricardo e Mill. Così Marx indicava quegli economisti che, dopo aver rinunciato a spiegare scientificamente le leggi dell’economia, diventarono i “pugili professionisti” degli interessi plutocratici. In origine, l’economia politica era una critica radicale del parassitismo dei proprietari terrieri e della rendita del capitalismo. Negli anni 1830, con il trionfo del capitalismo industriale in Gran Bretagna, l’attenzione si spostò dall’indagine scientifica, dalla sfida radicale al potere economico concentrato, ad un’apologia della situazione attuale.

Ecco una mia prima esposizione della cosa:

Questa scuola libertaria ha scritto sul proprio stemma le parole d’ordine reazionarie: “Tutto l’aiuto possibile a quei poveracci dei padroni.” Qualunque sia l’argomento, è facile indovinare chi sono i buoni e chi i cattivi; basta invertire lo slogan de La Fattoria degli Animali: “Due gambe buono, quattro zampe cattivo.” I buoni, le vittime sacrificali dello Stato Progressista, sono sempre i ricchi e potenti. I cattivi sono i consumatori e i lavoratori che si arricchiscono con soldi pubblici. A mo’ di esempio principale di questa tendenza, pensate a come Ayn Rand descrive le grandi aziende come una “minoranza oppressa”, e il complesso industriale-militare come “un mito, o peggio”.

Secondo loro, apparentemente, l’ideale di società di “libero mercato” non è altro che il capitalismo così com’è meno lo stato sociale e normativo: una versione ipertiroidea del capitalismo dei baroni ladri dell’Ottocento, forse; o, meglio, una “società riformata” da persone come Pinochet, il Dioniso a cui Milton Friedman e i Chicago Boys facevano da Aristotele.

I libertari volgari apologeti del capitalismo danno all’espressione “libero mercato” un significato ambiguo: sembrano incapaci di ricordare, da un momento all’altro, se stanno difendendo i principi del libero mercato o il capitalismo esistente. È così che arrivano a scrivere articoli chiusi, standardizzati, in cui sostengono che i ricchi non possono arricchirsi a spese dei poveri perché “non è così che il libero mercato funziona”, dando per scontato che questo che abbiamo sia libero mercato. Se costretti, ammettono a denti stretti che l’attuale sistema non è un libero mercato, e che lo stato interviene spesso a favore dei ricchi. Detto questo, però, tornano a difendere le ricchezze delle aziende sulla base dei “principi del libero mercato”.

In questi termini, l’articolo di Pulliam è libertarismo volgare al 99,9%: difende l’attuale sistema, apparentemente basato sui “principi di libero mercato” come se la nostra fosse quella società di libero mercato che non è mai esistita.

Questo è particolarmente vero se consideriamo le caratteristiche centrali del libertarismo: l’uso del linguaggio e delle teorie dell’economia di libero mercato per difendere l’attuale capitalismo reale. Pulliam non fa altro che dire, dall’inizio alla fine, che lo sfruttamento del lavoro nell’attuale sistema capitalista è impossibile, ma lo fa con tutta una serie di qualificativi e subordinate che indicano come in realtà pensi ad una società da manuale che non è mai esistita.

Dice: “come scrivono i progressisti accademici, la storia dei sindacati americani è finzione tanto quanto le favole di Esopo e dei fratelli Grimm.” Ma la storia del capitalismo e delle associazioni di lavoratori, così come viene descritta a sinistra, fa riferimento ad un mondo realmente esistito, ed è il “sistema di libero mercato” elogiato da Pulliam ad essere reale quanto il paese dei balocchi. Tutto il suo mondo è immaginario. Ad esempio:

L’autoproprietà porta a riconoscere l’istituzione della proprietà privata. In una società libera, una persona è padrona di ciò che produce o acquisisce tramite scambio consensuale. Entrando a far parte della società civile, in virtù di un fittizio (ma necessario) contratto sociale, la persona cede alcuni dei suoi diritti naturali in cambio della protezione della legge. Le nostre costituzioni statali e federale pongono i termini di tale “scambio”.

No, storicamente parlando il riconoscimento della proprietà privata è avvenuto con le enclosure (l’appropriazione delle proprietà comuni, es) e l’aiuto dello stato. L’idea di un diritto di proprietà privata che nasce dall’unione del proprio lavoro con una proprietà inutilizzata è una sciocchezza abissale inventata da Locke per giustificare la proprietà – acquisita col furto – degli aristocratici whig che lo pagavano per scrivere queste cose. In questo, lui e Pulliam sono molto simili.

E questo è solo l’inizio. Guardate tutte le subordinate poste qua e là quando spiega come, secondo lui, funziona la nostra società di “libero mercato”: “In una società basata sulla libertà individuale, uno stato minimo e la protezione della proprietà privata…” “in un libero mercato [i salari] sarebbero il frutto di uno scambio consensuale tra acquirente (il datore) e venditore (il dipendente) risultato di una competizione.” “In una società libera, una relazione di lavoro deve avvenire tra parti consensuali secondo termini accettati da entrambi, senza frodi o coercizioni.” “…in una società libera…” “In un mercato concorrenziale…” “Nel mondo del libero mercato…” “Ad ogni modo, esiste un’inerente disuguaglianza tra lavoratori e capitale? I classici modelli economici dicono di no.” (Lasciamo perdere il fatto che i classici modelli economici non descrivono nulla che non sia il prodotto della mente degli economisti). “Finché c’è concorrenza tra acquirenti e venditori, e assenza di costrizioni esterne…” “In assenza di potere di monopsonio (vedi qui, es)…” “L’unica cosa importante è che la concorrenza avvenga tra partecipanti non sottoposti a costrizioni.” E poi (ancora): “In una società libera…” Insomma, ogni volta che spiega come funzionano le cose deve metterci una subordinata con delle condizioni che non sono mai esistite nella società.

Tutte le frasi citate descrivono una società mitica che non è mai esistita fuori dalla propaganda legittimante del capitalismo. La concentrazione del potere in poche mani, la separazione del lavoro dalla proprietà dei mezzi di produzione e l’affermazione del sistema salariale non sono il risultato di una “originale accumulazione di capitale” frutto della frugalità. La concentrazione della proprietà terriera nelle mani di possidenti assenteisti non è il frutto di alcuni coloni che hanno unito il proprio lavoro alla terra. Il dominio della produzione e dello scambio delle merci, assieme al nesso di cassa, non è frutto della “propensione a barattare” o dello scambio monetario quale soluzione del “problema della mutua coincidenza dei voleri”. Noi non viviamo in una società di libero mercato originata da un “contratto sociale” per cui le persone si accordano su un governo dai poteri limitati a protezione della vita, la liberà e la proprietà.

Nessuna delle caratteristiche base dell’attuale sistema capitalista è nata come dicono le favole dei libertari di destra, così come i tuoi genitori non ti hanno trovato sotto un cavolo.

La stragrande maggioranza delle terre dell’Inghilterra medievale, fatta eccezione per quelle del re, della chiesa e della nobiltà, era proprietà comune sotto forma di campi aperti i cui diritti di possesso temporaneo venivano ridistribuiti periodicamente tra gli abitanti del villaggio, tranne una parte a pascolo comune e un’altra incolta. I contadini furono derubati, a forza, di questi diritti di possesso dei loro mezzi di sussistenza, prima con la graduale chiusura dei campi aperti avvenuta alla fine del Medio Evo, e poi tramite il parlamento che stabilì la chiusura di pascoli comuni, boschi e terre incolte a partire dal diciottesimo secolo, a vantaggio dei grossi possidenti terrieri locali. Fu così che nacque una classe lavoratrice senza proprietà che poi fu gettata nel mercato del lavoro salariato con l’unica possibilità di accettare un lavoro a qualunque termine.

Questo furto fu portato avanti nell’interesse degli agricoltori capitalisti che sostenevano, come spiega la letteratura politica del tempo, che, finché avesse avuto accesso indipendente ai mezzi di sussistenza, la popolazione rurale avrebbe rifiutato il lavoro salariato, oppure si sarebbe rifiutata di lavorare così tante ore e per una paga così bassa come quella offerta dalle classi possidenti.

Fu con l’ascesa del capitalismo agrario, le enclosure, l’affitto gravato del profitto e l’esproprio che fu creata la prima forza lavoro, pronta per essere poi usata dal capitalismo industriale.

E lo stato era più che disposto, fin dalle prime appropriazioni, a bastonare gli spossessati contadini per spingerli ad accettare una qualche forma di lavoro salariato. Queste pratiche risalgono alle leggi dei Tudor contro il vagabondaggio, che costringevano le “canaglie recalcitranti” ad accettare qualunque lavoro a qualunque termine gli fosse offerto, pena il taglio delle orecchie o peggio. E durante la Rivoluzione Industriale le Leggi sugli Insediamenti vietavano ai lavoratori di uscire dalla propria parrocchia per cercare un lavoro a condizioni migliori. Intanto le autorità parrocchiali, create dalla Legge sulla Povertà, radunavano disoccupati per mandarli da una parrocchia all’altra ed essere letteralmente acquistati all’asta da industriali di aree carenti di manodopera come Manchester. Tra l’ultimo decennio del settecento e i primi due dell’ottocento, inoltre, la classe lavoratrice fu soggetta non solo alle Combination Acts (che vietavano le associazioni di lavoratori, es) ma anche a tutta una serie di leggi poliziesche che proibivano società di mutuo soccorso e assembramenti di qualunque genere – tutto imposto amministrativamente senza giusto processo – con la scusa della “sicurezza nazionale” durante le Guerre Napoleoniche.

La situazione è stata riassunta accuratamente da J.L. e Barbara Hammond: La società inglese fu “smontata… e poi rifatta, come un dittatore rifà uno stato libero”, a tutto beneficio dei capitalisti.

Contrariamente al mito propagandato da Mises e altri, l’accumulazione capitalista non fu il prodotto delle privazioni di piccoli proprietari che vivevano nella frugalità e lavoravano duramente da buoni protestanti. Questi sobri, frugali capitalisti, laddove esistevano, rappresentavano la facciata dei soci nascosti dell’oligarchia terriera o delle aziende mercantili che fornivano gran parte del capitale da investire.

Dunque quella relazione “di libero mercato” tra datore e lavoratore che negoziano il salario tra pari, “senza frode o coercizioni”, eccetera eccetera eccetera, come diceva Ayn Rand, la mamma di Mises, era in realtà un negoziato tra i derubati e i ladri, o gli eredi, o gli assegnatari di roba rubata. E grazie alla protezione garantita dalla stato del “diritto di proprietà” dei ladri sul bottino, oltre a tutte le forme di rendita parassitaria e sostegno pubblico ancora esistenti, le strutture che garantiscono la disuguaglianza riprodottesi fino ai giorni nostri.

Quasi tutto ciò che Pulliam e altri libertari di destra, nella loro immaginaria società di libero mercato “naturale”, danno per scontato, come se fosse il risultato di un ordine spontaneo emergente, è anch’esso il risultato di un’imposizione dall’alto da parte delle forze preponderanti dello stato in collusione con le classi possidenti. Che uno ci creda o meno, la “proprietà privata” assoluta della terra non risale alla preistoria. La proprietà della terra, nel periodo che va dalla rivoluzione del neolitico all’ascesa dello stato, si basava quasi ovunque sul modello dei campi aperti proprietà comune del villaggio. Questo modello fu eliminato con la forza: in Inghilterra con i sistemi citati, in Bengala da Warren Hastings, in Russia dal doppio colpo di Stolypin e Stalin, nell’Africa Orientale britannica con il disboscamento, e così via fino alla nausea, all’infinito, senza fine, amen. E come spiega David Graeber in Debt, anche l’organizzazione della società attorno allo scambio di merci e la moneta metallica furono imposizioni – anch’esse violente – dello stato agli inizi dell’epoca moderna.

In breve, tutto il quadro dipinto da Pulliam, per cui il sistema capitalista nasce dalla “libera società” basata su un contratto sociale su cui fonda un governo dai poteri limitati a protezione della proprietà e dei contratti, in cui i lavoratori contrattano il salario con i datori sulla base della loro produttività sul mercato libero, in cui nessuna frode o coercizione ha reso possibile la divisione del lavoro, assieme a tutte le altre invenzioni dei capitalisti, tutto questo, in sostanza, non è che un mucchio di letame fumante. Il nostro è un sistema imposto dall’alto e mantenuto immobile fino ad oggi tramite l’uso massiccio della forza a livello mondiale e per alcuni secoli. Il capitalismo, quello storicamente esistente, non è opera della “mano invisibile”, ma del pugno di ferro.

Ma gli errori fattuali della critica di Pulliam non si limitano all’offuscamento delle vere origini del capitalismo e del sistema salariale. Riguardo i sindacati, ad esempio, ripete tutti i soliti luoghi comuni dei libertari di destra:

Un sindacato opera essenzialmente come un cartello, fissa il prezzo del lavoro dei suoi associati con la collusione interna invece di ricorrere alla concorrenza sul mercato, così come i paesi membri dell’Opec impongono a forza l’aumento del prezzo del petrolio invece di lasciare che sia il mercato a stabilirlo. L’accordo interno sul prezzo del lavoro è chiamato “contrattazione collettiva”.

Come l’Opec, il sindacato minaccia di negare la fornitura se chi compra non acconsente a pagare il prezzo “fissato”. Questo negare la fornitura si chiama “sciopero”. A differenza dell’Opec, però, il sindacato cerca di impedire ad altri venditori (non soci del cartello), anche con la minaccia della forza, di vendere ad un prezzo più basso. Questa pratica è chiamata “picchettaggio”. Gli scioperanti non solo negano collettivamente i loro servizi (il che è consensuale), ma cercano anche di impedire (con la forza o la costrizione) che altri rompano il picchettaggio. I sindacati chiamano questi altrilavoratori “crumiri”, ma si tratta semplicemente di venditori disposti ad accettare un salario inferiore – effetto della concorrenza e dello scambio consensuale –, cosa del tutto legittima in una società libera…

Inoltre i sindacati, a differenza dell’Opec, dipendono dalla forza costrittiva dello stato. Le leggi federali obbligano i datori a “riconoscere” un sindacato una volta che questo è stato “scelto” da una maggioranza dei lavoratori; obbligano i datori a negoziare unicamente col sindacato prima di prendere delle decisioni riguardanti i dipendenti; vietano ai datori di licenziare i dipendenti che svolgono attività sindacale; e vietano ai datori di sostituire il personale in sciopero in date circostanze.

Come tutti quelli che parlano così, Pulliam non conosce affatto la vera storia delle lotte dei lavoratori. Uno dei simpatici “miti” moderni che secondo Pulliam occorrere rivedere è questo: “Lo schema di contrattazione collettiva previsto dalla Wagner Act è impeccabile”; da questo si capisce che il suo obiettivo principale sono i liberal, non la sinistra o i socialisti.

A leggere quello che scrive, non sapresti mai che il tradizionale sciopero di massa e l’esclusione dei crumiri in origine non era né l’unica né la principale arma nelle mani dei lavoratori. A criticare l’efficacia degli scioperi tradizionali troviamo nientemeno che il sindacato degli Industrial Workers of the World. Invece di dare l’opportunità ai capi di chiuderti fuori e ingaggiare i crumiri, è molto più efficace manifestare sul posto di lavoro rallentando l’attività, con lo sciopero bianco, andando in malattia a macchia di leopardo, oppure spiegando ai clienti come il datore di lavoro risparmia sulla qualità del prodotto.

A leggere Pulliam, non si viene a sapere che la Wagner Act non serviva solo a vietare ai datori di fare certe cose. Cosa molto più importante, vietava ai lavoratori di fare molte altre cose: tutte quelle forme di azione diretta citate più su e molto altro. E questo era il suo obiettivo principale.

L’obiettivo centrale della Wagner Act era: addomesticare le organizzazioni dei lavoratori, demandando alle burocrazie sindacali, con il loro inquadramento, il compito di far rispettare i contratti di lavoro evitando l’azione diretta e gli scioperi selvaggi. Vietava soprattutto le pratiche più efficaci, perché più distruttive per i datori di lavoro, limitando l’attività dei sindacati agli scioperi convenzionali.

Quando fu approvata la Wagner, la principale componente aziendale della coalizione del New Deal era composta da industrie pesanti orientate all’esportazione e ad alta intensità di capitale. Data la necessità di pianificare per il lungo termine e di predire i risultati, la produzione industriale di massa di allora soffriva particolarmente le interruzioni; e il periodo precedente la Wagner fu particolarmente ricco di interruzioni della produzione. Allo stesso tempo, data la forte intensità di capitale e la prevalenza sui mercati industriali di prezzi imposti, le aziende potevano concedere grossi aumenti salariali senza tanti sacrifici.

Nelle sue linee essenziali, il regime introdotto dalla Wagner era praticamente identico alla situazione esistente con i sindacati aziendali dell’American Plan sviluppato secondo il modello di stato sociale capitalista degli anni venti. Con l’American Plan – tra i cui proponenti di spicco c’era Gerard Swope della General Electric, figura centrale anche della politica industriale di F.D. Roosevelt – ai lavoratori venivano garantiti periodici aumenti di stipendio legati alla produttività, riconoscimento dell’anzianità e diritto di rivendicazione. In cambio i dirigenti ottennero il riconoscimento del diritto di dirigere e ai capi sindacali fu demandato il compito di far rispettare i contratti e tenere in riga i lavoratori sul lavoro.

La reazione istintiva di Pulliam e di altri libertari simili vuole chiaramente, oltre al resto, denunciare come violazione dei diritti dei datori tutte quelle forme di azione diretta citate prima. Ma fermiamoci un attimo a riflettere sulle implicazioni di una relazione di lavoro con contratto incompleto. Questo è quello che dicono Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis:

Si stabilisce una relazione di lavoro quando, in cambio di un salario, il lavoratore B acconsente a sottomettersi all’autorità del datore A per uno specifico lasso di tempo in cambio del salario W. Mentre la promessa del datore di dare un salario è legalmente imponibile, la promessa del lavoratore di concedere un livello adeguato di sforzo e accuratezza, anche se promesso, non si può imporre. Il lavoro è per il lavoratore soggettivamente oneroso da fornire, prezioso per il datore e costoso da misurare. Il rapporto datore-lavoratore, dunque, rappresenta uno scambio controverso.

L’espressione “sforzo adeguato” non significa nulla tranne come viene interpretata nella pratica sulla base del relativo potere contrattuale del lavoratore e del datore. È praticamente impossibile specificare in un contratto a priori il livello di sforzo e la rendita di un lavoratore salariato, così come è impossibile per un datore di lavoro monitorare la rendita a posteriori. Ecco perché il luogo di lavoro rappresenta un campo controverso, e il lavoratore, così come il datore, è pienamente nei suoi diritti quando cerca di massimizzare i propri interessi entro i margini ampi di un contratto incompleto. Quanto sforzo è da considerarsi “normale” si vede solo nel contesto sociale all’interno di un luogo di lavoro, considerati gli equilibri di potere in un dato momento. E questo comprende eventuali rallentamenti, atteggiamenti “prudenziali” e altro simile.

Lo sforzo “normale” a cui ha diritto un datore, quando acquista forza lavoro, è una questione di convenzioni. Cosa significhi livello equo di sforzo è una questione culturale del tutto soggettiva che può essere determinata solo in virtù della reale forza contrattuale di lavoratori e datori in un particolare luogo di lavoro. Il sistema è molto simile all’interpretazione contestualizzata e localizzata (come la “ragionevole aspettativa” in particolari mercati) di norme riguardanti contratti impliciti, frodi e altro, in assenza di regole stabilite dallo stato. Se i libertari amano pensare che una “paga equa” è un concetto interpretabile, a discrezione del datore e limitato a ciò che questi può dare, dovrebbero ricordare che anche un “lavoro equo” è ugualmente interpretabile.

Immagino che Pulliam e quelli che pensano come lui risponderebbero che il lavoratore è moralmente obbligato a lavorare al massimo e ad obbedire agli ordini a prescindere dall’applicabilità di ciò. Ma la cosa non merita attenzione. L’idea di lavorare sempre al massimo è ridicola: significherebbe farsi male e sarebbe insostenibile sul lungo termine. Se poi ci mettiamo gli aggettivi “ragionevole” o “sostenibile” torniamo alla succitata questione della fattibilità. Quanto all’obbedienza incondizionata, è meglio che lascino perdere visto che è la tattica, molto efficace, su cui si basa lo sciopero bianco. In pratica, la produttività sul posto di lavoro dipende da quanto il lavoratore considera gli obblighi contrattuali un male da aggirare al fine di tenere in piedi l’attività nonostante le direttive.

A parte ciò, la minaccia anche solo di uno sciopero convenzionale ha valore se non si escludono i crumiri con la forza. Ci sono rendite naturali tacite che derivano da tre cose: la forza lavoro acquisisce una certa conoscenza del processo produttivo, la produttività dipende dal “capitale sociale” incorporato nelle relazioni costruite col tempo, e rimpiazzare la forza lavoro comporta dei costi. Quest’ultimo ha dei costi particolarmente alti perché le gerarchie di potere favoriscono l’accumulo di conoscenze specifiche nelle mani dei lavoratori, conoscenze che restano fuori dalla portata dei dirigenti. Ricostruire queste conoscenze, manuali e di altro tipo, nonché il rapporto sociale, è un compito duro che richiede anni. Mises pensava che la contabilità a partita doppia trasformasse l’“imprenditore” in un pianificatore onnisciente, un’idiozia contro cui vale leggere Oliver Williamson e altri Neo-Istituzionalisti.

Se qualcuno ha dubbi sull’efficacia di queste conoscenze tacite, su quanto il profitto dipende dall’accaparramento di tali conoscenze nonché dell’intelletto collettivo dei lavoratori, basta che vada a rileggere ciò che ho scritto sull’efficacia dello sciopero bianco, con cui il lavoratore esegue alla lettera le stupidità del management.

Altre parti delle leggi federali sul lavoro, come il divieto dello sciopero di solidarietà o di boicottaggio e il potere presidenziale di imporre “periodi di riflessione” secondo la Taft-Hartley, mirano ugualmente a tarpare le ali delle organizzazioni dei lavoratori e a privarli del potere che avrebbero anche senza l’imposizione della contrattazione collettiva della Wagner. I grandi scioperi regionali precedenti la Wagner richiedevano la coordinazione a monte e a valle delle catene di fornitura e distribuzione, per cui i lavoratori dei trasporti svolgevano un ruolo chiave nel trasformare lo sciopero di una singola industria in uno sciopero generale. L’effetto cumulativo di una concatenazione di scioperi anche solo parziali presso fabbriche, fornitori, grossisti, magazzini, dettaglianti, e poi gli scaricatori che rifiutavano di scaricare merci trasportate da crumiri per portarle dai fornitori alle fabbriche o dalle fabbriche ai rivenditori, tutto ciò, aggiunto al boicottaggio dei consumatori sull’onda degli scioperi, poteva avere effetti devastanti.

Il regime imposto dalla Wagner Act e tutte le altre leggi federali era in realtà un patto col diavolo che obbligava i lavoratori a deporre le armi più efficaci per limitarsi a qualche sciopero dichiarato alla scadenza di un contratto. Un po’ come chiedere ad un gruppo di cospiratori di sfilare in piazza. In cambio, ricevevano quello che già ricevevano tramite i sindacati aziendali con l’American Plan: aumenti legati alla produttività, riconoscimento dell’anzianità e diritto di rivendicazione. Quali vantaggi per i datori di lavoro? Niente più scioperi selvaggi, niente rallentamenti, malattie strategiche, scioperi bianchi e rivendicazioni personali, tutto imposto dai burocrati dei sindacati diventati il socio delle dirigenze. Queste ultime ottennero stabilità sul lungo termine, predicibilità produttiva, una disciplina sul lavoro imposta dagli stessi sindacati e, cosa più importante, il riconoscimento dei sindacati del “diritto dei dirigenti di dirigere”.

Anche Henry Hazlitt, che formula inizialmente questi punti in Economics in One Lesson, ammette che i sindacati potevano essere utili alla formazione dei prezzi fintanto che le conoscenze imperfette lasciavano il lavoratore all’oscuro della reale produttività del suo lavoro. Ma ad Hazlitt bisogna riconoscere un po’ di onestà intellettuale, almeno rispetto a Pulliam.

Quanto alla storia del capitalismo, Pulliam scrive la stessa robaccia.

Prima dell’industrializzazione e della divisione del lavoro sotto forma di specializzazione del lavoro, quasi tutti lavoravano la terra. Chi lavorava la propria terra aveva diritto al raccolto. Chi lavorava la terra di qualcun altro, o ne pagava l’affitto oppure divideva il raccolto col proprietario della terra. Con il tempo, i fabbri, gli scalpellini, i tessitori e altri acquisivano le risorse per comprarsi gli strumenti di lavoro e le materie prime, oppure si affidavano a qualcuno che fornisse loro i beni strumentali. Nel primo caso, l’artigiano era padrone di se stesso; nel secondo, era un apprendista o lavorava alle dipendenze di un altro. Il lavoratore doveva dividere il frutto del suo lavoro con chi gli forniva il capitale in termini convenienti ad entrambi. Da qui nasce concettualmente la moderna relazione di lavoro…

Con l’avvento della Rivoluzione Industriale, chi per secoli aveva tratto sostentamento – talvolta a stento o per niente – dalla produzione agricola ad alta intensità di lavoro, passò sempre più allafabbrica. Fu un cambiamento epocale. La tecnologia, spinta dagli investimenti e dalla ricerca del profitto, trasformò l’economia. Fabbriche, macchine, innovazioni e invenzioni (compresa la macchina a vapore) produssero drammatici cambiamenti sociali. … Spesso la popolazione migrava per andare dove c’erano opportunità. Il calo della mortalità portò ad una grossa crescita demografica. Il capitalismo trasformò molti aspetti della società, perlopiù in termini molto positivi.

Forse la relazione di lavoro “nasce concettualmente” così nella testa dei padroni e dei loro propagandisti a pagamento. Nella storia reale le origini sono altre.

Pulliam scrive come se il santo “fornitore di capitali” fosse del tutto casualmente in possesso dei mezzi di produzione, e come se il lavoratore, anche lui del tutto casualmente, si trovasse nella situazione di dover negoziare – da pari a pari – la spartizione della produzione “in termini convenienti ad entrambi”.

In realtà, i termini di questa “spartizione” venivano negoziati con un processo che, prendendo un’espressione cara ai libertari di destra, somigliava al lupo e l’agnello che decidono cosa mangiare a cena. Non era un caso se il capitale era accumulato nelle mani di pochi datori, e i lavoratori avevano solo la forza delle loro braccia da vendere. Dietro c’era tutta una storia, descritta da Marx a lettere di sangue e fuoco, di cui ho già fornito un accenno.

Quando l’autonomista Harry Cleaver organizza il corso sul Capitale, assegna lo studio dell’accumulazione primitiva come parte propedeutica prima di affrontare concetti come il valore d’uso, il valore di scambio, il circuito del capitale e tutto il resto. Questo per dimostrare che tutti i discorsi sull’inevitabilità del lavoro e il pluslavoro, le lotte sulla giornata lavorativa e tutto il resto non sono una semplice teoria astratta sulla formazione del prezzo. Abbiamo a che fare con un vero e proprio rapporto di forza risultato di crimini storici.

Quanto alla “divisione del lavoro” e le “invenzioni”, Pulliam, come abbiamo visto, sembra fingere di non sapere come mai c’erano persone che avevano grossi capitali da investire [in innovazioni] per poi raccogliere i frutti dell’accresciuta produttività. Come ho detto recentemente altrove, “[ogni singola funzione apparentemente svolta dai capitalisti – investire, creare posti di lavoro e così via – è qualcosa che avrebbero potuto fare i lavoratori stessi, organizzati orizzontalmente o in cooperativa, se i capitalisti non gliel’avessero impedito.” Il denaro dei capitalisti non è altro che “il marchio della ricchezza accumulata”, qualcosa che permette loro di occupare preventivamente i canali di investimento e finanziari, nonché di coordinare preventivamente ciò che altrimenti verrebbe coordinato orizzontalmente dai lavoratori. I capitalisti miliardari non “inventano” nulla. Come ho scritto a proposito di Elon Musk:

Ha comprato il diritto legale di spadroneggiare chi realmente inventa e sviluppa, oltre al diritto legale di prendere ciò che producono. Tutti i capitalisti non fanno che appropriarsi dell’intelletto sociale e del lavoro cooperativo di chi inventa veramente, per poi estrarre una rendita da ciò.

Pulliam, dopo essersi dilungato in lezioni di storia immaginaria, ha anche la faccia di scrivere: “È intellettualmente disonesto illustrare il passaggio da un’economia agricola ad una basata sulle fabbriche senza dare il dovuto credito al proprietario della fabbrica per aver accumulato capitale, concepito le macchine e assunto su di sé tutto il rischio che rende possibile l’impresa.”

Ciò che è veramente disonesto è non chiedersi come aveva fatto il proprietario della fabbrica ad accumulare capitale, come mai aveva a che fare con un mercato del lavoro formato da proletari senza terre e senza proprietà, e come aveva fatto ad acquisire il diritto di proprietà di una macchina molto probabilmente “concepita” da qualcun altro. Perché questo è ciò che fa Pulliam. Passa da un’economia agricola ad un sistema industriale e poi si inventa una storia che parla di “contratti sociali”, “società libere” e “governi limitati” per colmare le lacune.

Quindi Pulliam ripete il dogma, famigliare a chiunque legga gli scritti polemici di Mises.org, secondo cui “la paga dei lavoratori rispecchia il valore del prodotto marginale del lavoro” (“in assenza di potere monopsonico”).

Ci vuole una faccia di bronzo per star qui a ripetere questo pattume quando sono quarant’anni che i salari reali ristagnano mentre la produttività del lavoro continua a crescere – e dopo che, casualmente dico io, è stato sconfitto il potere dei lavoratori – e mentre i profitti e le compensazioni dei dirigenti crescono di svariate volte.

Mises, nonostante i difetti, era perlomeno abbastanza onesto da ammettere che quando una predizione a priori non si realizza, occorre prendere in ipotesi la possibilità che una delle condizioni preliminari non sia stata soddisfatta. In questo caso, il mancato adeguamento dei salari agli incrementi di produttività fa capire che alcune, se non tutte, le condizioni subordinate citate da Pulliam – “assenza di costrizioni”, “mercato concorrenziale privo di potere monopsonico” e così via – non sono state soddisfatte. In realtà, il potere contrattuale tra lavoratori e datori riflette una situazione costrittiva, eredità di un passato violento e dell’attuale intervento dello stato a favore dei datori.

Il problema della produttività marginale non è tanto la sua applicazione, quanto la teoria in sé. Come spiega John Bates Clark, la teoria sulla produttività marginale è sostanzialmente un ragionamento circolare. La “produttività marginale” di un fattore è ciò che viene aggiungo al prezzo finale del prodotto, il che significa che qualunque cifra uno riesce a spuntare per un suo “servizio” rappresenta per definizione la sua produttività marginale. Così che quando il possessore di un “fattore” (il capitale) estrae rendita a spese di un altro fattore (il lavoro), per effetto di una relazione di potere sbilanciata, la loro rispettiva “produttività marginale” è determinata dalla loro relazione di potere. In altre parole, non sono i profitti e i salari ad essere determinati dalla produttività marginale del capitale e del lavoro, ma il contrario.

E poi questa cantonata: “Il conflitto di classe è uno dei temi preferiti dei liberal.” Niente di più falso si può dire dei liberal. Pulliam confonde liberalismo e sinistra, che è tutt’altra cosa. Le origini del liberalismo [americano, es] risalgono al movimento progressista tra ottocento e novecento. Si tratta di un risultato diretto dell’emergere delle grandi aziende e di tutto quel complesso di grandi istituzioni burocratiche nate per servire i bisogni delle aziende.

Secondo Rakesh Khurana della Harvard Business School (fonte: From Higher Aims to Hired Hands) i primi dirigenti aziendali provenivano dall’ambiente tecnico industriale e vedevano nel proprio lavoro un proseguimento del lavoro nei reparti produttivi. La rivoluzione portata da questi tecnici nelle grandi aziende, scrive Khurana, fu in sostanza un tentativo di applicare l’approccio ingegneristico (standardizzazione di strumenti, procedimenti e sistemi) all’organizzazione del sistema.

Secondo Yehouda Shenhav (Manufacturing Rationality: The Engineering Foundations of the Managerial Revolution), il Progressismo era l’ideologia di dirigenti e ingegneri che amministravano le grandi aziende; tradotto in termini di azione politica, si trattava di applicare gli stessi principi di razionalizzazione alla società intera…

Al cuore della filosofia manageriale progressista c’era l’imperativo di trascendere le divisioni di classe e ideologiche attraverso l’applicazione di competenze disinteressate.

Spiega Shenhav che questa filosofia apolitica nasceva dalla percezione che gli ingegneri avevano di sé: “Le teorie manageriali americane venivano presentate come una tecnica scientifica volta ad amministrare, per il suo bene, la società nel suo insieme senza ricorrere alla politica.” Frederick Taylor, il cui approccio manageriale era un microcosmo progressista, vedeva nella burocrazia “una soluzione alle spaccature ideologiche, la soluzione ingegneristica alla lotta tra le classi.” Progressisti e tecnici industriali “erano spaventati all’idea di una possibile “lotta di classe” e consideravano l’“efficienza” il modo per arrivare all’“armonia sociale, facendo sì che l’interesse di ogni lavoratore coincidesse con quello del suo datore.”

Lo vediamo anche nel liberalismo di oggi. I liberal possono anche accusare i “cattivi” miliardari di essere avidi, ma non immaginano una società senza miliardari, semmai una società in cui “miliardari patriottici” come Warren Bufett paga la sua “equa parte” di tasse, dà un salario equo, e tutti sono in pace. Liberal come Nancy Pelosi credono davvero che sia possibile diventare miliardari facendo del bene e senza sfruttare i lavoratori. Vogliono una società in cui i lavoratori hanno diritto ad una fetta più grande della torta, riconoscendo allo stesso tempo la legittimità del profitto quale ricompensa del genio imprenditoriale. In pratica, vogliono il capitalismo di Henry Ford senza il suo marciume antisemita.

Pulliam, non sorprendentemente, accusa unicamente le organizzazioni dei lavoratori di essere la fonte delle dispute violente. Benjamin Tucker, un assennato libertario sostenitore del libero mercato, uno che conosceva bene la storia del capitalismo e il suo funzionamento, vedeva le cose un po’ diversamente. Commentando le violenze del caso di Homestead e altri, spiega che gli aggressori erano i capitalisti: “la prima violazione della libertà in questo caso è imputabile direttamente a loro.” I capitalisti stavano in cima ad un sistema basato sul furto; il loro profitto dipendeva dai privilegi, dai diritti di proprietà creati artificialmente, dai monopoli imposti dallo stato a spese dei lavoratori oltre ad interventi dello stato in altre forme che riducevano artificialmente il potere contrattuale dei lavoratori. Un mercato del lavoro libero, spiega,

è sempre stato negato non solo ai lavoratori di Homestead, ma a tutti i lavoratori del mondo civilizzato. E i colpevoli sono i vari Andrew Carnegie. I capitalisti, di cui questo capofficina di Pittsburg è un tipico rappresentante, hanno scritto sugli statuti ogni genere di proibizione e tasse (di cui il dazio è la più inoffensiva) che mirano a limitare la concorrenza tra datori di lavoro…

…Carnegie, Dana e gli altri dovrebbero prima eliminare dagli statuti ogni legge che viola la libertà di tutti. Se, a quel punto, ci sarà qualche lavoratore che interferisce sui diritti dei datori di lavoro o fa violenza contro qualche pacifico “crumiro”, o attacca le guardie del suo datore di lavoro, che siano i detective di Pinkerton, il vicesceriffo o la milizia di stato, giuro che, da anarchico e in conseguenza della mia fede anarchica, sarò tra i primi a presentarmi volontario di una forza che reprima questi disturbatori dell’ordine, cancellandoli dalla faccia della terra se è necessario. Ma finché restano queste leggi invasive, non posso non vedere in ogni conflitto di forze la conseguenza di un’originale violazione della libertà da parte dei datori di lavoro, e se è necessario spazzarli via, che i lavoratori prendano la ramazza!

Pulliam riserva alla conclusione la sua idiozia più grossa sostenendo che, da quando i sindacati sono stati piegati dalle politiche neoliberali di Reagan e della Thatcher quarant’anni fa (con l’aiuto importante di quelli come lui), i lavoratori stanno meglio che mai. Laddove i pessimisti di sinistra vedono decenni di stagnazione, con i nuovi posti di lavoro che dal 2008 sono perlopiù a paga bassa, con un’intera generazione inchiodata ad un impagabile debito scolastico, apprendistato gratis, lavori precari e “livelli base” che richiedono la laurea ma sono pagati quindici dollari l’ora, Pulliam invece vede tutta un’orgia di vantaggi per i lavoratori. È entusiasta:

Grazie alla “gig economy” resa possibile dalle applicazioni per gli smartphone e altre tecnologie simili, molti lavoratori preferiscono lavorare a contratto da indipendenti con orari flessibili piuttosto che avere il tradizionale rapporto dipendente. Molti hanno il telelavoro, lavorano part-time o fanno un lavoro condiviso, cose inimmaginabili nel 1935.

È normale che Pulliam, uomo di spettacolo fino alla fine, concluda un articolo di fiabe con la fiaba più grossa. Solitamente sono scettico riguardo le possibilità anche di un fenomeno da baraccone come lui di trovare persone a cui vendere la paccottiglia. A pensarci bene, però, i suoi lettori non sono quelli che soffrono per la stagnazione dei salari, gli affitti alle stelle, i costi dell’assistenza sanitaria e le montagne di debiti. Sono i miliardari che pagano per queste cretinaggini.

Mutual Exchange Radio, Podcast
Mutual Exchange Radio: Roderick Long on Class Theory

You can now subscribe to Mutual Exchange Radio on iTunes, Stitcher, and Spotify.

This month’s discussion at the C4SS podcast Mutual Exchange centers around Long’s work on libertarian class theory, as well as the normative concerns that rise out of such a theory on balancing distributive and relational justice concerns with individual liberty. As we will discuss, libertarian class theory sees a primary creator and enforcer of class distinctions as the state. This is a wide-ranging discussion that touches on the economic and sociological analysis on class theory at the heart of Roderick’s work on the issue, the empirical plausibility of such a theory, whether class distinctions of this sort would continue to exist under market anarchism, and the ethical and normative framework of justice that motivates this theory. Roderick draws from Aristotelian virtue ethics to bring the seeming contradictions between a concern for individual property rights and a concern for equal treatment of all in society into balance in interesting ways.

Transcript:

Zachary Woodman: Welcome to this episode of Mutual Exchange Radio. I’m your host Zachary Woodman. Joining me today is Roderick Long from Auburn University. We are at the Eastern APA in Philadelphia, decided to get some extra podcasting done, or in addition to the Will-episode since we were all together for a Molinari panel.

So hello Roderick.

Roderick Long: Hi, good to be here.

Zachary Woodman: So today we’re going to discuss some of your work on libertarian class theory and what some of the normative implications of it are, how it differs from other class theories and maybe why it is a superior one to other possible class theories.

So maybe we should start before going into your account with a general idea of what a class theory is and what we want it to capture, what it should capture.

Roderick Long: Okay. So, a class theory is meant to explain certain kinds of power relationships among different groups in society. The one that’s best known is the Marxist theory of classes. According to which what determines the ruling class status is control over the access to the means production.

So under capitalism, the capitalist class controls the means of production. And the proletariat doesn’t have access to the means of production of factories, land, et cetera. This is the idea behind this and then just explain what’s wrong in society.

Why it is that some groups are systematically underprivileged or oppressed and what needs to be changed. Now, in fact, in the libertarian tradition, there are sort of two, at least two, different versions of libertarian class theory. So there’s one that is like a substitute, a switch…

Well, I say it’s a switch as though it’s a response to Marx’s class theory. It’s actually on the whole older than Marx’s. But there’s a version that simply says the basis for the ruling class isn’t access to the immediate production, it’s access to political power or the political means and…

Zachary Woodman: …the resources of the state.

Roderick Long: Yeah. So the idea is that, whereas on the classical Marxist view — although actually there turns out to be more than one classical Marxist view, at least I want to start a very familiar version of the Marxist view — classes emerged through the market and then the ruling class seizes power, seizes the state.

That’s not Marx’s only story, but that’s like one way the story seems to go. And then, so this is sort of traditional, libertarian, or classical liberal version, according to which it’s state privilege that creates this ruling class. And so the problem that needs to be addressed is state power and not the economic distribution. But there’s also more lefty version of the libertarian version which looks like a fusion of the Marxist and classical liberal versions.

Although all three are roughly theorizing around the same time. To some extent the Marxist view might be the latest of the three. So you get people like Thomas Hodgkin and so forth. Who were very early left-libertarian class theorists. And to put it anachronistically, this view looks like a cross between the classical liberal theory and the Marxist theory in that they see the concentration of ownership of the means of production as resulting from state power, but they do see kind of the constitution of ownership and things of production as the problem, as opposed to other sort of more right-wing versions of classical liberal theory that don’t really focus that much on ownership of the means of production, think it’s just a matter of state control and so forth.

So for a more right-wing version of classical liberalism, the oppressed classes might easily include, they might or might not depending on the details, people with vast economic resources on the grounds that they got those resources through market means not through the state.

Whereas the left-libertarian tends to be that in fact most vast disparities of wealth are the result of state privilege, not the result of the market. Now as I said, the Marxists sort of have two views because there’s attempts in the official Marxist theoretical view, according to which markets give right rise to economic inequality, and then the super-privileged on markets so then are in a position to get control of the state.

But then when Marx is talking about history, then he talks as though state privilege has been part of it all along and state privilege has been driving it. When he’s talking about history, Marx makes fun of the idea, that it felt like a bourgeoisie fairy tale or something, that it’s just through greater thrift in industry that the wealthy classes got their excess wealth. He says, no the history of capital cumulation has written the letters of blood and fire or whatever. But a lot of later Marxists have sometimes downplayed that. So for example in the ABC of communism by Bukharin and Preobrazhensky — two people that had the misfortune of being to the left and to the right of Stalin and paid the price both way in cases — but before that, they wrote what was sort of the Soviet Union’s standard intro Marxist textbook and in the ABC of communism they say, “Well look, capitalism isn’t the same thing as having a market with commodities and production for exchange and so forth. That’s not capitalism. You don’t have capitalism until you have a concentration of ownership of the means of production with a capitalist class everyone else is forced to work for.

Zachary Woodman: Markets Not Capitalism. *laughs*

Roderick Long: Right. But the problem, they say, with simple commodity production is that it’s unstable; that it automatically tends to turn into concentrated capitalism because some people are thrifter or smarter and so forth and they accumulate more and eventually they become super wealthy and they get control of everything. And they say, “We can see that that that’s what actually has happened”. And so they imply that the existing disparity and wealth actually arose out of a simple commodity production through just some people being thrifty and smarter — the very thing that Marx had dismissed as a bourgeoisie fairy tale. So there’s this kind of bifurcation in the Marxists as to exactly the state and state power crucial to serve accumulation when they’re trying to refute the people who say that the capitalist class got wealthy just through their own efforts. But then, when they’re trying to justify not having markets and private property, then the rule of the state seems to vanish. Then over on the classical liberal or libertarian sides, you got the early class theorists. In France, people like Charles Comte and Charles Dunoyer and Augustin Thierry who have this view about the state power, but they saw themselves as champions of the bourgeois class. Charles Comte for example says, “Some people are living in mansions, other people are living in hovels, your initial response is this is unjust. Once you realize that this is the result of the free market, then you’ll realize it’s okay.” Whereas someone like Hodgskin would have said, “What the hell are you talking about? Look at the actual history. They didn’t get this this way”. And then someone like Thierry ended up in a way being the same kind of champion for bourgeois class rule that Marx became for proletarian class rule.

He initially thought no one should be in charge of the state. He was, if not quite an anarchist, at least close to it. And the problem is just having anyone in charge of the state at all. We need to radically decrease state power, but by the end of his career he was saying, “Now that the French revolution has happened and now that the bourgeois classes is in control of the state, now it’s great and wonderful because they’re class that can be trusted.”

Because they are the third estate, their interests are identical with the interests of everyone. And so he has the same kind of what seems to me like the naivete that Marx had about the proletarians, he has about the bourgeois.

They’re thinking that once they’re in power, they’ll continue to represent society as a whole or something like that. So, my favourite class theory is more along the line of lines of Hodgskin. I think that vast disparities in wealth are difficult to maintain in a free market, because if you’ve got open competition, then if some people are getting much wealthier than other people, you can imitate what they’re doing and compete a lot of that wealth away from them. Things like intellectual property and so forth… The main function of intellectual property is to prevent you from imitating what other people are doing. And they would like to expand that as far as possible. Protectionism kind of. You know, I had the idea of building a restaurant here, so I don’t want anyone else to go to restaurant anywhere near me because it takes my idea away.

So on the left-libertarian version of class theory, the problem looks similar to what the Marxists identify as a problem, namely concentrations of capital ownership, ownership of the means of production, such that most people have no choice except to work, perform wage-labour for a smaller group of people. But their account of how it arose and what maintains it — and not just how it arose historically, but what continues to maintain it — it has a lot more to do with violent intervention, particularly, although not solely, but particularly by the state.

Zachary Woodman: So there’s a lot in there to unpack. I guess maybe the first question that one might have, especially when one comes from the more naive oor vulgar libertarian background, or maybe a more centrist liberal background, is, “Why should we want a class series to begin with?”

They might think all it is is bad social science, that all it is is this ideologically informed attempt to account for the distribution of income and all we need is to understand like certain economic processes to understand why income is distributed, or they might think that if we’re going to be methodological individualist, it doesn’t make sense to talk about classes as operating these large social features. So why should we want a class theory to begin with?

Roderick Long: Well, I mean, you shouldn’t want one, unless it’s true.

Zachary Woodman: *laughs*

Roderick Long: It’s not like, “Oh, you know, there’s just a general need for a class theory.” I think there’s good reason to think it’s true, but so let’s start with the last bit, “Is a class theory consistent with methodological individualism?”.

Of course, methological individualism is not always understood by everyone in exactly the same way but a class theory doesn’t have to say that classes act as some sort of agents over and above their members or anything like that.

Zachary Woodman: Although Marxists sometimes slip into that.

Roderick Long: They sometimes talk that way. They don’t always, when they’re being more careful. Heck, I think the libertarians sometimes talk that way too when they’re not being careful. But actually, to some extent, I think you could have many elements of a libertarian class theory, even if none of the people were intending anything. I don’t think that’s the case.

But… So here’s what I have in mind: suppose that the wealthy people have no intention of actually trying to maintain themselves as a class and suppose that the state isn’t actively trying to serve them. Imagine the state is just passing laws at random.

Just random laws, whatever. Some laws benefit the rich, some laws benefit the poor, some benefit them both, some harm them both… the state just generates things like a random number generator. I don’t think that’s what happens, but imagine it did. Then there’s going to be a filtering process. If something affects the interest of the rich, the rich have have lobbyists, they’ve got time, they’ve got lawyers, they’re in a position to be aware of what of what’s happening. They’ve got the resources to fight it and combat it and lobby against it. And so, it’s going to be harder for those laws to get passed or easier for them to get repealed.

Whereas the poor people are too busy working, they’re dispersed in interest. They don’t have the time or often they don’t have the education to know what to do. Don’t have the money to fight it. And so even if the government passed laws at random, I think there’d be a tendency for the laws to end up favoring the rich over the poor on average, for that reason. So, that doesn’t involve any conscious intentions for anything.

Zachary Woodman: That should be a basic insight of public trust.

Roderick Long: Yeah. And once you add conscious intentions, it doesn’t necessarily mean that all members of the ruling class have some strong feeling of class solidarity with each other. Because often they’re rivals. They may the cooperate to hold down any dangerous outsider, but in all of these coalitions each one wants more power than the others.

I don’t think that the capitalists are all marching arm in arm. And I don’t think the state is just a purely passive tool of the capitalist class. The people working within the state have their own interests that aren’t identical with, although they’re symbiotic, with the capitalist class.

It’s a partnership where each one would like to be the dominant partner, just like church and state in the middle ages. It says, “Look, there’s jockeying for power”. And so when people think that big government and big business are at odds, I think that’s mostly an illusion. But there’s a kernel of truth to it. There are genuine conflicts. There are cases where people in this side want one, people in this other side want something else. And likewise people in government and people in business are not completely unified either. But nevertheless, there are certain overall common tendencies. There are certain things that, if you lobby, if you’re trying to protect your company by law, to make the economy generally less competitive and make it harder for other people to come along and compete with you… That’s also gonna protect and other already established interests and so forth. And then there’ll be cooperation among these things. If a bunch of corporations get together and lobby, they can be more effective. And they will sort of trade favors with each other and then people in the government are trading favours with each other. You know, it’s, it’s not some kind of harmonious class solidarity. It’s not that the capital’s class as a whole, or that the government as a whole or anything as a whole acts as an agent. But nevertheless people’s incentives will often lead them to act in systematically coordinated ways.

Zachary Woodman: They might cultivate an ideology. Not that they act all uniformly, but that they have this sense of belonging.

Roderick Long: Yeah. I’m not saying that there’s no such thing as class solidarity. Part of what that means is that class solidarity isn’t necessary for this to happen.

Zachary Woodman: And class solidarity doesn’t undermine methodological individualism.

Roderick Long: Right. But certainly, it’s often likely that people in privileged groups tend to relate to other people in privileged groups and tend to think of themselves [as] naturally belonging where they’re belonging and tend to see outsiders as interlopers.

These people go to similar schools and similar functions and hang out together and they form friendships and social ties and form common views of the world often. Not always. I’m not saying that there’s no class solidarity, but there’s multiple things going on that reinforce the overall effect.

Zachary Woodman: So the overall answer to that objection is that — you know, there’s a line in Mises where he says like analysis of nations doesn’t undermine methodological individualism. And it’s for similar reasons to that, that you can have a group of individuals… not consciously interacting with each other, but the class can emerge as an emergent phenomenon to use Hayekian phraseology.

Roderick Long: And a lot of people criticize class theory… The two criticisms they often make… one is, they say, well, it’s just a conspiracy theory.

Zachary Woodman: Right.

Roderick Long: The answer is: well, sometimes these things are conspiracies. Sometimes you actually find evidence that these people are collaborating.

Because the more concentration of power that you have, the easier it is for these people to talk to each other and cooperate. And sometimes it doesn’t even count as a conspiracy instance, often they’re doing it fairly in the open. But also it doesn’t always need to be a conscious conspiracy. Often people’s economic interests will just lead them to act and the relevant way.

Zachary Woodman: And it seems like a confusion of like out latent functions — is a sociological term — of class with people thinking it’s an intended function of it.

Roderick Long: And the other criticism that you often hear, particularly on the right, of class theory, is it is driven by envy. If you think that the rich are getting rich illegitimately, you’re just saying it out of envy.

Well, then the answer is: well, let’s look and see why they’re getting rich. If it turns out, in fact, they’re getting rich through systematic government privilege, that is restricted…

Zachary Woodman: Or other illegitimate means.

Roderick Long: If it turns out that the highway man has a lot more money than the rest of us because he’s been robbing us all. Is it envy exactly that makes us resent him? It’s resentment, but it seems like it could be perfectly justified resentment. In any case, even if there’s envy involved, that is a motivation for getting people interested in class theory, that doesn’t make class theory false.

You have to look and see what the evidence is.

Zachary Woodman: So, the other objection one might make, and this is one that is not just a problem for class theory but for the broader project of left-market anarchists, is the possibility that we’re wrong about the empirical question, about what causes disparities in wealth.

Or that even if we’re right about that question under current economic conditions, that in a purely free market, there would be massive disparities that would recreate these sorts of classes. And you don’t necessarily have to be a Marxist to think that. You could find some mechanisms broadly within the neoclassical economics, like Piketty tries to explain that.

So what, what do you think are the arguments against those sorts of possibilities?

Roderick Long: Well, I mean obviously we don’t have complete detective knowledge of what would happen in a fully freed market. So I don’t think we can say with absolute certainty there’s nothing that would create this very large systematic disparities in wealth. But we can just look and say, “Well, look at what’s causing them now, look what the overall effect is.” If you see someone just hobbling along and they’ve got a 200 pound sack on their back and they’re hobbling along with difficulty, you can help them by getting that sack off the back.

And you would say, “Well, who knows if you’ve got the sack off their back? Maybe there would cause something else to make them probably even worse”. It’s possible. But it’s not initially the way we bet. The bet is, well, if there’s something that’s systematically causing a problem… getting rid of it will get rid the problem.

And of course sure social phenomena are complicated and interconnected and various ways and it’s not like you move one thing and, and you can just easily predict whatever everything else is gonna happen. We always have to go by our best guess and our best guess is that when we look at what actually seems to be causing these disparities, there always seems to be this hand of force involved.

Zachary Woodman: Let’s go into that best guess. Let’s go into the reasons you have for that and possible other reasons.

So let’s start with the reasons you have for thinking that. What are discrete empirical pieces of evidence that current disparities in wealth are caused largely by state control and intervention.

Roderick Long: Okay. So I mentioned IP as something that prevents people from imitating wealth generating activity. There’s more obvious kinds of subsidies to corporations, but there are also various indirect ones. Kevin Carson likes to talk about transportation subsidies. So for example, the fact that the the vast share of wear and tear on the roads is caused by these big shipping companies, but you don’t pay a proportional share of the taxes for maintaining the roads, which means in effect, tax funded highways end up being a subsidy from the everyone else to these big box companies and so forth. You’ve got various kinds of protectionist legislation that helps big companies. You’ve got…

Zachary Woodman: …certain sorts of trade restrictions.

Roderick Long: You know, you’ve got…

Zachary Woodman: …regulatory capture.

Roderick Long: …what I call the capture of the labour movement. More right traditional right wing libertarians see the labour movement as the beneficiary of the state. They think of the overall effect of liberal legislation is that it empowers unions at the expensive of employers. The left libertarian analysis is if you look at it in its totality, not just look at individual pieces of legislation that seem to be benefiting unions but look at it in its totality, in fact [it] indeed seems to have been intended to be in effect to de-fang the labour movement and make it a kind of junior partner in the big government business big business thing. Then you get these legalised unions but there are restrictions. Government can tell you when to strike and it can rule out sympathy strikes and various things. The right wing libertarian analysis of unions is, it’s just the cartels to raise labour prices. But in fact, traditionally, for a lot of the labour movement it was something more than that. There really was a the goal to try and get something more like labour control of industry. And it’s turned into a bunch of little labour cartels, because that was something easier for government to deal with. And so a lot of labour legislation has been driven in that direction. And then just sort of broadly there’s… I mean Kevin has another nice distinction of what he calls primary and secondary regulations.

So there are all these regulations that look as though they’re designed to help the less affluent. But often they turn out to be highly visible ways of mitigating the effects of less visible regulations that are just part of the basic framework.

So take a very straightforward example. Back in the Reagan administration,it had this deregulation of the savings and loan industry. They had lots of restrictions on how risky loans they could make. And they took those restrictions off.

So to a lot of people it looked like in the direction to free market move, and it caused a lot of problems. But from a more careful analysis to say, well look… What had happened was, first they gave them the federal deposit insurance saying, “If you, if you make excessively risky loans and you are in danger of going out of business, running out of money, the taxpayers will insure and cover your losses”. But given that, we want these regulations on you that you can’t do stuff that is too risky. So they gave them a government privilege and then restricted how they could use it. Then the deregulation comes along and what it does is… it took away the restriction without taking away the privilege!

So now the savings and loans were free to gamble with the taxpayer’s money, knowing that their losses would likely be covered.

Zachary Woodman: So that was worse than by bailouts…

Roderick Long: Yeah. So what looked like a move in the direction of less regulation really wasn’t.

Another example is liability caps for things like oil spills and so forth. Where if a company knows that there’s a limit to how much it can be sued in case of oil spill, they’re going to be less conscientious about avoiding those things and take more risks.

Just basic things like starting a business. The kinds of regulatory hoops you have to go through to start a business, which if you’re wealthy and established, it’s easy. You can jump through those hoops. You’ve got the lawyers you’ve got the time. But if you just a very small business or entrepreneur or you’re some of the inner city who just wants to start a hair braiding business. Or if you want to start your own taxi service, and all you’ve got is a car and a cell phone, which is all you need to run a taxi service, really… But are all these regulations, you know…

Zachary Woodman: …medallion services and what have you…

Roderick Long: Yeah, some of those medallions would cost like something [around] a hundred thousand dollars. [It] Is a big difference between… the number of people who can afford a business whose capital equipment is a car and a cell phone is a lot larger than those who could afford a car and a cell phone and a hundred thousand dollar license…

And although things like Uber and Lyft have liberalized that a little bit, there’s still…. no, there’s still a centralized corporation [with] a big advantage to get certain kinds of exemptions sometimes. It’s an ongoing fight.

Zachary Woodman: And they’re using their intellectual property to have barriers on who can use it.

Roderick Long: So Uber and Lyft and they haven’t made it such that just anyone can go and just start their own ride sharing service without any legal hassles. They’re an improvement over the preexisting section, but… Another thing that would be really easy for less affluent people to start is restaurants, if they could just start something in their own home and using their own kitchen, but zoning rules that out. Or another thing is daycare. Actually my mother wanted to start a daycare/sort of nursery school with some of her friends and they would take care of the kids while so some of the mothers would be working and others would be taking care of the kids of the other ones.

Anyway, it turned out that in order to do that, they’re supposed to have a lot of money upfront to pay various kinds of fees and licensing and they had to have degrees and education. They didn’t need a degree in education to take care of their own kid, but [they] had needed to [have] education to take care of each other kids.

So they couldn’t do it. And it just goes on and on

Zachary Woodman: My mother with therapy had to go into grad school just so she could be a therapist in the state, or be a social worker even in the state of Michigan. Go to a grad school that was licensed.

Not that the grad school was licensed, but they had to have a partnership with the Michigan state licensure so she could get the license directly through the grad school.

Roderick Long: [There] where all of cases where in order to have a hair braiding business, you have to get a certificate, that requires taking a course for doing lots and lots of different things with hair that they weren’t planning to do.

Zachary Woodman: Right, right.

Roderick Long: And of course, the course also costs a lot of money. I remember in — this was a while ago, I don’t know if it’s still true, but I wouldn’t be surprised if it is — that in Louisiana, there was this controversy about how difficult was to enter the florist business. And you had to have this very difficult process of getting a license to be a florist because we all know the damage that people can do with unlicensed flower arrangements.

Zachary Woodman: *laughs*

Roderick Long: And it turned out that the people in charge of granting licenses to new florists [were] a board staffed by people from existing florists who were being asked to authorize their competitors. And so of course they tended to be a little…

Zachary Woodman: Yeah. And there are examples in the drug industry, where to prove equivalence of a generic drug to a name brand drug, you have to prove the chemical equivalence. They have to send in a sample from the would be competitors like from Pfizer, who have you, and of course, Pfizer never sends you the samples.

Roderick Long: I’m talking about things in a very small scale likehair braiding or florists but also things like the government sending in the army to protect the interests of large corporations and countries.

This happens at every level of scale,

Zachary Woodman: Right. And this has the effect both of stopping the poor from accumulating wealth by starting their own business and stuff and stuff like that and also by increasing prices for various things. for them that disproportionately affect the worst off.

Roderick Long: Yeah.

Zachary Woodman: So, I mean these are all effects that you don’t need to be a left-libertarian to acknowledge. I think Rob Reich in his book on inequality acknowledges a lot of this and he’s like a progressive economist. Steven Teles and […] his coauthor [Brink Lindsey] for The Captured Economy has a whole book on this and then they’re relatively centrist progressives and libertarians. So, you don’t have to be a […] libertarian to acknowledge all that, but you still might think, “Yeah, that’s all true about our existing economy, but even if you had a purely freed market…”. Maybe they might cite Piketty’s analysis of how under markets the rate of return on capital is bigger than the growth rate, and so that causes disproportionate returns on those who already have capital… And they might think that therefore there are reasons to believe that even in a completely free market, you still have these problematic unequal distributions… So what’s your general thought on those types of accounts?

Roderick Long: Well, I think it underestimates the entrepreneurial potential of people working on their own, not working for these big firms, the ability to produce stuff that doesn’t rely on these guys. So, it’s one thing to have accumulated because it’s not just that you’ve accumulated capital in the past, but the ability to keep on doing it in the face of this massive storm of upstarts. Because look at all the businesses that people do start or try to start and get squashed down. I think there’s a massive entrepreneurial drive from where people are constantly trying to just start something. Everything from selling loose cigarettes in the streets to whatever, selling drugs, whatever it is. There are a lot of things that don’t require a lot of capital upfront. So it’s not just the accumulation of capital. It’s the prohibition on free entry into a lot of these things.

Zachary Woodman: Alright. So moving on a bit from that question, one might think that there are other ways, not just through the market, but through other cultural forces that classes are created. They might have an intersectional analysis of class in terms of gender, in terms of race. Probably race being the biggest one.

They’ll point out that in America poverty is largely a feminized phenomenon. It’s largely a racialized phenomenon. Historically disenfranchised racial groups tend to be poor. The poorest people tend to be single women with children. And they might think, maybe what’s going on a bit here is there’s an ideology that maybe the state helps use, but is largely independent of the apparatus of the state that stops these people from accumulating wealth.

So discrimination against these groups and what have you. And so to think that it’s largely just the state that creates these classes is to miss this large cultural, social explanation. So what’s the left-libertarian response to that, or how do they incorporate that insight?

Roderick Long: I mean there’s division among left-libertarians on this issue.

Zachary Woodman: What’s your take?

Roderick Long: Well, I’ll just say, I know some libertarians who remind me a bit of vulgar Marx’s in the sense of saying,”No, really it’s just the state” — sort of the left-libertarian analogue of vulgar Marxists — “It’s just the state”, and I don’t think that’s the case.

I definitely think that culture and ideology and so forth matter and also, of course, I don’t think that the state is the only form of violence. [When] we’re talking about gender politics… a lot of the male violence against women is not motivated by the state. It’s a freelance violence that helps to maintain power imbalance between men and women. I don’t discount that. But I think that having market incentives as opposed to governments incentives is very effective in combating it, even though if it’s not all you need. And here’s a distinction I’d want to make. So, a lot of libertarians who want to talk about discrimination, all of them will say, “Look, discrimination is costly because if you’re not hiring the best people or having the best customers, it hurts you economically”.

And so the market incentives will…

Zachary Woodman: That’s what Gary Becker and Milton Friedman say.

Roderick Long: Yeah and I think that hat’s overstated. I think there is a way that a market helps that problem, but not quite the way people think, because a lot of people… if they’re prejudiced and their peer group is also prejudiced, they may not want to go against their peer group. Suppose that you’re a white guy living in a racist, white community and you want to you pay your black employees more or you want to accept black customers who get more money, but then you know that you’re going to be shunned by your white peer group. You might not do it. Often the way that economics breaks up cartels in general — cause it’s a kind of a racial cartel — is not so much that it leads members of the cartel to cheat on each other, ’cause often they have non-monetary reasons to hang together, but then it brings in outsiders who aren’t part of that culture. Yeah. So here’s a story about my grandmother. So my grandmother lived in… she wasn’t from Florida, she was like from Chicago. She moved to Florida in the 1940s, maybe, in Daytona beach. She paid her black servants way more than her white neighbours did — not because she wasn’t racist, she was racist as hell but her flavor of racism was different from the local flavour. And she didn’t do it just to get the best employees. Although, in fact, that was the result and caused all the neighbours to complain.

She did just because she thought it was un-classy to pay people below a certain level. It was below her dignity to pay people that little. Her motives were not ideal. As a matter of fact, she did get economic benefits from getting the best of the local black employees. Because she wasn’t part of this local group. She wasn’t planning to live forever in Florida. She didn’t identify with this peer group. She didn’t give a crap what they thought about anything. And so, she wasn’t motivated primarily by the economic incentives, although that was probably part of it. I think in general, economic incentives break up cartels more successfully by luring competitors in from the outside than necessarily from breaking up the cartel from within. So I think those things can be effective, but also I think we shouldn’t think of the market as just a matter of sitting back and letting the price system take care of things. I mean, I think the price system is amazing. It can in fact take care of lots and lots of things, but also I think, you know, we think of market the markets as sort of the totality free exchanges, not all free exchanges are just matters of, you know, I want to get, you know, I want to maximize my monetary profit or something like that.

I think that there’s a vital role for deliberate social action to try and change the culture. I think that even if people did work like that, if everyone were just robotic profit maximizers, the market would, would have solved these things pretty well, but as long as you’ve go a lot of people who are being driven by bad non-monetary incentives, it’s really crucial to have people driven by good non-monetary incentives to combat it.

And so I think that’s one of the reasons I think that libertarians shouldn’t focus just on getting rid of state intervention, even though I think state intervention is a huge part of the story. But that they should also be focused on getting involved in these kinds of solidarity movements and sort of precisely the sorts of things that intersectional feminists and race theorists and so forth are interested in.

So, I think that, although we’re a lot more optimistic than a lot of more traditional leftists are about the power of markets and so forth, nevertheless I think that these other movements are absolutely crucial too and we should be supporting them.

Zachary Woodman: Right. And that’s very good. I guess that’s enough on the distinguishing [features] of libertarian class theory. I [would like] to go into the normative motivations for that project. Well, maybe we can go into what we care about with egalitarianism.

What sort of egalitarianism do you buy into, what do you think the point of distributive justice is? And why? There’s this classic libertarian view that distributed justice is, to paraphrase Hayek, a mirage of some sorts; that we shouldn’t care about it because free exchange can create an unequal wealth distributions, even if the free exchange is completely valid. Nozick made that argument with his Will Chamberlain example. So why should we care about [it]?

Roderick Long: I should say that my views have evolved somewhat since I wrote that. I’m not sure I disagree with anything I said in that article, but yeah. Probably the range of kinds of equality I’m interested in is probably greater now. So what I said back then in that article was that the libertarian conception of freedom is itself a form of a egalitarianism.

Zachary Woodman: Right.

Roderick Long: The idea was a quality of authority and idea. An idea that goes back to Locke. When Locke and Jefferson say that we’re all created equal, […] the kind of equality they have in mind is a equality of authority. No one has the right to tell anyone else what to do.

Zachary Woodman: That’s something most liberal theories share in general.

Roderick Long: In principle, but they end up supporting an organization that… one criticism of the state is the state is an organization that is unequal. […] So, people think of the state’s job was to ensure na equality among the governed, but the question is: what about equality between the governed and the governors? There’s this inequality and power, and you can say, “Well, if it’s a democratic state, then somehow it’s really all just us” or, “We control it or we rotate into and out of it”, and so forth. In practice, you end up meeting […] either people in a political office or people with private political influence or people with badges and guns and truncheons, being in a position to impose stuff on us that we don’t have [?] to impose on them. So there’s a sense in which just the basic libertarians conception of freedom is itself a form of egalitarianism. But I wouldn’t limit my egalitarianism to that. I think that’s a very important form of egalitarianism. It would be, it worthwhile be having that, even if we didn’t get the kind of wealth quality that I would expect. But, I think the wealth equality, that I expect… I also think it’s valuable in its own right. People often say, a lot of right-libertarians say, “Well look, it’s not the degree of equality of wealth that matters. All it matters is sort of…

Zachary Woodman: …how it was attained.

Roderick Long: Yeah. Well also they’ll say how, what matters is, as long as it’s going up, it doesn’t matter.

Right.

And I think they’re half right. In the sense in that my ideal to getting rid of wealth inequality would not be… if I could do it by sort of reducing everyone to an equal level of poverty or something like that.

But of course that’s not what, you know… So take something like Rawl’s principal. Which is that deviations from equality are fine so long as the worst off people are better off than they would be under equality. So, that’s not the kind of egalitarianism that wants… that would get rid of equality of i by, reducing ourselves to some sort of Harrison Bridger on equality. [?]

A lot of libertarians say that they don’t see any value in…

Zachary Woodman: …in anything like that? Distributive justice.

Roderick Long: I see some value to it. I certainly don’t think it’s the whole story of justice. I don’t think that it trumps the kinds of property rights considerations that someone like Nozick has. Suppose we all became fantastic and much more wealthy than we are, but it was still massively unequal, I think, there’ll be a problem.

I mean, I take it but it’d be a problem because how we relate to each other in society, what all kinds of opportunities we have to interact and possibly being left out of things…

Zachary Woodman: The relational egalitarianism of Liz Anderson is what you have in mind…

Roderick Long: Maybe something like that. And of course, to a lot of right libertarians it’s just going to sound like envy, but it’s not envy in the sense of, “I resent you from having more and I want to take it away from you”.

It’s like, I want to be sort of a full participant in the society. Now, how does the value of that kind of concern relate to the value of something like Nozickian rights? Well, this is where my Aristotelianism comes in. So Eric, In the Aristotelian view, this as I interpret it, as I interpret the idea of the unity of virtue is that… The traditional way of putting that unity of virtue is that you can’t have one virtue completely without having them all. The strong version of it is that all the virtues are just different names for one virtue. That’s like Socrates’ view. That’s not Aristotle’s view. Aristotle’s view is there are different virtues.

Zachary Woodman: To be courageous, you will also…

Roderick Long: …to be fully courageous!

Zachary Woodman: Fully or, I guess the better example as giving is, to be fully benevolent, in certain situations, you’re going to have to do the courageous things, you have to be courageous.

Roderick Long: Yeah. So, he doesn’t rule out the possibility that you could be like 70% benevolent but only 40% courageous or something like that. I think that he would allow that. But you couldn’t be a hundred percent benevolent without being a hundred percent courageous because there are going to be cases where doing the benevolent thing requires facing some kind of danger. But for me, the most important point about the unity of virtue is not just that you can’t have one without having them all with it. You can’t settle what it means. We can’t settle what courage requires of you without figuring what benevolence requires of you and vice versa. So that the contents of the virtues are inter-defined. Each one has some sort of provisional content to begin with. But as you work out the details, there’s a kind of mutual adjustment to come up with our content.

So I think that there are some virtues that are very much social consequence oriented, like benevolence, and there’s some that are much more deontic rights oriented like justice. But if those two are standing in relationship of sort of reciprocal determination, that means that in filling in one, you also have to fill in the other so that you may have to adjust the content of justice to fit consequentialist concerns. But also, you may have to adjust the concept of what counts as a good result by concerns of justice.

Zachary Woodman: Okay. So, that’s a really fascinating… I hadn’t heard you make that argument for it. And that’s really fascinating use of the unity of virtue, which is a doctrine that I’m generally skeptical of cause I’m not much of an Aristotelian myself. But, one objection that comes to mind to that is that, well, it doesn’t look like we need to fully conceptually spell out what a just distributive society is. I guess the way you cash [?] that was in terms of what a benevolently distributive society would be, although in the literature it’s usually talked about in terms of justice. But since we’re in virtue theory, now we should keep those two distinct that guess.

Roderick Long: Well sometimes see with benevolence, benevolence feeds into determining the content of justice.

Zachary Woodman: Right. That’s that’s the claim. And it looks to me like, if what we mean by justice here is like non-aggression libertarian stuff, what justice demands of you is that you don’t initiate force or fraud bla bla bla in illegitimate ways. It doesn’t look like you need to make much reference to distributive justice to know what that is. And a Rawlsian would push back to say, “Well, I don’t really need to refer to a theory of property rights to know what a just society looks like distributively.” So, it looks like… why would we think that there’s this important sort of conceptual link to them in this unity of virtue way to explain them?

Roderick Long: Well, there are different ways of specifying the general libertarian principles. You’ve got general libertarian principles about rights and so forth for different ways of specifying the details.

And likewise, you can have general concerns about distributive justice and different ways of specifying the details. And the idea is that each one has some content of its own, it doesn’t start off as a blank slate because if they all start off with blank slates, then trying to mutually adjust blank slates wouldn’t get you anywhere.

But the idea is that it’s reasonable to take these distributive concerns into account when choosing among different ways of instantiating the basis libertarian principles and vice versa.

Zachary Woodman: So give me some examples.

Roderick Long: This isn’t really a matter of social policy, it’s more a matter of individual action but the question is like, “Is it [right] to steal bread when you’re starving”, or something like that. And so there’s this one right-libertarian view that would say, “No, it’s your duty to starve”. Back in the 90s, the Liberty magazine had this poll where they asked people, “If you are falling out of a building and you grab on to someone else’s balcony to prevent yourself from falling to your death and they say, ‘Get off my balcony.’ Are you obligated to let go and fall to your death?”. And there was a significant percentage that said yes. And in fact, that example ended up getting incorporated in one of L. Neil Smith’s science fiction libertarian novels, where he seemed to endorse that position.

And so the question is, well that’s one interpretation of the libertarian principle. We can also have the interpretation that in a situation like that, what you owe them is maybe something like reparation afterward, but not actually… if you’re breaking into someone’s cabin to avoid freezing to death or something, should we say that you’re just required to die or can we say that inemergency situations it’s alright to make use of their property but then you should do your best, if possible, to make restitution to them later. And I’d say, well, in choosing among those different interpretations, it makes sense to take into account considerations of benevolence and welfare and so forth.

And as you choose the less creepy answers to those questions that would be an example. Let’s say there are different ways of interpreting land rights…

Zachary Woodman: Occupancy & Use versus homesteading.

Roderick Long: Yeah. And also things like, even in cases where you don’t actually get full property title to something, what you have to do in order to get an easement. So there are some libertarians who will say, “Well look, if someone buys up all the land around your house well, you should have contractually acquired an easement before that. And if you didn’t, well, you’re just out of luck and you can just come in and out of a helicopter”, versus the view that, “Well no, by buying up all the land around your house, not letting you out, they’re imprisoning you.” and so they’re violating your liberty. So those are two different ways of interpreting the libertarian principle.

Well, it’s legitimate to bring in social welfare considerations to choose between them and say, “Well, in light of those, it’ll be more reasonable to take the one that they have to give you an easement.” And like I was talking about things like native American land rights, where someone will say, “Well look, in the cases of the nomadic tribes, maybe they weren’t alternative landscape enough to get full ownership, so could you just grab all that stuff?”, the thing that they hunted over or were they entitled to an easement, at least over the areas that they hunted, even if they didn’t have full property rights and you could say, “Well, if you take the benevolence seriously, it’s going to be in favor of giving them an easement as opposed to what actually happened.”

No, of course what actually happened was, even Indian tribes that had farms and settled, they had stuff that that would clearly have been private property, in extended Lockean views. The government took that too. […] The government was just sort of misapplying libertarian principles, but…

Zachary Woodman: Right.

Roderick Long: But some libertarians have argued, “Well, this is for the nomadic tribes and nomadic tribes didn’t have any property rights as they did just take whatever.” And I think that’s going to be a less plausible interpretation once you bring in benevolence to choose among these different interpretations of the libertarian principle.

Zachary Woodman: Right. That’s really interesting. Other thing that came to mind is, that it’s pretty uncontroversial among mainstream political philosophers, as I take it, to adjust one’s view of distributive justice in light of other justice considerations. The famous objection to look at egalitarianism is it would require continual interventions, into your life, in problematic ways that violate liberal justice to correct for bad luck.

Maybe we need to control how people parent their kids or what have you. Alright, I think that’s really interesting. The other thought that I have, when you apply the doctrine of virtue to try to link a thick conception of distributive justice with a thinner libertarian view is one might think that virtue theory is something that should only apply to individuals. When we talk about the virtue of courage, benevolence, blah, blah, blah, that’s something that works with individuals that doesn’t really apply to whole societies to all polities. And it would be some sort of fallacy to start applying virtues to society, so why should we be using like a doctrine of the unity of virtue to try to link features that we want societies to have, and they’re not really virtuous proper.

Roderick Long: Well, all these decisions are made by individuals. So anyone who’s implementing, anyone who’s acting and doing a role in being part of a legal system or something, whether they’re a judge or a legal theorist or some kind of law enforcement person or light rights protector, whatever they are, all the people who are the agents of the legal system, be it a state or some kind of something more anarchic, you know… they’re individuals and the individual contact is government of virtues and everything the state does ultimately, or whatever any legal system, state or anarchic, happens in virtue of individuals making decisions and they’re always going to be governed by it by these virtue considerations. So, you don’t get off the hook for following the virtues, just because you’re acting as an agent of a legal system. Now of course, the traditional virtue theorists thought of the purpose of the state as to promote virtue. And so they were very paternalistic and intrusive, you know, not all of them as paternalistic and intrusive as Plato’s Republic…

Zachary Woodman: Cause it’s like Aristotle’s politics…

Roderick Long: So Aristotle’s politics… it looks very libertarian compared to Plato’s Republic, but it looks a lot like Plato’s Republic compared to libertarianism.

But I think that what they failed to think about was they were thinking about virtue as something to promote, but they are forgetting about the ways in which virtue should constrain the behavior of the people running the system. And so, suppose that I think that there’s this value of respect that you owe to all other people, something a lot of the ancient virtue theorists sometimes seem to think, sometimes not. And of course Aristotle explicitly didn’t think that, he thought that there were natural slaves. But you’ve got people like Cicero who says, we’re all equal parts of this — well, he didn’t say equal but — we’re all parts of humanity and everyone deserves respect and so forth, but he had no problem with slavery, he never explained it. But, they think of it as value of respect and so they would think, therefore, it’s the job of the state to promote, make people respectful, but you have to say, “Well look, the state is going to [viewing] this in virtue of individuals doing various things and they’re bound by that respect too. And so you can’t promote respect in ways that violate respect. So, the idea that the natural political implementation of virtue ethics is a state that promotes virtue is a mistake because virtue requires taking an attitude toward other people that’s inconsistent with the kind of paternalistic micromanaging that the traditional virtue ethical state was favoring.

Zachary Woodman: So, what I had in mind by giving voice to that objection was something somewhat different. I had in mind that Hayek in The Fatal Conceit

Roderick Long: Oh yeah.

Zachary Woodman: …argues that we need to apply a different sort of… maybe putting it in terms of whether virtue applied as societies or state institutions was the wrong way to give voice to this line. But I had in mind that, you know, Hayek in The Fatal Conceit says that we now live in such a large, complicated society that we have to apply different ways of thinking about ethics, maybe different virtues, to our lives in our intimate orders and our intimate groupings, like families, relationships, blah, blah, blah, as opposed to the extended order of society, you know…

Roderick Long: Yeah.

Zachary Woodman: …the world out there. And maybe we can catch this out in terms of virtue ethics by thinking about like how a lawyer has to exhibit virtues to different degrees in different ways, when he’s arguing in his court case, as opposed to when he’s talking to his wife. A lawyer who — and this is a very non-Aristotelian way of thinking about it as I see it — a lawyer…

Roderick Long: That’s a very Ciceronian way of thinking about it. *laughs*

Zachary Woodman: Maybe. The lawyer who were to treat his court case the way he treats a discussion with his wife, would very likely lose the court case. Whereas, if he were to go home and get in this combative debate with his wife, he’d probably get a divorce very quickly and we would view him as not a good husband and we wouldn’t feel him as not a good lawyer in the other case. So, why would we think that the way virtues work, work the same in the political realm as they do in the public space as they do in the private space of our intimate […] lives?

Roderick Long: Well, it’s part of virtue to recognize that one and the same virtue will have different manifestations in different social contexts. That’s been a part of virtue ethics forever. There’s this often disagreement of what those contexts are., I agree that there are differences in these contexts, but I think that people have tended to be too comfortable with allowing radical differences, like… basically all the things that cops are allowed to do.

Zachary Woodman: Right.

Roderick Long: But also take another example that’s sort of similar to your example and that I think is partially right and partially wrong. So, in business ethics there is this famous art article by Albert Carr, I think called “Business Bluffing or something like that? [the title is Is Business Bluffing Ethical?] It often appears in business ethics textbooks, where he says you don’t use the same ethics in business that you do in dealing with personal friends and family. The operators claim different set of rules. What I think to some extent is right, but he takes it instead of saying, “Look, it’s like poker. In poker, you know they’re trying to deceive you.” And by playing the game, you’ve sort of consented to their deceiving you. So, likewise when you’re in business, when you’re engaging in economic transactions in the market, you know they’re trying to deceive you and you’ve sort of consented to that by entering these economic transactions. Which really seems… And it’s not just that they don’t have to be as bedeviled to you as you would be a family member, but actually they can deceive you as long as they don’t actively lie and so forth. They can manipulate you and so forth.

And I think it’s just wrong. This idea that we’ve consented, like consenting to play a poker game. I mean, there’s no such thing as consenting to engage in economic trade in the market, you just have to do it in order to survive. And so what they did really sounds more like sort of the social contract argument that somehow by just living in a place you’ve consented to all kinds of crap from the government. Likewise, they said by living in a place you’ve consented to all that kinds of crap from business people. So, I think there’s a limit to how far you can have these different roles mean different ethics things. Now of course, part of Hayek’s idea was, “Well, it doesn’t make any sense to talk about the justice of a distribution.”

Zachary Woodman: Right.

Roderick Long: Because justice applies only to the actions of individuals and so it doesn’t apply to spontaneous orders. But of course you can always translate talk about the justice of a distribution into talk about the justice of what individuals either individually or in concert with each other should do in response to an existing distribution. So you can always translate talk about social justice into talk about what individuals should do.

Zachary Woodman: But at that point, haven’t you just conceded the point and gotten rid of the distributive justice. And gotten just back to the end…

Roderick Long: No, cause I think it’s [?] saying what people justly should do in response to a distribution, given distribution… whether they should try and change that distribution or not, that’s an issue of distributive justice.

Zachary Woodman: Okay.

Roderick Long: Now, it’s true that there’s a kind of communism that can work at the level of the family that I think can’t work at the level of society as a whole.

Zachary Woodman: Right. That’s what I also think […].

Roderick Long: And that’s fine, that’s right. And in fact, if you try to apply it to the level of the society as a whole, it’ll cause starvation and chaos and if you’re benevolent, you don’t want to do that. And so…

Zachary Woodman: The rest of that quote is, if we apply it or the ethics to our intimate groupings, we would demolish them and if we applied the intimate grouping ethics of the extended order, we would destroy it.

Roderick Long: Yeah. So, benevolence is when a simple minded application of benevolence to the social order would have horrific results, then a nuanced understanding of benevolence would say, “Well, don’t do that.” But nevertheless, I don’t think that’s a reason to think that there’s no reason to be concerned about systematic inequalities of wealth or thinking that there’s just not a problem. Now, if it’s true that the only way we could get rid of them is by some sort of intrusive violation of people’s property rights, then I’m saying, “Alright well, I guess then the worlds sucks, we don’t want to do that.”

But to the extent that you can combat these kinds of inequalities without violating libertarian rights, I think we should. It’s a better society if more people can participate on an equal well basis. Part of it is just that societies work better when more people’s ideas can enter into the competition. And if there’s a vast inequality of wealth between one group and another, then the lower group… they may be living comfortably, but they’re not able to participate as much in that conversation, I think the society as a whole suffers from that.

Zachary Woodman: Yeah. And not to mention that there might be something intrinsically wrong with excluding people from the conversation….

Roderick Long: Yes.

Zachary Woodman: …who would otherwise want to participate in it. Or excluding people from certain social practices, cultural rights etc.

Roderick Long: Yeah. To take an extreme example. A lot of people say, “Black people shouldn’t complain about the legacy of slavery because if the slavery never happened, then they would have been born back in Africa instead of here and so they would have been living in much worse poverty.” Well, actually they would never have been bored at all because this history meant that two different parents meant, but anyway.

Zachary Woodman: We don’t need to get into modal identity here. Transmodal identity. *laughs*

Roderick Long: Treating people like crap is not justified by the fact that your ability to do it is made possible by a series of events that had they happened otherwise those persons would have been worse off. It’s like if I come up to you and I punch you in the face and you fall over and then by sheer luck that means that you end up not being hit by a bullet that someone else was firing, I’ve actually benefited you by punching in the face.

I wasn’t trying to benefit you but as a matter of fact you’re better off. So now I might say, “Oh, instead of me owing you for punching in the face, you owe me for saving you from the bullet.” No. And so likewise when people are excluded from things you could say, “Well yeah, but under this regime where they’re excluded, they’re much better off and are much more comfortable than they would have ever been before.” What’s great. Want to keep them comfortable? Good. They wouldn’t want to impoverish everyone in the name of equality, but if people are excluded from things, it’s just not a respectful way to treat people.

And it doesn’t mean that you need all of it, you know… a bunch of stuff imposed by law?! Because that’s also not a respectful way to treat people but happily that’s not the only way we can deal with it.

Zachary Woodman: Alright. So the last question I always like to ask is what are three works, could be books, articles, documentaries. that people you think the listeners should read pertaining to this or generally to learn more about what you’re interested in.

Roderick Long: Okay. So on libertarian class theory, three books that I’d recommend. One is an anthology, I was a co-editor of it along with David Hart and Gary Chartier and Ross Kenyon. It’s titled Social Class and State Power: Exploring an Alternative Radical Tradition and it’s just a collection of various works in classical liberal class theory — both more lefty ones and more righty ones — from basically the 17th century through today. It gives us a range of different versions.

Then, specifically on the French liberal class theorists, in particular Charles Comte, Charles Dunoyer and Augustin Thierry, who wrote this journal in early 19th century France that developed a lot of these ideas early on. David Hart on his website has got a couple of different versions of his dissertation, and he’s got a couple of different titles depending on the version, but most of them have either as the title or the subtitle something like The Radical Liberalism of Charles Comte and Charles Dunoyer. And that’s useful because the class theory book that I mentioned before doesn’t have stuff from them. Well, it has like a little snippet or something but hardly anything from them has been translated. And so it’s a really useful account of them. And then, for the third thing, for more specifically the kind of class theory that left-libertarians go for in for these days, there’s yet another anthology: Markets Not Capitalism by Gary Chartier and Charles Johnson. It has a few older things like stuff from Benjamin Tucker in the 19th century but it’s mostly a recent — like from the last 20 years — left libertarian analysis of the interaction between state power and the power of big business and the corporate elite.

And so those are the three things that come to mind.

Zachary Woodman: Alright. Roderick Long, thank you for coming on the show. We hope to have you on again!

Roderick Long: Thanks, I enjoyed it!

Feature Articles
The Free Labor Market and Other Capitalist Just-So Stories

Some years ago, I coined the term “vulgar libertarianism” to refer to a particular, egregiously bad form of right-libertarian analysis. I did a long series of posts (“Vulgar Libertarianism Watch”) at my now mostly inactive blog, in which I applied the concept to a considerable volume of absolutely wretched material from the right-libertarian commentariat. I thought I’d pretty well left off beating that particular horse, considering the state of its corpse. But having just stumbled across the most astonishing example of vulgar libertarianism I’ve seen in years — “The Exploitation of Labor and Other Union Myths,” by Mark S. Pulliam (The INDEPENDENT REVIEW, Winter 2019/20) — I can’t resist picking up the old gore-flecked bat for a few more swings.

“Vulgar libertarianism” was, in part, a play on the vulgar Marxism of the Second and Third Internationals, from Engels and Kautsky on, which turned “historical materialism” into a crude self-parody. It was in equal part an allusion to what Marx called the “vulgar political economy” of the generation after Ricardo and Mill. By the latter term, Marx meant that political economy had ceased to be an attempt at the scientific explication of the laws of economics, and the economists had instead become “hired prize-fighters” on behalf of plutocratic interests. Classical political economy was originally a radical critique of the parasitism of landlords and the rent-seeking of mercantile capitalists. But with the triumph of the industrial capitalists in 1830s Britain, the focus of political economy shifted from scientific investigation and a radical challenge to concentrated economic power, to an apology for the status quo.

Here is how I first explained the idea:

This school of libertarianism has inscribed on its banner the reactionary watchword: “Them pore ole bosses need all the help they can get.” For every imaginable policy issue, the good guys and bad guys can be predicted with ease, by simply inverting the slogan of Animal Farm: “Two legs good, four legs baaaad.” In every case, the good guys, the sacrificial victims of the Progressive State, are the rich and powerful. The bad guys are the consumer and the worker, acting to enrich themselves from the public treasury. As one of the most egregious examples of this tendency, consider Ayn Rand’s characterization of big business as an “oppressed minority,” and of the Military-Industrial Complex as a “myth or worse.”

The ideal “free market” society of such people, it seems, is simply actually existing capitalism, minus the regulatory and welfare state: a hyper-thyroidal version of nineteenth century robber baron capitalism, perhaps; or better yet, a society “reformed” by the likes of Pinochet, the Dionysius to whom Milton Friedman and the Chicago Boys played Aristotle [Note — that should be Plato].

Vulgar libertarian apologists for capitalism use the term “free market” in an equivocal sense: they seem to have trouble remembering, from one moment to the next, whether they’re defending actually existing capitalism or free market principles. So we get the standard boilerplate article arguing that the rich can’t get rich at the expense of the poor, because “that’s not how the free market works” — implicitly assuming that this is a free market. When prodded, they’ll grudgingly admit that the present system is not a free market, and that it includes a lot of state intervention on behalf of the rich. But as soon as they think they can get away with it, they go right back to defending the wealth of existing corporations on the basis of “free market principles.”

And Pulliam’s article is 99 and 44/100% vulgar libertarianism — a defense of the current system in terms of “free market principles,” as though it were the kind of free market society which has never actually existed — all the way through.

That’s especially true of the central feature of vulgar libertarianism: its use of the language and theory of free market economics to defend actually-existing capitalism. From beginning to end, Pulliam makes dogmatic pronouncements about the impossibility of labor exploitation in the existing capitalist system — but with qualifiers and subordinate clauses that make it clear he’s referring to a storybook society that never existed

Pulliam states that, “[a]s written by progressive academics, the history of labor unions in America is as full of fiction as Aesop’s fables or the Grimm brothers fairy tales.” But the leftist account of the history of capitalism and of organized labor refers for the most part to a world that actually existed — whereas the “free market system” to which Pulliam pays homage is every bit as fabulous as the land of Cockaigne. His entire world is imaginary. Just for starters:

Self-ownership leads to recognition of the institution of private property. In a free society, one owns what one produces or acquires through consensual exchange. When entering into civil society, pursuant to a fictitious (but essential) social contract, people surrender some of their natural rights in exchange for the protection of laws. Our state and federal constitutions represent the terms of this “bargain.” 

No, historically speaking recognition of the institution of private property follows enclosure of the commons with the help of the state. The idea of property claims arising primarily from putting vacant land to use with one’s own labor was some ahistorical shit Locke came up with to justify the property — acquired through robbery — of the Whig aristocrats who financed his writing. In that, he was a lot like Pulliam.

But that really is just for starters. Look at all the asides he throws in, in his description of how our “free market” society allegedly works: “In a society based on individual liberty, limited government, and the protection of private property….” “in a free market [wages] would be determined by a consensual exchange between buyer (employer) and seller (employee) as the result of competition.” “In a free society, an employment relationship must be between willing parties on terms acceptable to both, without fraud or coercion.” “…in a free society…” “In a competitive market…” “In the world of free markets…” “In any event, is there an inherent inequality between labor and capital? The classical economic model shows otherwise.” (Never mind whether the classical economic model describes anything outside the economist’s head.) “As long as there is competition among buyers and sellers as well as the absence of external coercion…” “Absent monopsony power…” “All that matters is the existence of competition among uncoerced market participants.” And (again): “In a free society…” In every case, his assertion of how things actually work includes a qualifying clause whose conditions have never been met by any society in history.

All the phrases in quotes in the paragraph above describe a mythical society that has never existed outside capitalism’s legitimizing propaganda. The concentration of wealth in a few hands, the separation of labor from ownership of the means of production, and the rise of the wage system, did not occur as the result of the “original accumulation of capital” through individual abstention. The concentrated ownership of land by absentee landlords did not come about through homesteaders mixing their labor with the soil. The predominance of commodity production and exchange, and of the cash nexus, did not come about via “the propensity to truck and barter” or the emergence of specie exchange from “the problem of mutual coincidence of wants.” We are not living in a free market society that was created by a “social contract” in which people agreed to create a limited government for enforcing life, liberty, and property.

None of the defining features of the current capitalist system came about by the means asserted in right-libertarian Just-So Stories, any more than your parents found you under a cabbage leaf.

The overwhelming bulk of land in medieval England, outside the domains of King, Church, and nobility, was common property in the form of open fields to which possessory rights were periodically redivided among villagers, or common pasture and waste. The peasantry was forcibly robbed of its rights of possession over the means of subsistence, first by the gradual enclosure of the open fields in late medieval times, and then by Parliamentary Enclosure of common pasture, wood and waste from the 18th century on at the behest of local landed elites. It was by such means that a propertyless working class was created and thrown into a wage labor market in which their only choice was to accept labor on whatever terms were offered. 

These robberies were carried out in the interest of capitalist farmers who argued explicitly, in the political literature of the time, that the rural population either would not work for wages at all, or would refuse to work for as long hours or as low wages as the propertied classes desired, so long as they had independent access to the means of subsistence. It was through the rise of agrarian capitalism, enclosure, rack-renting and eviction that the wage labor force was first created, ready made for later industrial capitalists to use.

And the state was more than ready, from the earliest enclosures on, to whip and torture the dispossessed peasantry into some form of wage labor. This goes back to the Tudor laws against vagrancy, forcing “sturdy rogues” to accept work on whatever terms offered and cropping their ears — or worse — if they refused any job offered. And in the Industrial Revolution, the Laws of Settlement prohibited workers from leaving their parish of origin on their own to seek work on better terms. Instead, the parish Poor Law authorities loaded up the unemployed by the gross and shipped them across parish lines to be auctioned off to employers in labor-poor areas like industrial Manchester. In addition to that, the English working class in the last decade of the 18th century and the first two decades of the 19th was subjected not only to the Combination Laws but to a whole host of police legislation outlawing friendly societies and all large public gatherings — all enforced by administrative bodies without common  law due process — under the guise of “national security” during the Napoleonic Wars. 

The situation was quite accurately summarized by J. L. and Barbara Hammond:  On behalf of the capitalists English society was “taken to pieces … and reconstructed in the manner in which a dictator reconstructs a free government.” 

Contrary to the myth recited by Mises and others, capitalist accumulation was not financed primarily by the abstention of small masters who lived frugally and worked hard like good Protestants. Where such thrifty and abstemious capitalists actually existed, they were usually fronting for silent partners in the landed oligarchy or the mercantile corporations who provided most of the investment capital. 

So that “free market” relationship between employers and laborers, negotiating wages as equals, “without fraud or coercion,” and blah de blah de blah, Hail Ayn, Mother of Mises, was actually a negotiation between the people who were robbed, and either the robbers or the heirs and assigns of the robbers. And thanks to the state’s enforcement of the “property rights” of the robbers to their stolen loot, and all the ongoing forms of rent extraction and subsidy that exist to this day, the structure of inequality has replicated itself right up to the present.

And virtually all the things Pulliam and other right-libertarians take for granted, in their image of the “natural” free market society, as the result of spontaneous emergence, are likewise the result of imposition from above by overwhelming state force in collusion with the propertied classes. Believe it or not, the individual, fee-simple model of “private property” in land does not go back to Fred and Wilma’s bungalow in Bedrock. The almost universal model of land ownership, in the period from the neolithic revolution to the rise of the state, was the open field village system. It was suppressed by violence — in England by the measures recounted above, in Bengal by Warren Hastings, in Russia by the one-two punch of Stolypin and Stalin, by land clearances in British East Africa, ad infinitum, ad nauseam, world without end, amen. And as David Graeber recounts in Debt, societies organized around commodity exchange and specie currency were likewise imposed — again, violently — by states in the early modern period. 

In short, the entire picture of the world Pulliam presents, of the capitalist system as a “free society” that emerged through a social contract to create a limited government for enforcing property and contracts, with workers negotiating wages with employers based on their productivity in the free market, with no coercion or fraud, all of it facilitated by the division of labor and inventions brought about by those capitalists, is — to put it plainly — a big steaming pile of shit. What we have is a system imposed from the top down, and maintained to the present day, through the massive use of force on a global scale over a period of several centuries. Capitalism, as an actual historical system, did not emerge through the “invisible hand,” but by the iron fist.

But this whitewashing of the actual origins of capitalism and the wage system by no means exhausts all the factual errors in Pulliam’s diatribe. For example, he repeats all the standard right libertarian talking points about labor unions:

A union essentially operates as a cartel, fixing the price of its members’ labor by internal collusion rather than by market competition—just like members of the Organization of the Petroleum Exporting Countries (OPEC) work to increase the price of oil rather than letting the competitive market set the price. The internal price fixing for labor is called “collective bargaining.”

Like OPEC, a labor union threatens to withhold supply if the buyer does not agree to pay the “fixed” price. This withholding is called a “strike.” Unlike OPEC, however, a union attempts to prevent other sellers (who are not members of the cartel) from selling at a lower price, sometimes with the threat of violence. This is called a “picket line.” Strikers not only collectively withhold their own services (which is consensual) but also seek to prevent other workers from crossing the picket line (through force or coercion). Unions call these other workers “strike breakers” or “scabs,” but they are merely sellers willing to accept a lower wage—a function of competition and consensual exchange—which is entirely legitimate in a free society….

Also, unions, unlike OPEC, depend on government coercion. Federal law requires employers to “recognize” unions once they are “elected” by a majority of the employees; requires employers to negotiate exclusively with the union before taking action regarding the employees; prohibits employers from firing employees because of their union involvement; and prohibits employers from replacing striking workers under certain circumstances.

But like everyone else who uses these talking points, he doesn’t know the first thing about the actual history of labor struggle. One of the more amusing “myths” Pulliam sees fit to address is “The Model of Collective Bargaining Used in the Wagner Act Is beyond Reproach” — making it obvious that his imagined target is liberals and not leftists or socialists. 

You wouldn’t know, reading him, that conventional mass strikes and the exclusion of scabs originally weren’t the only, or even the primary, weapon in labor’s arsenal. You’ll find no greater critics of the effectiveness of the conventional strike than in the Industrial Workers of the World. Rather than giving your boss the opportunity to lock you out and hire scabs, it’s far more effective to go on strike on the job by slowing down, working to rule, having sick-outs at random unannounced intervals, or telling the customers all the dirt about how your employer cuts corners on quality.

Reading Pulliam, you’d also have no idea that the Wagner Act didn’t just forbid employers to do certain things. Far more importantly, it forbade workers to do a whole lot of things — namely, all those forms of direct action on the job I enumerated in the previous paragraph, along with a whole lot more. And that was the main point.

The central purpose of the Wagner Act was to domesticate organized labor, by enlisting union bureaucracies as enforcers of labor contracts against direct action and wildcat strikes by their own rank-and-file. It prohibited precisely those labor practices that were most effective — because most disruptive to employers — and limited unions to conventional strikes.

At the time Wagner was passed, the central business component in the New Deal coalition was capital-intensive, export-oriented heavy industry. Given the long planning horizons of mass production industry and its need for predictability, it was extremely vulnerable to disruption — and disruption was exactly what there was a lot of in the period before Wagner. At the same time, given its capital-intensiveness and the predominance of administered pricing in industrial markets, such firms could afford fairly large wage increases without much sacrifice.  

In its substantial provisions, the Wagner regime was virtually identical to the state of affairs under the American Plan’s company unions, developed under the ‘20s model of welfare capitalism. Under the American Plan — a leading proponent of which was GE’s Gerard Swope, also a central figure in FDR’s industrial policy — workers were guaranteed periodic productivity-based wage increases, recognition of seniority and a grievance process. In return, management got official recognition of its right to manage, and the union leadership was enlisted in enforcing contracts and keeping their members in line on the job.

By the way:  The knee-jerk reaction of Pulliam and like-minded right-libertarians will no doubt be to denounce the forms of direct action on the job I discussed earlier as violations of the employer’s rights. But let’s stop for a moment to consider the implications of the labor relation’s status as an incomplete contract. As Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis argue,

An employment relationship is established when, in return for a wage, the worker B agrees to submit to the authority of the employer A for a specified period of time in return for a wage w. While the employer’s promise to pay the wage is legally enforceable, the worker’s promise to bestow an adequate level of effort and care upon the tasks assigned, even if offered, is not. Work is subjectively costly for the worker to provide, valuable to the employer, and costly to measure. The manager-worker relationship is thus a contested exchange.

The very term “adequate effort” is meaningless, aside from whatever way its definition is worked out in practice based on the comparative bargaining power of worker and employer. It’s virtually impossible to design a contract that specifies ahead of time the exact levels of effort and standards of performance for a wage-laborer, and likewise impossible for employers to reliably monitor performance after the fact. Therefore, the workplace is contested terrain, and workers are justified entirely as much as employers in attempting to maximize their own interests within the leeway left by an incomplete contract. How much effort is “normal” to expend is determined by the informal outcome of the social contest within the workplace, given the de facto balance of power at any given time. And that includes slowdowns, “going canny,” and the like. 

The “normal” effort that employers are entitled to, when they buy labor-power, is a matter of convention. What constitutes a fair level of effort is entirely a subjective cultural norm, that can only be determined by the real-world bargaining strength of owners and workers in a particular workplace. It’s a lot like the local, contextual definitions (e.g. what constitutes “reasonable expectations” in a particular marketplace) that the common law of implied contract, fraud, etc., would depend on in a common law system absent state regulation. If libertarians like to think of “a fair day’s wage” as an open-ended concept, subject to the employer’s discretion and limited by what they can get away with, they should remember that “a fair day’s work” is equally open-ended.

I suppose Pulliam and like-minded folks could respond by arguing that the worker is morally obligated to work to their maximum effort, and to obey all orders as given, regardless of enforceability. But that doesn’t bear much looking into. The idea of maximum effort is ridiculous; literal maximum effort would lead to injury, or would otherwise be unsustainable over an extended time. And if qualified by “reasonable” or “sustainable,” we’re back to the same subjective test already discussed. As for literal, unquestioning obedience, they probably shouldn’t go there, considering that that’s the basis for the extremely effective tactic of working to rule. In practice, workplace productivity depends on the extent to which workers treat management directives and company policies as damage to be routed around, and keep things going despite management. 

Aside from all that, the threat of even conventional strikes has some value without forcible exclusion of scabs. There are natural rents accruing to the existing workforce’s tacit or situational knowledge of the production process, to the productivity accruing to the “social capital” embedded in the relationships they’ve built up over time, and to the cost of replacing them. The replacement cost is especially high because, given the tendency of power hierarchies to promote information-hoarding by workers, the tacit knowledge of the production process isn’t even in management’s possession. It, along with the social relationships built up by the previous workforce, must be painstakingly rebuilt over a period of years. Mises may have thought the miracle of double-entry bookkeeping turned the “Entrepreneur” into an omniscient planner, but reading Oliver Williamson and other New Institutionalists is useful as an antidote to such nonsense.

If you doubt the role of such tacit knowledge, or the extent to which corporate profit depends on enclosing it and workers’ cooperative intellect for rents, go back and reread the discussion above of the effectiveness of the work-to-rule tactic, in which workers stop correcting for the stupidity of management. 

Other portions of federal labor law, like the prohibition of sympathy and boycott strikes and the Presidential power of imposing “cooling off periods” under Taft-Hartley, are also aimed at clipping the wings of organized labor and depriving it of powers it would have had even without enforced collective-bargaining under Wagner. The great regional general strikes in the pre-Wagner period involved coordination all up and down the supply and distribution chains, with transport workers playing a key role in transforming single-industry strikes into general strikes. The cumulative effect of a concatenation of even partially effective strikes in factories, suppliers, wholesalers, warehouses, retailers, and transport workers refusing to haul scab cargo either from suppliers to factory or from factory to retailer, coupled with consumer boycotts encouraged by strikers, could be quite devastating.

So the Wagner regime, and the rest of federal labor law, were in effect a devil’s bargain in which workers were asked to give up their most effective weapons and instead restrict themselves entirely to declared mass strikes in the periods between the expiration of one contract and the ratification of another. It was like asking the Massachusetts militiamen at Concord to come out from behind the rocks, put on red uniforms and march in parade ground formation. And in return, they were given the same things provided via company unions under the American Plan:  productivity-based pay raises, respect for seniority, and a grievance process. What did employers get out of it? An end to wildcat strikes, slowdowns, random sick-outs, work-to-rule, and the open mouth — all enforced by the union bureaucracy, as partner to management. They got long-term stability, predictability, labor discipline enforced by the unions themselves, and — most important of all — union recognition of “management’s right to manage.”

Even Henry Hazlitt, who originally formulated many of these right-libertarian talking points in Economics in One Lesson, admitted that unions could be useful for price discovery, insofar as imperfect information left employers ignorant of the actual productivity of labor. But then Hazlitt probably deserves a little credit for intellectual honesty, at least compared to Pulliam.

Pulliam’s approach to the history of capitalism is similar hackwork.

Prior to industrialization and the division of labor in the form of specialized trades, nearly every man toiled on the land. If he owned the land outright, the crops he grew were his property. If he toiled on the land of another, he either paid rent or shared his crop with the owner. As trades developed, blacksmiths, cobblers, weavers, and the like either had the resources to acquire their own tools and supplies or had to rely on another to furnish these items—capital goods. In the former situation, he was his own master; in the latter, he was an apprentice or workman in the employ of another. The workman had to share the bounty of his labor with the provider of capital on terms agreeable to both. This is the conceptual origin of the modern employment relationship….

With the advent of the Industrial Revolution, a population that for centuries had subsisted—sometimes barely or not at all—primarily on labor-intensive agricultural production increasingly became engaged in factory production. This was a momentous shift. Technology, enabled by capital investment and the profit motive, transformed the economy. Factories, machinery, innovation, and inventions (including the steam engine) wrought dramatic social changes…. People often relocated to pursue opportunities, and the sheer number of people vastly increased due to sharply declining mortality rates. Capitalism transformed society in many ways, most of them quite positive.

That may be the “conceptual origin” of the employment relationship, in the minds of employers and their hired propagandists. But it’s certainly not the historical origin. 

Pulliam writes as though the immaculate “provider of capital” just happened to be there, in possession of the means of production, and the workman just happened to not be in possession of them, so that these two individuals who just happened to find themselves in this circumstance were left to negotiate — as equals — a division of the labor product “on terms agreeable to both.”

But in reality, the terms of this “sharing” were negotiated in a process — to borrow a phrase popular among right-libertarians — comparable to a wolf and a sheep voting on what to have for dinner. Capital didn’t just happen to be concentrated in the hands of a few employers, and workers didn’t just happen to have only their labor power to sell. There was a history behind these circumstances — a history, as Marx put it, written in letters of blood and fire. I already summarized that history above.

When the autonomist Harry Cleaver teaches his reading course on Capital, he assigns the historical material on primitive accumulation as background before starting his students out at the beginning with use-value, exchange-value, the circuit of capital, etc. The reason is to show that all the talk about necessary labor and surplus labor, the struggle over the working day, and all the rest of it, isn’t just some abstract theory of price formation in political economy. It’s a real power relationship resulting from historic crimes. 

As for the “division of labor” and all those “inventions,” Pulliam ignores — as we have already seen — the question of how it just happened to be the owners of large-scale capital who were in the position of having the capital to invest, and hence of reaping the benefits of all that new productivity. As I argued elsewhere recently, “[e]very single function allegedly performed by capitalists — investing, creating jobs, etc. — is something that could have been done horizontally/cooperatively by workers themselves if capitalists hadn’t preempted those functions.” Capitalists’ money is just “a symbolic marker of their accumulated wealth,” which enables them to preempt the channels of investment, finance, and coordination which might otherwise be organized horizontally by workers themselves. So billionaire capitalists aren’t actually “inventing” anything. As I wrote of Elon Musk:

He bought legal rights to boss around the people who are doing the inventing and developing, along with legal rights to their product. Literally all capitalists do is enclose the social intellect and cooperative labor of those who do the actual inventing, and extract rents from it.

Pulliam, after his extended indulgence in imaginary history, has the gall to write: “It is intellectually dishonest to skip from an agricultural economy to the factory system and deny the factory owner any credit for amassing the capital, devising the machines, and incurring the risk that made the enterprise possible.”

What’s really dishonest is to skip from an agricultural economy to the factory system without asking how the factory owner amassed the capital, how he happened to confront a labor market of landless, propertyless proletarians, or how he wound up with ownership rights to a machine almost certainly “devised” by someone else. And that’s exactly what he does. He literally skips from the agricultural economy to the factory system, and then manufactures a fake history about “social contracts,” “free societies,” and “limited government” to fill in the gaps.  

Pulliam also repeats the dogma, familiar to any regular reader of the polemics at Mises.org, that “workers will be paid equal to the value of the marginal product of labor” (“absent monopsony power,” that is).

It takes an especial amount of chutzpah to repeat this chestnut after four decades in which real wages have remained stagnant while labor productivity continued to rise — but after, purely coincidentally I am sure, the power of organized labor was broken — and profits and management salaries have skyrocketed several hundred percent.

Mises, for all his faults, was at least honest enough to admit that when an a priori prediction apparently fails to materialize, one should consider the possibility that one of the conditions attached to that prediction has not been met. In this case, the failure of wages to match productivity increases suggests that some or all of the conditions in Pulliam’s subordinate clauses — “absent coercion,” “in a competitive market without monopsony power,” etc. — haven’t been met. And in fact, the respective bargaining power of worker and employer reflect a coercive background, resulting both from past violence and from present state intervention on behalf of employers.

But the problem with marginal productivity isn’t just its application — it’s with the theory itself. As stated by John Bates Clark, marginal productivity theory is essentially circular. The “marginal productivity” of a factor input is what it adds to the final price of the product, which means that whatever a factor owner is able to get away with charging for their “services” is by definition their marginal productivity. So when the owner of one “factor” (capital) extracts rents at the expense of the owner of another factor (labor), as a result of an unequal power relationship, their respective “marginal productivity” is determined by their power relationship. In other words, it’s not so much that profits and wages are determined by the marginal productivity of capital and labor, as the other way around.

Here’s an especially good howler. “Class conflict is a favorite theme for liberals.” This approximates, as close as humanly possible, the direct opposite of the truth about liberalism. Pulliam conflates liberalism with the left, when they are entirely different things. The origins of liberalism lay in the Progressive movement at the turn of the 20th century. It was a direct outgrowth of the rise of the managerial corporation and the complex of other large, bureaucratic institutions that arose to serve its needs.

According to Rakesh Khurana of the Harvard Business School (in From Higher Aims to Hired Hands), the first corporation managers came from an industrial engineering background and saw their job as doing for the entire organization what they’d previously done for production on the shop floor. The managerial revolution in the large corporation, Khurana writes, was in essence an attempt to apply the engineer’s approach (standardizing and rationalizing tools, processes, and systems) to the organization as a system.

And according to Yehouda Shenhav (Manufacturing Rationality: The Engineering Foundations of the Managerial Revolution), Progressivism was the ideology of the managers and engineers who administered the large organizations; political action was a matter of applying the same principles they used to rationalize their organizations to society as a whole….

At the core of Progressivism’s managerialist ethos was the imperative of transcending class and ideological divisions through the application of disinterested expertise. 

In Shenhav’s account this apolitical ethos grew out of engineers’ self-perception: “American management theory was presented as a scientific technique administered for the good of society as a whole without relation to politics.” Frederick Taylor, whose managerial approach was a microcosm of Progressivism, saw bureaucracy as “a solution to ideological cleavages, as an engineering remedy to the war between the classes.” Both Progressives and industrial engineers “were horrified at the possibility of ‘class warfare’” and saw “efficiency” as a means to “social harmony, making each workman’s interest the same as that of his employers.”

We see this even in present-day liberalism. Liberals may chide “bad” billionaires for their greed, but their vision isn’t of a society without billionaires — it’s of a society in which “patriotic billionaires” like Warren Buffett pay their “fair share” of taxes, along with paying a living wage, and everybody gets along. Liberals like Nancy Pelosi, fundamentally, believe that it’s entirely possible to become a billionaire by doing good and without exploiting labor. They want a society that gives the worker a bigger slice of the pie, while still recognizing the legitimacy of profit as the result of entrepreneurial genius. Basically, they just want the capitalism of Henry Ford, without the antisemitic crankery. 

Pulliam, to no one’s surprise, puts the blame entirely on organized labor as the source of violence in labor disputes. But Benjamin Tucker, a principled free market libertarian who actually knew something about the history of capitalism and its functioning, saw things a bit differently. In surveying the violence at Homestead and elsewhere, he argued that the capitalists were the primary aggressors: “the original violation of liberty in this matter is traceable directly to them.” They sat atop a system founded on robbery; their profit depended on privileges, artificial property rights, and monopolies enforced by the state at the expense of labor, and other forms of state intervention that artificially reduced the bargaining power of labor. A free labor market, he said,

has constantly been denied, not only to the laborers at Homestead, but to the laborers of the entire civilized world. And the men who have denied it are the Andrew Carnegies. Capitalists of whom this Pittsburgh forge-master is a typical representative have placed and kept upon the statute-books all sorts of prohibitions and taxes (of which the customs tariff is among the least harmful) designed to limit and effective in limiting the number of bidders for the labor of those who have labor to sell….

….Let Carnegie, Dana & Co. first see to it that every law in violation of equal liberty is removed from the statute-books. If, after that, any laborers shall interfere with the rights of their employers, or shall use force upon inoffensive “scabs,” or shall attack their employers’ watchmen, whether these be Pinkerton detectives, sheriff’s deputies, or the State militia, I pledge myself that, as an Anarchist and in consequence of my Anarchistic faith, I will be among the first to volunteer as a member of a force to repress these disturbers of order and, if necessary, sweep them from the earth. But while these invasive laws remain, I must view every forcible conflict that arises as the consequence of an original violation of liberty on the part of the employing classes, and, if any sweeping is done, may the laborers hold the broom! 

Pulliam saves the biggest howler of all for his conclusion, in which he argues that, in the forty years since unions were broken through the shift to neoliberal state policies under Reagan and Thatcher — with substantial help from people like him — workers have never had it so good. At a time when Gloomy Guses on the Left see decades of wage stagnation, and a period since 2008 when most new jobs are low-wage, and an entire generation is stuck in unpayable college debt, unpaid internships, precarious jobs, and “entry-level” positions that require masters degrees but pay $15/hr, Pulliam sees an endless carnival of worker empowerment. Why, he breathlessly enthuses,

In the “gig economy” enabled by smart-phone apps and similar technology, many workers prefer the flexible hours of independent-contractor arrangements in lieu of traditional employment. Many employees telecommute, work part-time, or even share jobs—options that were unimaginable in 1935.

It’s only fitting that Pulliam, a showman until the last, closes an article full of fairy tales with the biggest fairy tale of all. I’d normally be skeptical that even a carnival barker like him could find big enough suckers to sell this pitch to. But on further reflection, it’s not the people actually suffering from the stagnant wages, skyrocketing rents and healthcare costs, and mountains of debt who are his marks. It’s the billionaires who shell out the money for this crap.

Commentary
Solarpunk Visions: A Call to Action

Solarpunk is a somewhat newer subculture inspired by science fiction, most notably steampunk and cyberpunk, and environmentalism. It is a media genre that has produced amazing works in the fields of video games, animation, film, television, literature, and music. It also exists as a real life movement which has influenced areas of society such as fashion, architecture, and technology, while pushing towards a more ecologically sustainable technologically-enhanced future.

While the movement as a whole does not subscribe to any particular set of political or economic values, many in the community subscribe to some variation of social ecology, eco-socialism, green libertarianism, or environmental anarchism. As such, they envision a world where the pursuit and implementation of green technology is equally as important as permaculture and gardening and they see their goals as real, grounded, and sustainable, even while inspired by speculative fiction.

It is this idea that has spawned Solarpunk Action Week.

Solarpunk Action Week will take place every six months in accordance with the planting seasons with dates announced before each planned Week of Action on their official Tumblr and Mastodon. The next Week of Action is from March 8th-14th, 2020 and is a week of independent decentralized and autonomous actions all undertaken with the goal of helping to create a solarpunk society.

So what can you do to participate? Well there are plenty of options. Start a food garden using techniques such as permaculture, vertical and rooftop gardening, guerrilla gardening, and responsible GMO use. Install solar panels or a wind turbine on your property. Hop on the SolarCoin train or even invest in FairCoin. Build one of Precious Plastic‘s four machines to help recycle your plastic waste. Make changes to work towards a zero waste lifestyle. Use the heat generated from your crypto-mining operation to help grow more tropical plants in your greenhouse or to heat your home during the winter. Weatherproof your house to prevent unnecessary energy use. Support green tech projects such as the Fairphone. Properly recycle your electronics. Create a community meshnet, tool sharing shed, hackerspace/makerspace, bicycle repair cooperative, lending library, science lab, free store, clothing swap, and/or seedshare. Start composting. Start spreading the idea of using Cell 411 over Lyft or Uber. Join a group such as the Environmental Unionism Caucus of the Industrial Workers of the World, Earth First!, or Fight Toxic Prisons. Take action to help stop the rollout of 5G until privacy and health concerns are properly addressed. Utilize sharing platforms such as Freecycle, Shared Earth, and OLIO. The possibilities are nearly endless if you put your mind to it.

So participate however you wish to and are able. The limit is only your imagination and resources. And be sure to post your action ideas using #solarpunkweek on Mastodon and Tumblr to share with others around the world doing the same. Hope to see you back there every six months until we’ve achieved our solarpunk utopia.

 

Italian, Stateless Embassies
La Guerra delle Polpette 2

Un sogno impossibile

Di Logan Marie Glitterbomb. Originale pubblicato il 9 febbraio 2020 con il titolo The War on Hamburgers Part 2: An Impossible Dream. Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.

Nel mio precedente saggio La Guerra delle Polpette dicevo che se vogliamo creare un sistema alimentare più ecologico dobbiamo consumare meno carne, ma anche che la maggior parte delle persone non fa così perché lo considera un sacrificio. Indicavo anche alternative, come l’Impossible Whopper di Burger King, per rendere più digeribile il “sacrificio”. Qualcuno ha pensato che stessi promuovendo il consumismo etico. Niente di più lontano dal vero.

Se non risulta abbastanza chiaro dai miei scritti precedenti come Agorism vs. Ethical Consumerism: What’s Worth Your Money?, lasciatemi dire che non credo nell’esistenza del consumismo etico, in una forma o nell’altra, nell’attuale panorama sociale. Come sistema per navigare nel mercato io sostengo tattiche come l’imprenditoria nel mercato nero o grigio, il boicottaggio mirato di massa, campagne di disinvestimento e sindacalismo di base, ma non il consumismo etico. E l’Impossible Whopper è, non a caso, proprio un esempio del perché il consumismo etico non funziona.

Già sapevo che comprare alternative vegane fa poco o nulla per cambiare la sostanza di base di questo sistema agricolo industriale capitalista, ma serve solo per essere cooptato dal capitale che così crea un mercato di nicchia di cui soddisfare la domanda. Già sapevo che se vogliamo salvare l’ambiente dobbiamo abbandonare gradualmente l’attuale agricoltura industriale per abbracciare un sistema fatto di produzioni biologiche locali, permacoltura e un uso responsabile degli ogm. Già sapevo che dobbiamo passare dagli allevamenti industriali ad un sistema fatto di allevamenti decentrati a livello locale e carni prodotte artificialmente. Già sapevo che occorre passare da una dieta fortemente carnivora ad una più vegetariana, pur ammettendo l’impossibilità di un veganismo mondiale. Non avevo però tenuto conto di una cosa, che se è vero che una scelta più vegetariana ha meno costi di una più carnivora, non tutto il vegetariano nasce uguale.

Allora, dov’è la questione? Cosa ho dimenticato? Che l’Impossible Whopper è fatto con la soia. Ma non soia qualunque, bensì un apposito ogm che produce l’ematina, che dà uno spiccato sapore di carne. Di per sé, l’alterazione genetica non è un pericolo, ma la maggior parte della soia ogm coltivata nei cosiddetti stati uniti, compresa quella usata per l’Impossible Burger, è compatibile RoundUp, brevettata e prodotta dalla Bayer (che di recente si è fusa con la Monsanto) e trattata con un pericoloso pesticida conosciuto come glifosato ovvero, appunto, RoundUp.

Se è vero che vari studi dimostrano che gran parte del glifosato va via lavando a fondo il prodotto, il che riduce i possibili effetti negativi associati al consumo, è però anche vero che il glifosato è pur sempre dannoso per l’ambiente e, potenzialmente, per la nostra salute in generale. Viene spruzzato su ciò che mangiamo, filtra nella nostra terra, finisce nella nostra acqua e viene ingerito dagli animali, tutte cose con cui possiamo entrare in contatto o consumare. Allora la domanda è: non è che i presunti vantaggi ambientali derivati dal fatto che l’Impossible Whopper è vegetariano sono annullati dal fatto che sia fatto con soia ogm brevettata trattata con glifosato, magari assieme ad altre pratiche pericolose per l’ambiente come la monocoltura?

In tutta onestà, non sono sicuro. Non ho ricerche o numeri da mostrare. Sono solo una persona preoccupata che cerca di capire come fare un po’ meno danni al mondo che ci ospita. No, Burger King non ci salverà. E neanche il consumismo etico. Ma possiamo diminuire il consumo di carne, mangiare più alimenti completi, mangiare biologico quando possiamo, coltivare il nostro orto se ci è possibile, e sostenere l’agricoltura locale quando possiamo farlo. Questo è il meglio che possiamo fare mentre ci diamo da fare per smantellare e rimpiazzare l’attuale sistema distruttivo basato sull’industrializzazione dell’allevamento e dell’agricoltura.

Stigmergy - C4SS Blog
Bring C4SS to LibertyCon 2020!

The Center for a Stateless Society (C4SS) wants to bring about a world where individuals are liberated from oppressive states, structural poverty, and social injustice. We use academic studies, book reviews, opinion editorials, essay collections, podcasts, and social media to spread left-wing market anarchist ideas far and wide.

Students For Liberty’s LibertyCon (April 3-5) is the year’s premier gathering of libertarian minds from all over the world – and C4SS is a mere $800 away from getting an exhibitor table at this event. This is a wonderful opportunity to promote radical left market anarchist ideas among libertarians from around the globe.

Every penny counts and the Center appreciates any and all help you are willing to give. Let’s get C4SS to LibertyCon and start building the new world in the shell of the old!

Head over here to donate!

Commentary
Why I Don’t Support the Women’s March

On January 21, 2017, I took to the streets of DC alongside thousands of other women supposedly joined in unity and solidarity with the rights of all women, but what I experienced said otherwise. Even in the weeks leading up to the march there were issues between white organizers and organizers of color as well as attempts to distance the march from sex worker rights activists within the women’s movement. But after much fuss from the wider activist community and threats of boycotts and counter-demonstrations by those standing in solidarity with sex workers, they quietly reversed their public stance, adding support for sex workers back into their platform.

Despite these setbacks, I still held out hope after seeing how organizers were at least somewhat responsive to criticism and how the march was ultimately made up of various elements, some more reactionary and some more revolutionary. I was there to network with the revolutionaries and build from there. However when I and several fellow anti-fascist activists split from the general inauguration protests to join the Womens March in solidarity, we were met with distrust, hatred, and even bigotry. Not only was my womanhood questioned by several transphobic “feminists” but several liberals attempted to unmask me and other activists and even went so far as to complain to the police, having them swarm us and demand that we unmask or leave.

We did neither, continuing to march for the rights of all women within the confines of the law and even met a kind movement elder who apologized for her sisters’ behavior, checked in on our mental and physical health, and offered us water and food, wishing us safety as we parted ways. Eventually the lack of solidarity from the rest of the marchers became too disheartening and so we left to join the other J20 protesters elsewhere.

When the Women’s March anniversary rolled around, I began seeing local events pop up in celebration, and acknowledging that my city is slightly better on these issues than others, I considered going to our local solidarity march just to check it out and see if it was any better. After all, the Women’s March had gained some notoriety for celebrating the birthday of former Black Panther and current fugitive Assata Shakur on their social media so it couldn’t be all bad, could it? But then I realized that the rhetoric was still vagina-centric, still barely acknowledged trans women and their issues, still lacked a strong intersectional analysis, and seemed to be much more of an anti-Trump rally than an actual women’s rights march.

I’m not interested in protesting Trump. He’s part of a much larger problem, a problem that I thought the Women’s March could be in a position to address at least a little. Instead the Women’s March seems only marginally distinguishable from a Hillary Clinton rally, making one wonder if most of these middle class white women would even be marching if Trump hadn’t won. Take your bad vagina puns and ugly crocheted hats and fuck off. I have no ill will towards the amazing activists in Codepink and others who have attempted to inject more radical politics into the Women’s March over the past few years but I don’t have that kind of patience at the moment. Come back and grab me when the March is serious about fighting for the rights of all women, until then I’m sitting this one out.

 

Feature Articles
The War on Hamburgers Part 2: An Impossible Dream

In my essay The War on Hamburgers: A Practical Alternative to World Veganism, I posited that the way to create a more environmentally-friendly food system would require us to consume less meat but that a majority of people would not do so if it felt like a sacrifice. As such, I touted alternatives such as Burger King’s Impossible Whopper as a means to make such a “sacrifice” easier to digest. This was seen by some as me advocating for the practice of ethical consumerism. That could not be further from the truth of the matter.

If my previous writings such as Agorism vs. Ethical Consumerism: What’s Worth Your Money? and others have not made it apparent, let me clarify that I do not believe that any sort of ethical consumerism exists within this current economic framework. I advocate agorist alternatives and tactics such as black and grey market entrepreneurship, targeted mass boycotts and divestment campaigns, and grassroots syndicalism as a means to navigate the market, not ethical consumerism. And the Impossible Whopper is an unsurprising example of exactly why ethical consumerism does not work.

I already knew that purchasing vegan alternatives does little to nothing to change the underlying core of this capitalist system of industrial agriculture but rather just serves to be co-opted by capitalism’s creation of niche markets to fill such demand. I already knew that in order to save the environment we would have to transition away from industrialized agriculture entirely and towards a system of decentralized local organic food production, permaculture, and responsible GMO use. I already knew that we would have to transition away from factory farming and towards a system of decentralized local livestock farming and cultured or lab grown meat. I already knew that we’d have to shift our diets away from heavy meat consumption and towards more plant-base options, while also understanding that a call for world veganism is an impossible one. I had forgotten to take into account, however, that while plant-based options are usually less environmentally costly than meat-based ones, not all plant-based options are created equally.

So what’s the issue? What did I overlook? Namely that the Impossible Whopper is made with soy. And not just any soy, but specifically genetically modified soybeans, which is used to make the heme which gives it the meaty flavor that is so impressive. While genetic modification is not a danger in itself, a majority of genetically modified soy in the so-called united states, including that used to make the Impossible Burger, is RoundUp ready soy, which is patented and owned by Bayer (who more recently merged with Monsanto), and sprayed with the harmful pesticide known as glyphosate or RoundUp.

While studies have shown that washing your produce thoroughly helps remove a majority of the glyphosate remaining on your produce before eating, thus reducing possible negative health effects associated with consumption, glyphosate is still harmful to the environment and potentially our health more broadly. It is sprayed onto our food, seeps into our soil, washes into our water, and is ingested by wildlife, all of which we may interact with and/or consume. So the real question is, is the supposed environmental benefit of the Impossible Whopper being vegan outweighed by the fact that it is made with patented genetically modified soybeans sprayed down with glyphosate, likely in tandem with other environmentally harmful practices such as monocropping?

Honestly, I’m unsure. I don’t have the right studies to look at or the numbers to crunch. I’m just a concerned citizen trying to figure out how to cause slightly less harm to the world that houses us. No, Burger King will not save us. No, ethical consumerism will not save us. But let’s lower our meat consumption, eat more whole foods, eat organic when we can, grow our own food if possible, and support local farmers in our community when we can afford to. That’s about the best we can do in the meantime while we work to dismantle and replace our current destructive system of factory farming and industrial agriculture.

Commentary
Combating Big Tech: An Agorist Response to the YouTube Strike

From December 10th-13th, 2019 (December 14th-17th for those in the UK due to the desire to not limit access to important political news during an election period), YouTube creators and their supporters went on strike, refusing to upload or watch any content or even log onto the site, to protest YouTube’s new terms of service. The new policies put many creators at risk of losing income, and for some, their entire channels. The walkout was the collective effort of the YouTubers Union and the FairTube campaign and their allies. Both of these campaigns are an example of grassroots wildcat unionism, something championed by syndicalists and agorists alike.

The typical agorist response to a corporate giant like YouTube is to create a more decentralized alternative. Thankfully there have been many such alternatives that have been made by activists and programmers concerned with issues of privacy and free speech. BitChute, DTube, and PeerTube are probably the biggest examples in the current market. While BitChute and DTube seem to have been mostly overrun with alt-right types in the wake of previous YouTube censorship policies which successfully drove many of them offsite, PeerTube seems to be decidedly more left-friendly. That being said, there’s no reason to cede a good platform to the alt-right just because they flocked to it first. We need hardcore leftists and anarchists of all stripes to flock to these platforms themselves and disrupt the algorithm in hopes of yanking a few misguided souls out of the alt-right rabbit hole.

So if there are usable alternatives such as PeerTube, DTube, and BitChute,  why bother trying to unionize YouTube? Well, it’s simple, really: YouTube still has the biggest audience. Sure, creators could move to alternative platforms, but it’s not a guarantee their audience will go with them. Plus, while DTube and BitChute allow users to tip creators directly and DTube even awards creators in cryptocurrency for the traffic they create, such alternatives are often less reliable as a source of income than the ad revenue that can come from running a channel on YouTube.

So yes, start your BitChute, DTube, or PeerTube channel and fund it using SubscribeStar or Bitbacker (although can we all please agree to just let Hatreon die?) if that’s what you want to do, but at the same time don’t forget about the hardworking working class people that make a living as YouTube content creators and who refuse to be driven off of a platform their content helped to build into the financial success it is today.

And sure, the strike didn’t bring YouTube to its knees nor did the strikers win their demand to halt the new terms of service change, but that was expected. This was merely a trial exercise and one of the first steps to building solidarity. But even a smaller action like this did help to show our power as YouTube’s traffic did noticeably decrease, even if only slightly, during the strike, sending a clear message to the corporate giants: they need to listen to the creators on their platform and their needs, or face financial blowback.

As of the writing of this article, the campaign has not announced their next step, but more information can be found on the FairTube and YouTubers Union websites and social media moving forward for those who wish to keep updated. Don’t just consume content, support those who create it.

Italian, Stateless Embassies
Crescita della Decrescita e Confusione Socialdemocratica

Di Asem. Originale pubblicato il 23 gennaio 2020 con il titolo The Growth of Degrowth and the Confusion of Democratic Socialists. Traduzione di Enrico Sanna.

Bisogna ammettere che chiunque abbia inventato l’espressione Decrescita ha fatto un pessimo servizio a chi sostiene che occorre ridimensionare l’attuale modo di produzione industriale per, ad un tempo, fermare i cambiamenti climatici e migliorare le condizioni di vita di tutti. Detto semplicemente, la Decrescita è una proposta che punta a ridurre le emissioni di anidride carbonica riducendo il bisogno di risorse necessarie alla vita nelle società industrializzate. Tra le proposte c’è un ritorno all’agricoltura locale con il consumo di prodotti di stagione al posto dell’attuale industria alimentare, o la produzione locale di energia, ad esempio con pannelli solari e impianti eolici, al posto dell’energia da combustibili fossili che genera traffici intercontinentali. Chi propone queste cose ammette che ciò comporta un cambio drastico dello stile di vita per tutti, anche i poveri. Molti beni di base oggi largamente accessibili non sarebbero più tali. Sarebbe difficile, ad esempio, farsi un panino al tonno in località lontane dal mare. Mentre le grosse attività produttive, dato il loro attuale consumo energetico, smetterebbero di funzionare. Una volta riconosciuti i sacrifici, dobbiamo ammettere però che la Decrescita porta con sé molti benefici, come il taglio di due terzi della settimana lavorativa e il calo drastico degli affitti rispetto ai redditi.

La Decrescita è un prodotto diretto del movimento ambientalista, ma le idee non sono una sua esclusiva. Almeno in ambito anarchico, l’idea di piccole attività manifatturiere e agricole, gestite da una rete di contadini e operai con funzioni in parte intersecantisi e scambiabili, può essere fatta risalire alle idee di Kropotkin di un secolo fa, ma la ritroviamo anche – con più chiarezza e coscienza ecologica – negli scritti di Murray Bookchin e, nell’ultimo decennio, nell’anarchico Peter Gelderloos di An Anarchist Solution To Global Warming. Qui Gelderloos immagina piccole città senza automobili, con una produzione agricola locale, la trasformazione dei rifiuti in biocarburanti, energia prodotta localmente in piccoli impianti che, con alcune eccezioni come gli ospedali, di notte sono spenti. Le sue idee riguardo la lotta al riscaldamento globale sono praticamente quelle di chi propone la Decrescita. Di questi ultimi Gelderloos condivide anche lo scetticismo verso il progresso tecno-scientifico. Detto ciò, troviamo le stesse idee anche altrove.

Ultimamente è nato un dibattito tra sostenitori della Decrescita e marxisti democratici ugualmente interessati a problemi ecologici. Kevin Carson ha affrontato il tema in un saggio recente, in cui giustamente mostra le sue simpatie per la Decrescita. Carson vede però nelle due parti una sorta di imprenditorialismo verde che impone tassi di anidride carbonica dai palazzi del potere comandati da politici eletti che pigiano bottoni su un grande schermo mentre scienziati in camice si danno da fare per tenere in piedi Project Cybersyn 2.0, mentre il resto della società si alza la mattina e riceve le istruzioni sul cellulare, va a lavorare presso la Walmart dei Lavoratori e produce tutto quello che il Socialismo Cibernetico gli ordina di produrre per tenere viva la pianificazione centrale. Pur dichiarando guerra a questi “Ecomodernisti”, Kevin ha trascurato alcuni punti dei fautori della decrescita, soprattutto il fatto che hanno scarso interesse per le frizioni di classe. I sostenitori della decrescita analizzano i problemi di classe in due testi almeno (uno parla della questione della rendita e dell’allungamento dell’orario di lavoro per potersi permettere la casa e limitare la propria impronta ecologica), ma sono riluttanti ad ammettere che all’origine del problema ci sono i proprietari delle case e, in un elenco di proposte, solo un punto va in questa direzione. I sostenitori della Decrescita chiedono di “sostenere il settore economico cooperativo no-profit che si sta espandendo in Spagna”, il che si tradurrebbe in cooperative di consumo e credito mutuo o, a voler essere proprio buoni, cooperative di lavoratori come la spagnola Mondragon. Improbabile, vista l’assenza di una critica chiara sul lavoro salariato e sulle relazioni sociali dipendente-datore nei testi sulla Decrescita. Questo non significa che tra loro non ci sono rossi, ma semplicemente che la Decrescita somiglia più ad una sorta di socialdemocrazia comunistica fortemente regolata.

Visto che nessuna delle parti giunge ad una definizione precisa della “crescita”, si finisce per parlarsi addosso reciprocamente, e non aiuta il fatto che una parte si definisca “decrescita” nonostante tra le proprie fila ci sia una frangia di primitivisti e sostenitori anti-civilizzazione. Non meraviglia se da fuori si fatica a capire i concetti. Tra i marxisti confusi c’è Leigh Phillips, autore di The People’s Repubblic of Walmart e Austerity Ecology & the Collapse-Porn Addicts: A Defence of Growth, Progress, Industry and Stuff. Kevin Carson dedica quasi quaranta pagine, su cinquanta, alla confutazione delle sue tesi. Phillips, autodichiaratosi nemico della Decrescita e sostenitore accanito della crescita, in realtà sostiene la crescita solo per certi versi, come il prodotto interno lordo, la produttività oraria in fabbrica, e la crescita in termini di reddito annuale della classe lavoratrice. Allo stesso tempo, Phillips è contro la crescita quando questa produce disoccupazione, detenuti e senzacasa. Da marxista qual è, si entusiasma per le vittorie della classe lavoratrice, come la giornata lavorativa di otto ore e il fine settimana libero, e immagino che sarebbe favorevole alla proposta, che sta prendendo piede, di ridurre la settimana lavorativa a quattro giorni. Insomma, Phillips è un sostenitore della decrescita, con la minuscola e solo per certe cose.

Il teorico della Decrescita Jason Hickel ha recentemente scritto un articolo che già nel titolo ha due termini in contraddizione semantica tra loro: ‘degrowth’ and ‘radical abundance’ (‘decrescita’ e ‘abbondanza totale’, ndt). Nel sottotitolo troviamo una frase che, se presa fuori contesto, sembrerebbe estratta da qualche libro o articolo sul comunismo di lusso completamente automatizzato: “Una delle affermazioni fondamentali dell’economia della decrescita è che ristabilendo i servizi pubblici e allargando i beni comuni si potrà avere ciò che occorre per vivere bene senza dover avere un forte reddito.” È vero che tra i sostenitori della Decrescita ce ne sono che diffidano della scienza e della tecnica, persone che non esitano a dire che per evitare i cambiamenti climatici dobbiamo tornare allo stile di vita degli anni cinquanta, ma sono proprio quelli come Hickel, sostenitori più dell’abbondanza materiale che della scarsità, che hanno una posizione più articolata con la loro critica della crescita in termini di prodotto interno lordo, e che coerentemente limitano la “decrescita” ad una piccola porzione delle attività sociali, come il lavoro salariato, la rendita, la produzione di massa capitalista, cose la cui riduzione si tradurrebbe in una crescita del tempo libero, maggiore spazio vivibile, alimenti demercificati per tutti e, cosa importantissima, crescita delle arti e delle scienze in conseguenza dell’abbondanza di tempo libero e della ricerca di un’attività che abbia un senso.

Phillips e quelli come lui vanno in confusione, o non capiscono il punto, quando si parla di calcolo, e questo per due ragioni. La prima è che la decrescita usa letteralmente la stessa etichetta di un sottogruppo degli pseudoprimitivisti, così che è difficile superare i condizionamenti generati dall’associazione mentale. E dato che Phillips ha scritto un intero libro in materia, è difficile perdonare questo passo falso. La seconda riguarda l’economia e il calcolo ecologico, per cui Phillips e i suoi colleghi Srnicek e Williams (autore di Inventing the Future) faticano a comprendere la superiorità della produzione iperlocale operata da piccoli gruppi in organizzazioni fluide pensate appositamente.

Srnicek e Williams fanno l’esempio della contabilizzazione delle emissioni. Nonostante l’impronta ecologica lasciata dal trasporto intercontinentale, dicono, importare prodotti agricoli fuori stagione in Gran Bretagna è più ecologico che produrre a livello nazionale. Questo perché il sistema globale ottimizza i flussi e aumenta la produzione così da permettere ai britannici di avere questi prodotti a basso prezzo e con una minore impronta ecologica. Verissimo. Pertanto, ogni volta che si fa il calcolo economico della produzione di massa opposta ad organizzazioni stigmergiche ad hoc di produttori e consumatori indipendenti, ecco che la prima risulta sempre più efficiente e produttiva, ma solo nel presente. L’errore del paragone sta nel fatto di misurare l’efficienza in quel momento senza considerare la crescita e l’evoluzione. Per quanto Phillips abbia scritto un libro intitolato In Defense of Growth, Progress, Industry and Stuff, le tesi esposte difendono l’efficienza nel presente, non tengono conto del futuro.

Poniamo ad esempio che si voglia rifornire di banane a febbraio una grossa città del nord come Vancouver, in Canada. Se non ci fossero i grossi aiuti statali a sostegno delle reti logistiche globali e le loro infrastrutture commerciali, quasi nessuno a Vancouver potrebbe comprare banane, che per i lavoratori diverrebbero un bene di lusso come il caviale o lo champagne. Una vera alternativa sarebbe lo sviluppo di tecnologie sufficientemente economiche, come la crescita in container climatizzati, e produrre banane localmente durante l’inverno. All’inizio la produzione sarebbe molto costosa, forse cinque o dieci volte tanto, e accessibile solo ai ricchi, ma con un tasso di progresso al livello di due cifre percentuali l’anno, ovvero un decimo della legge di Moore, nel giro di un decennio o due i costi sarebbero inferiori a quelli dell’agricoltura industriale con prodotti di sintesi, modifiche genetiche e sistemi a clima controllato. E il tutto verrebbe fatto non da un esercito di pianificatori centrali con enormi catene logistiche che attraversano il globo, ma da qualche decina di supermercati di Vancouver che coltiva banane in container sul tetto e condivide informazioni utili con altri produttori in altre città. Certo, qualcuno potrebbe dire che queste stesse tecnologie potrebbero essere utilizzate anche in qualche sorta di socialismo cibernetico, ma si ripresenterebbe il problema delle dimensioni di scala. Viste le dimensioni molto più grandi, sperimentare varianti e configurazioni fino a raggiungere il metodo scientificamente ottimale costerebbe molto di più a causa dei maggiori costi generali e della maggior manodopera necessaria a mettere in atto ogni più piccolo atto, e questo frenerebbe il progresso. Secondo la capitalista Silicon Valley, il sistema ottimale per lo sviluppo industriale passa da un’infrastruttura formata da una piccola rete di finanziatori che diano finanziamenti d’avvio a piccoli gruppi di non più di una dozzina di persone con un alto tasso di fallimento, salvo poi scegliere quei gruppi che hanno successo e acquisirne l’attività con grassi assegni al fine di allargare il proprio monopolio, invece di spendere un sacco di soldi per fare tutto in casa.

Se quelli come Phillips fossero per il progresso, dovrebbero sostenere un sistema ideale di produzione che dia la massima libertà di sperimentare, sbagliare, aggiustare e avere successo, diffondendo la conoscenza di ciò che funziona e non. Le organizzazioni si ridurrebbero ad una sola persona. Ma visto che gran parte di ciò che facciamo ne richiede di più, la regola dovrebbe essere: il numero più prossimo ad uno. Il sistema assumerebbe la forma grafica di una distribuzione esponenziale in cui gran parte delle organizzazioni è composta da una unità, quindi una coppia, quindi poche dozzine, e infine una coda formata da un piccolo numero di grosse organizzazioni le cui condizioni sono dettate da realtà oggettive, come nel caso delle cooperative di minatori del rame in Cile che hanno diverse migliaia di soci. Questo capovolge la tendenza attuale, che consiste nel mettere su la più grande organizzazione possibile in forma monolitica per poi cercare di farla andare con un voto popolare a due opzioni: sì o no; o, peggio ancora, alienare la classe lavoratrice delegando ad una classe minoritaria di parlamentari il compito di ampliare il numero delle opzioni fino alle centinaia. Ridimensionando il modello organizzativo e le unità produttive, i lavoratori possono andare oltre la democrazia, riunendosi in gruppi di affinità e decidendo consensualmente, cose semplicemente impossibili in un consiglio comunale o in un’assemblea di lavoratori.

Apparentemente, molti socialdemocratici e ecomodernisti stanno facendo gli stessi errori delle rivoluzioni repubblicane del passato, oggi un relitto sociale dell’epoca dei re e degli imperatori. Queste rivoluzioni hanno mantenuto al servizio della borghesia tutto quel macchinario statale pensato per servire re e nobili, unicamente sostituendo i vertici del potere con un parlamento democratico. Le rivoluzioni borghesi non sono mai monolitiche, al loro interno c’è sempre un certo numero di egalitari, e ci sono buone ragioni per credere che il liberalismo classico abbia lontane origini in quegli artigiani e contadini populisti e indipendenti inglesi che formarono un primo embrione del pensiero socialista. Prendendo le redini di uno stato pensato per la monarchia, i Digger inglesi, i contadini populisti americani, e i manovali indipendenti che possedevano solo la propria forza lavoro, tutti questi misero su movimenti sociali per conto proprio e non andarono da nessuna parte. Il Regno del Terrore dei Giacobini dovrebbe insegnarci che le istituzioni nate per servire i re non generano Libertà, Eguaglianza e Fratellanza per le masse neanche se aggiungiamo una classe di parlamentari con una ghigliottina in cima. Così come le democrazie liberali hanno portato ad un miglioramento delle condizioni di vita, lo stesso accadrebbe se aziende gigantesche come Amazon e Walmart fossero rilevate e poste sotto il controllo dei lavoratori. Se i lavoratori dovessero rivoltarsi improvvisamente e la famiglia Walton o Jeff Bezos dovessero ritrovarsi a negoziare un piano d’uscita e cedere tutto ai lavoratori ad un prezzo conveniente per non rischiare il fallimento per uno sciopero generale, la cosa farebbe uscire dalla povertà milioni di lavoratori, a cui si aggiungerebbero decine di milioni di famiglie e più considerando le esternalità positive.

Le organizzazioni comunitarie possono servirsi di ciò per creare istituzioni particolari, ad esempio dedicando un settore particolare ai “prodotti fatti in casa”, a favore delle famiglie locali che rischiano lo sfratto, da rivendere a prezzo di costo o al fine di usare il surplus per finanziare cooperative di lavoratori locali. Tutto bene, ma poi c’è un modello gestionale con milioni di lavoratori che votano in elezioni paragonabili a quelle nazionali. È nell’interesse dei lavoratori mantenere la struttura ereditata dalle grandi istituzioni piramidali per proteggersi dalla concorrenza capitalista; ma va anche detto che tutte le strutture gerarchiche in aziende come Walmart servono a dirottare le informazioni e il controllo verso l’alto affinché i capi possano prendere le decisioni. Una volta che il potere decisionale è nelle mani dei lavoratori, i quali oltretutto sono i veri produttori, le strutture gerarchiche, utili solo a dare esecutività alle decisioni dei vertici, diventano uno spreco di energie. Se i lavoratori, in un ipotetico luogo di lavoro rinnovato di un’ipotetica cooperativa Walmart, volessero allargare la propria libertà, non dovrebbero far altro che eliminare gli ormai inutili quadri ed esecutivi, solo così questa nuova ipotetica Walmart si discosterebbe da una unità produttiva monolitica di tipo sovietico gestita da un comitato eletto di pianificatori centrali, per assumere le sembianze di un insieme di cooperative di lavoratori indipendenti gestite dal basso, con risorse comuni logistiche e di pianificazione, condivisione del reddito, accordi mutui e un sistema di vasi comunicanti che permette l’interrelazione tra lavoratori, unità produttive e organizzazioni.

Tutta la questione si riduce ad una discussione non sull’aumento o meno della crescita economica, ma su come misurare crescita e benessere. Vogliamo una società gestita da un governo socialdemocratico comunitario che si occupa dei cambiamenti climatici, mentre la maggioranza delle persone lavora meno ore e ha più tempo libero e non vuole seccature su questioni come la casa? O vogliamo uno stato nazione democratico pianificato centralmente, in cui i lavoratori possono permettersi beni di consumo di massa ma devono passare gran parte della loro vita al lavoro? Entrambe le parti pensano che la soluzione passi attraverso un’enorme autorità di regolamentazione e un potere decisionale democratico, sono in disaccordo soltanto sulla posizione di tale autorità di regolamentazione: a livello nazionale o locale? Per il resto, pensano che occorra mantenere le attuali strutture piramidali, con un po’ più di controllo democratico al vertice.

Anarchy and Democracy
Fighting Fascism
Markets Not Capitalism
The Anatomy of Escape
Organization Theory